The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Robin Cowan (a), Paul A.
David (b) & Dominique Foray (c)
The Explicit Economics of Knowledge: Codifcation and Tacitness
Content |
|
Abstract
1. Introduction: What’s All this Fuss over Tacit
Knowledge About?
2. How the Tacit Dimension Found a Wonderful New
Career in Economics
2.1 The Roots in the Sociology of Scientific
Knowledge, and Cognitive Science
2.2 From Evolutionary Economics to Management Strategy
and Technology Policy 3. Codification and Tacitness Reconsidered 4. A Proposed Topography for Knowledge Activities 5. Boundaries in the Re-mapped Knowledge Space and
Their Significance 6. On the Value of This Re-mapping 6.1 On the Topography Itself 6.2 On Interactions with External Phenomena |
7. The Economic Determinants of Codification 7.1 The Endogeneity of the Tacitness - Codification
Boundary 7.2 Costs, Benefits and the Knowledge Environment 7.3 Costs and Benefits in a Stable Context 7.4 Costs and Benefits in the Context of Change 8. Conclusions and the Direction of Further Work Acknowledgements References HHC: Index added
Industrial and Corporate Change, 9 (2), 2000 , 211-253 |
page 1
This paper attempts a greater precision and clarity of
understanding concerning the nature and economic significance of knowledge and
its variegated forms by presenting ‘the skeptical economist’s guide to “tacit
knowledge’’. It critically reconsiders
the ways in which the concepts of tacitness and codification have come to be
employed by economists and develops a more coherent re-conceptualization of
these aspects of knowledge production and distribution activities. It seeks also to show that a proposed alternative
framework for the study of knowledge codification activities offers a more
useful guide for further research directed to informing public policies for
science, technological innovation and long-run economic growth.
1. Introduction: What’s All this Fuss over Tacit Knowledge
About?
With increasing frequency these days references appear in the
economics literature to ‘tacit knowledge’. More often than not the meaning of this term
itself is something that remains literally tacit - which is to say, those who
employ it are silent as to its definition. Something is suggested nevertheless by the
common practice of juxtaposing mention of tacit knowledge and references to
‘codified knowledge’. What is all this
about? Why has this distinction been
made and what significance does it have for economists?
Polanyi (1958, 1967) introduced the term into modern
circulation, by pointing to the existence of ‘the tacit dimension of
knowledge’, a form or component of human knowledge distinct from, but
complementary to, the knowledge explicit in conscious cognitive
processes. Polanyi illustrated this
(a) University of Maastricht, MERIT,
Maastricht, The Netherlands, (b) Stanford University and All Souls College,
Oxford, UK and (c) University of Paris -
Dauphine & IMRI (CNRS), France.
211
conceptualization
by reference to a fact of common perception: we all are often aware of certain
objects without being focused on them.
This, he maintained, did not make them the less important, as they form
the context that renders focused perception possible, understandable and
fruitful. Reference to the findings of
Gestalt psychology in regard to other perceptual phenomena formed another
important aspect of Polanyi’s conceptualization of tacit knowledge: people
appear to be perceptually (and/or intellectually) aware of some objects and
things about the world only as entities - as illustrated by the
identification of a particular human face or voice. [1] Knowledge of this kind
consists of holistic understandings, and thus is not completely amenable
to purely reductionist analyses.
Subsequently, the term ‘tacit knowledge’ has come to be more
widely applied to forms of personal knowledge that remain ‘UN-codified’ and do
not belong in the category of ‘information’, which itself is thought of as an
ideal-type good having peculiar economic features that differentiate it from
other, conventional economic commodities. [2]
One may observe the growing practice
among economists of juxtaposing ‘tacit’ and ‘codified’ knowledge, which
casually applies the former term as a label for the entire (residual) category
of knowledge that cannot be seen to be conveyed by means of codified, symbolic
representations, i.e. transmitted as ‘information’. In this process of inflating the usage of the
term, the emphasis upon context and contextual understanding that was present
in psychological references to the ‘tacit dimension’ of human knowledge has
been largely discarded. Tacit knowledge
thus has come to signify an absolute type, namely: ‘not codified knowledge’. Among economists it is used more and more in
this way, without explicit definition, and therefore without further
explication of the conditions that might underlie ‘tacitness’ or the resort to
codification of knowledge.
But, more than having become merely another overly vague bit
of fashionable economic jargon, ‘tacit knowledge’ now is an increasingly
‘loaded’ buzzword, freighted with both methodological implications for
micro-economic theory in general, and policy significance for the economics of
science and technology, innovation, and economic growth. Indeed, references to ‘tacitness’ have become
a platform used by some economists to launch fresh attacks upon national
policies of public subsidization for R&D activities, and
1. Polyani (1967, pp. 4-6):
‘I shall reconsider human knowledge by starting from the fact that we can know
more than we can tell... Gestalt psychology has demonstrated that we may know a
physiognomy by intergrating our awareness of its particulars without being able
to identify these particulars ...’
2. Most significant, from
the economist’s viewpoint, is the absence of super-additivity and the
negligible marginal costs of transmitting information. These properties and their implications are
discussed more fully in the following text, but the canonical references are
Nelson (1959) and Arrow (1962).
212
equally
by other economists to construct novel rationales for governmental funding of
science and engineering research and training programs.
The first-order result of all this would seem to have been
the creation of a considerable amount of semantic and taxonomic confusion. In and of itself, this might be both expected
and tolerable as a transient phase in any novel conceptual development. Unfortunately, one cannot afford to be so
sanguine, because those very same confusions are being exploited to advance
economic policy conclusions that claim to be grounded upon propositions that
are well established (if only recently recognized in economics) about the
existence of different kinds of knowledge pertinent to scientific,
technological and organizational innovation. In our view, however, such claims in many
instances are neither analytically nor empirically warranted.
This essay responds to a felt need for greater precision and
clarity of understanding concerning the nature and economic significance of
knowledge and its variegated forms, by presenting what might be described as ‘the
skeptical economist’s guide to “tacit knowledge”. Our skepticism, however, does not extend to
questioning the seriousness of the array of issues that economists and others
have been discussing under the general rubric of tacit knowledge, which truly are
important and deserving of careful consideration. Furthermore, we acknowledge that some of the
now-classic contributions to the economics of scientific and technological
innovation, when regarded from an epistemological perspective, appear
unwarrantedly simplistic in their handling of some subtle questions concerning
‘knowledge’ and ‘information’, and the relationship between the two.
Our immediate purposes in this paper are to critically
reconsider the ways in which the concepts of tacitness and codification have
come to be employed by economists, and to develop a more coherent
re-conceptualization of these aspects of knowledge production and distribution
activities. We seek to show, further,
that a proposed alternative framework for the study of knowledge codification
activities - perhaps because it rests upon explicit microeconomic foundations -
offers a more useful guide for further research directed to informing public
policies for science, technological innovation and long-run economic growth.
The following section elaborates on our contention that the
terminology and meaning of ‘tacitness’ in the economics literature, having
drifted far from its original epistemological and psychological moorings, has
become unproductively amorphous; indeed, that it now obscures more than it
clarifies. Among the matters that
thereby have been hidden are some serious analytical and empirical flaws in the
newly emerging critique of the old economics of R&D. By the same token, we also can identify
equally serious
213
flaws
in the novel rationale that has recently been developed for continuing public
support of R&D activities, based upon the alleged inherent tacitness of
technological knowledge.
An explicit re-examination of some fundamental conceptual
underpinnings in this area is therefore in order. Although this requires that we re-open
questions which readers coming to the topic from economics may feel are settled
well enough for their purposes, a persuasive case can be made for doing so; and
setting it forth in section 3, we seek to show that a new taxonomic framework
would prove helpful in clearing away a number of the conceptual confusions that
presently are impeding the progress of research in this area. Such a framework is proposed in section 4, providing
a topography of ‘knowledge transaction activities’, the salient features of
which are discussed in section 5. A
number of advantages afforded by the novel conceptual structure (those that are
discernible a priori) are indicated in section 6. But, as the proof of any pudding of this kind
is to be found only in the eating, we proceed to put it to practical use in
section 7, where we consider the economic costs and benefits of codification
activities in different knowledge environments, thereby exposing the main
endogenous determinants of the dynamic path of the boundary between what is and
is not codified in the existing state of knowledge. Section 8 concludes with some brief comments
indicating the implied directions for theoretical and empirical work needed to
further explore this promising vein in the economics of knowledge.
2.
How the Tacit Dimension Found a Wonderful New Career in Economics
To motivate this undertaking we begin with a closer look at
the intellectual background of the increasing frequency with which the notion
of tacit knowledge currently is entering economic policy discussions. It is fair to say that economists have not had
much preparation to deal with the recent debates that are emerging in their
midst over the nature of knowledge and the significance of its tacit dimension.
This is understandable, because the
popular social science career of this concept began elsewhere... long ago, and
in a far distant discipline.
Must economists now prepare themselves to become ever more
deeply involved in discussions of the nature of knowledge, and begin to care
about the various categories into which other disciplines claim knowledge
should be sorted? Is this not something
better left for epistemologists and others of similar philosophical
inclination? Although one might be
tempted to answer the latter in the affirmative, it is now too late to ignore
the very meaning of
214
something
that a large and growing number economists and other social scientists seem
bent upon discussing. It seems helpful,
therefore, to approach the subject with some background awareness of the
historical path by which ‘tacitness’ made its way from the philosophical
writings of Polanyi (1958, 1967) into widespread currency in the economic
journals.
2.1 The Roots in the Sociology
of Scientific Knowledge, and Cognitive Science
The pioneering role was taken by those who called themselves
‘sociologists of scientific knowledge’ (SSK), thereby distinguishing their
purpose and approach from that of the then mainstream Mertonian school in the
sociology of science. Proponents of the
SSK program were more interested in the role of social forces (under which both
economic and political interests were subsumed) in shaping the cognitive
aspects of scientific work. The traditional
approach in the sociology of knowledge had, by contrast, tended to focus
attention upon the role of macro-institutional settings, reward structures and
the like, in mobilizing resources for the pursuit of scientific knowledge and
organizing the conduct of research. By
and large, it had thereby eschewed direct engagement with the epistemological
issues that occupied philosophers of science, and so it appeared to accept if
not endorse the latter’s formal accounts of ‘the scientific method’ as the ‘disinterested
confrontation of logically derived propositions (theory) with empirical
evidence (fact)’.
That picture, however, did not appear to square with the one
found by some SSK-inspired students of contemporary scientific practice. They observed that some kinds of knowledge
deployed in scientific inquiry - most notably that relating to the assembly and
operation of experimental apparatus and instrumentation, and the interpretation
of the data which these generated - were not communicated as hypotheses or
codified propositions, or by any means resembling the formalized modes of
discourse with which philosophy of science traditionally had been preoccupied. Rather, working scientists appeared to be more
occupied with ‘craft knowledge’, and much of what seemed crucial to their
research efforts was not being transmitted among them in the form of any
explicit, fully codified statements.
Collins’s (1974) notably influential study in this vein
examined the early construction of the TEA laser in a number of laboratories,
and reported that none of the research teams which succeeded in building a
working laser had done so without the participation of someone from another
laboratory where a device of this type already had been put into operation. For Collins, ‘[t]he major point is that the
transmission of skills is not done through the medium
215
of
written words’. Subsequent contributors
to the sociology of scientific and technological knowledge have read this and
other, kindred observations as showing that ‘the diffusion of knowledge could
not be reduced to the mere transmission of information’ (Callon, 1995).
A contrast thus was posed between the ‘algorithmic model’ of
knowledge production, which is concerned exclusively with the generation of
consistent propositions and the transmission of explicit declarative
statements, on the one hand, and the so-called ‘enculturation model’ of
scientific activities on the other. This
distinction was invoked primarily by philosophers and sociologists who sought
to challenge the idea that science, and specifically the modern scientific
method, was a source of ‘privileged’ statements. The putative privilege in question derived
from the implication that scientific statements could be stripped from the
social contexts in which they had been formed and in which they had acquired
meaning, and consequently could be promulgated as part of an authoritatively
universal, ‘codified’ body of knowledge about the physical world. Challengers of that view leaned heavily on the
seeming importance of tacit knowledge in the actual conduct of scientific
activities.
At this juncture in the narrative a few remarks should be
entered about the distinction observed here between ‘information’ and
‘knowledge’, terms that we shall continue to avoid using interchangeably. We find it useful to operationally define an
item of information as a message containing structured data, the receipt of
which causes some action by the recipient agent - without implying that the
nature of that action is determined solely and uniquely by the message itself. Instead, it is the cognitive context afforded
by the receiver that imparts meaning(s) to the information-message, and from
the meaning(s) follow the specific nature of the induced action(s). The term ‘knowledge’ is simply the label
affixed to the state of the agent’s entire cognitive context. [3]
The algorithmic model to which reference has been made
above, strictly interpreted, implies the absence of any meaningful distinction
between information and knowledge. Under
this approach all the cognitive and behavioral capabilities of whatever human
or non-human agent is being described must have been reduced to ‘code’, that
is, to structured data and the necessary instructions for its processing. Only in that way could a
3. From the foregoing it
should be evident that we do not find it helpful to conflate ‘what humans learn
in order to assimilate, digest and use information’ with the concept of ‘tacit
knowledge’, and thereby to arrive at the glib but empty formalization:
‘information = codified knowledge’ and ‘knowledge’ = ‘tacit knowledge +
‘information’. The definitions offered
in the text make explicit the distinctive usage of the terms data,
information and knowledge in Dasgupta and David (1994), David and
Foray (1995) and Cowan and Foray (1997). As we point out below, when knowledge is
defined in this way, i.e. as an attribute of individual agents, some delicate
conceptual issues arise when one tries to be precise in extending the notion by
speaking of ‘social knowledge’ as the attribute of some collectivity of agents.
216
purely
algorithmic actor generate further data and/or instructions for future actions
- whether those were physical actions, or simply the processing, classification,
storage, retrieval and transmission of information. It is possible, therefore, to say that what an
(algorithmic) economic agent ‘knows’ is nothing more nor less than
‘information’.
To stop there, of course, would be to ignore, inter alia,
the manifest differences between intelligent human agents and computers. Humans create new categories for the
classification of information, and learn to assign meanings to (sensory) data
inputs without the assistance of programmed instructions of which they are
consciously aware. Not surprisingly,
then, the term ‘knowledge’ is applied in ordinary language when referring to
human capacities that appear to be accessed without the intermediation of any
formal code. In other words, humans (and
other living creatures) ‘know things’ that they have not acquired as
‘information’ and which, not having been reduced to symbolic representations
(code), are held in forms that are not readily available for communication to
others - at least not explicitly as ‘information-bearing’ messages. At the same time, however, it is no less
important to notice that the capacities of humans to ‘decode’, interpret,
assimilate and find novel applications for particular items of information
entail the use of still other items of information. These latter equally are part (and may well
form the critical part) of the ‘cognitive context’ within which the recipient
of a given message assigns to it ‘meaning(s)’. Moreover, there is nothing in this observation
that would imply a lack of awareness on the part of the individual concerned
about the pertinent ‘information context’, or any inability to transmit it to
others.
2.2 From
Evolutionary Economics to Management Strategy and Technology Policy
For some considerable time, economists took little if any
interest in the question of separating the notion of knowledge from their idea
of information, and scarcely noticed the sequel distinction that other
disciplines had drawn between the algorithmic and enculturation models of
learning and associated behaviors. But
things have moved on from that stage, and in several directions. A parallel and related course of development
also has been evident in the management studies literature, from the early
formulations such as that provided by Winter (1987), to the recent wave of
books on ‘knowledge management’, as exemplified by Leonard-Barton (1995),
Nonaka and Keuchi (1995) and Davenport and Prusak (1998).
Thus, the importance of tacit knowledge as a strategy asset
is ack-
217
nowledged
today by students of rational management practices on the one hand, [4] and at the same time is cited as being
crucial by critics of the ‘algorithmic’ approach of modern economic analysis of
all aspects of human behavior. In its
latter manifestations, the concept of the inextricable tacitness of human
knowledge forms the basis of arguments brought not only against the residue of
behaviorist psychology which remains embedded in the neo-classical formulation
of microeconomic analysis, but against virtually every construction of rational
decision processes as the foundation for modeling and explaining the actions of
individual human agents.
Whether the emergence of these disparate intellectual
developments can be said to constitute scientific ‘advance’, however, remains
another matter. Quite clearly, the
challenge being brought against algorithmic representations of knowledge
generation and acquisition goes much deeper than arguments for ‘bounded’
rationality following the work of Newell and Simon (1972); and it has been
argued in far more sweepingly general terms by critics of the whole artificial
intelligence (AI) program such as Hofstader (1979) and, more recently, Penrose
(1989, 1997). In those quarters, tacit
knowledge has come to stand for the aspects of human intelligence that cannot
be mimicked by any (computer) algorithm.
It may be remarked that were the latter rather nihilistic
arguments against the quest for AI to be read as statements conditional on the
presently available and foreseeable states of technology, rather than as
absolute assertions of impossibility, this would leave room for the boundary
between tacit knowledge and knowledge of other kinds to be other than
inextricably fixed. Instead, what was
tacit, and correspondingly what was not, would be subject to some future
readjustments by improvements in the performance of computer hardware and
software - because increasing processing speeds, reduced access times, expanded
storage and more efficient algorithm designs permitted the faithful
reproduction of an increasing range of human capabilities. [5] The
resolution of debates over the mutability of this boundary would carry many
implications for economics, but, as will be seen, the way in which the idea of
tacitness has come to be used opens the possibility that still other,
4. The definition of
knowledge given in the text (above) is broadly consonant with, albeit rather
more spare than the way the term is being used in this literature, as may be
seen by the following ‘working definition’ offered by Davenport and Prusak
(1998, p. 5): ‘Knowledge is a fluid mix of framed experience, values,
contextual information, and expert insight that provides a framework for
evaluating and incorporating new experience and information. It originates and is applied in the minds of
knowers.’
5. Balconi (1998)
explores the effects of changes in the modern technology of steel product
manufacturing upon the boundary between the codified and the tacit elements of
the knowledge deemed relevant for production operations and worker training. The relevance here is simply that this
boundary is mutable under the influence of technological changes other than
those in the domain information technology narrowly construed.
218
non-technological
conditions also are influential in determining what knowledge is codified and
what is not.
One may locate the seedbed of the modern flowering of
economic discussions of tacit knowledge in the early attention that was
directed to Polanyi’s writings by Nelson and Winter’s (1982) widely noticed
critique of neoclassical analysis and initiation of a program of research in
evolutionary economics. [6] Their discussion of the parallels between
individual human skills and organizational capacities (Nelson and Winter, 1982,
ch. 4) gave particular prominence to the concept of tacit knowledge, and
expanded upon its significance for economists concerned with the internal
workings of the firm. [7] Those passages remain as perceptive and
stimulating, and as fresh and balanced today as when they first appeared,
almost two decades ago, and it is a pity that a larger proportion of the
economists who now talk about tacit knowledge and its implications do not
appear to have acquainted themselves with this ‘local source’. [8]
What Nelson and Winter (1982) say about the nature and
significance of tacitness in knowledge conveys not just one sharply defined
concept, but a nexus of meanings, each carrying somewhat distinctive
implications. Their first reference to
the term (1982, p. 73), for example, offers only a parenthetical clarification:
‘The knowledge that underlies skillful performance is in large measure tacit
knowledge, in the sense that the performer is not fully aware of the
details of the performance and finds it difficult or impossible to articulate a
full account of those details’ (emphasis added).
Yet, as is made clear shortly following this statement,
Nelson and Winter accept Polanyi’s (1967) account of such situations as being
contextual, rather than absolute: ‘the aim of a skillful performance’ may ‘be
achieved by the observance of a set of rules which are not known as such to the
person following them’. Reference then
is made to Polanyi’s earlier philosophical work,
6. For the subsequent
elaboration of a more thorough-going rejection of microeconomic optimization,
in the evolutionary models of Schumpeterian competition, see e.g. Dosi (1988),
Dosi et al. (1988) and Dosi and Egidi (1991). Evolutionary modeling in economics now spans a
wide range of practice in regard to how ‘bounded’ the bounded rationality of
agents is assumed to be. Anderson (1994)
discusses this and other issues in the algorithmic representation of the
general class of Nelson-Winter type models.
7. Skinner(1994, p. 11)
points out that the use made of Polanyi’s concept by Nelson and Winter(1982)
emphasized what cognitive scientists refer to as the granularity of the
efficient mode of mental storage for learned skills and procedures
(‘routines’), rather than for the storage of declarative statements. Skinner suggests that, in developing the
former theme, Nelson and Winter were influenced strongly by the previous work
in cognitive science and AI, e.g. by Newell and Simon’s (1972) formulation of a
production system model of information processing for ‘learning,’ and the idea
of learned routines being holistically stored for recall (as ‘scripts’) - a
concept due to Shank (1988), who was a leading figure in cognitive science and
AI fields on the faculty of Yale University during the 1970s and 1980s (as were
Nelson and Winter).
8. Had things been
otherwise, it seems only reasonable to suppose that we would have been spared
at least the more serious confusions and unwarranted generalizations that have
become commonplace in the literature.
219
Persona/Knowledge
(1958, p. 49), where an example is presented of a swimmer keeping himself
buoyant by regulating respiration, yet remaining unconscious of doing so. In this case the operant rule (‘never empty
your lungs fully’) plainly is one that is articulable, could be known to
another person, and so might be transmitted verbally by a swimming instructor -
were the latter aware of the principle of buoyancy. In other words, Nelson and Winter (1982, p.
77) do not insist, any more than did Polanyi, that tacitness implied
‘inarticulability’, even though the inarticulability of some (personal)
knowledge logically implied that the latter would remain tacit.
On the question of ‘awareness’, Nelson and Winter (1982, p.
78) recognize that the skillful performer may have ‘subsidiary awareness’ of
the rules that are being followed, while being ‘focally aware’ of some other - most
probably novel - facet of the task in which she is engaged. This reinforces an appreciation of the
contextual boundaries within which knowledge will be tacit, rather than
explicitly recognized and articulated. Yet,
if one can describe behavior in terms of ‘rule conformity’, then it is clear
that the underlying knowledge is codifiable - and indeed may have
previously been codified.
Most significant still, for what we shall say about the more
recent strain of the literature on tacitness, is Nelson and Winter’s (1982, p.
78) acknowledgement that this quality is not inherent in the knowledge. They write: ‘The same knowledge,
apparently, is more tacit for some people than for others. Incentives, too, clearly matter: when
circumstances place a great premium on effective articulation, remarkable
things can sometimes be accomplished’. In
amplification of this point, they offer the example of an expert pilot giving
successful verbal instruction via radio to a complete novice as to how to land
an airplane - even though the ‘expert’ had never had occasion previously to
make explicit what was entailed in his successful performance of a landing. Indeed, their section on ‘Skills and Tacit
Knowledge’ concludes by emphasizing that
… costs matter. Whether a particular bit of knowledge is in principle
articulable or necessarily tacit is not the relevant question in most
behavioral situations. Rather, the
question is whether the costs... are sufficiently high so that the knowledge in
fact remains tacit (p. 80).
This important set of observations deserved much more
attention and elaboration than it has been accord by the subsequent literature,
and we have sought (in section 7, below) to begin the work of rectifying this
oversight.
It is unfortunate that these more complicated aspects of the
concept had been all but forgotten, were they ever widely grasped when
‘tacitness’ made
220
its
debut on the economic policy stage. Among
the most notable of the uses to which the idea of tacit knowledge is being put
on the more mundane levels at which most economists operate, and certainly the
uses that have the greatest impact in economic policy circles, has been the qualification
- and in some instances the outright rejection - of the practical policy
conclusions drawn from the classic information-theoretic analysis of the
economics of R&D activities.
Following the seminal work of Arrow (1955, 1962) and Nelson
(1959), an entire generation of economists treated scientific and technological
knowledge as ‘information’. To that
degree, they reasoned, the knowledge generated by research activities possessed
certain generic properties of public goods. Much of the case for government subsidization
of science and engineering research, and for innovative activity more
generally, came to be grounded on the proposition that qua information,
such knowledge could not be optimally produced or distributed through the
workings of competitive markets.
Nowadays we are more and more frequently instructed
otherwise. In the newer understanding of
science and technology as being pursuits inextricably involved with tacit
knowledge, it is claimed that the old public policy rationales are exploded;
the essential understandings are said to be the portion of knowledge that
remains uncodified, and so deprived of the public goods properties that would
result in informational spillovers and market failure. Thus, as this argument concludes, the traditional
economic case for subsidizing science and research in general collapses, as
there is little or no basis for a presumption of market failure. Similar arguments are advanced in the context
of policy debates over the role of intellectual property rights in providing
incentive for innovation: the claim is that the information presented (in
codified form) in a patent is insufficient to allow others to actually make use
of the patented invention, and it is the correlative ‘tacit knowledge’ that
resides with the innovator that provides the real source of private,
rent-appropriating (monopoly) power. [9]
But, at the same time, tacit knowledge is invoked by
defenders of government subsidization of science as part of a strategic
innovation policy. A standard argument
against public subsidy to science is that foreigners engaging in applied,
commercially oriented R&D would free-ride (since information is a public
good and travels freely) by exploiting the basic knowledge discoveries that our
researchers vie to codify for disclosure in the
9. For further discussion
see Arundel and Kabla (1999). The force
of such claims would seem restricted largely to the case of process patents
rather than product patents. Arundel
(1996, 1997) reports that the CIS survey of EU firms found that 18-20% of
respondent companies in the size range above 199 employees regarded process
patents as a ‘very important or crucial’ source of competitive advantage,
whereas in the case of product patents the corresponding figure was in the 30-40%
range.
221
scientific
journals and similar archival publications. To this, the proponents of a strategic role
for tacit knowledge reply, nations and regions, like individual enterprises
undertaking R&D investments, can count on the benefits of ‘sticky data’ - to
use von Hippel’s (1993) arresting term. Knowledge
does not travel freely, a condition that rests largely on the importance of
tacit knowledge residing only in the heads of the scientists and engineers
engaged in its production. Codified
knowledge may have low marginal costs of transmission and is thus slippery and
hard to contain, but that is largely irrelevant if what one needs is its
‘sticky’, tacit counterpart. [10]
The inherent ‘stickiness’ of certain kinds of knowledge,
consequently, enables business (or other) entities to protect their ability to
appropriate the benefits derivable from their research investments fully, by
controlling access to the repositories of uncodified knowledge. For this, minimal recourse is required to the
protection of intellectual property in the form of patents and copyrights; a
mixture of trade secrecy law and labor law (master-servant relations) governing
the behavior of current and former employees may be enough. Thus, curious though it may seem, the tacit
dimension of scientific and technological knowledge has found a new career for
itself in science and technology policy debates: it is beginning to supplant
its now dubious companion, ‘codified knowledge’, as the core of a new rationale
for government research funding intended to build national and regional
‘competitiveness’ through innovation.
According to this application of the argument, even though
the essential tacit knowledge concerning how to exploit what has been invented
might be less than perfectly ‘sticky’, what this implies is that its economic
benefits are only available to be captured locally. In other, more formal, terms, it is asserted
that the marginal costs of knowledge transmission rise very rapidly with
‘distance’ from the context in which such knowledge was generated. Research by-products in the form of
technological knowledge - being concerned with how best to get instrumentation
involving chemical, mechanical, electrical and optical processes to work - are
seen as inherently more strongly tacit in nature. That is held to be particularly beneficial for
would-be commercial developers who are able to situate closer to the locus of
such discoveries (see e.g. Pavitt, 1987; Nelson, 1992; Patel and Pavitt, 1995).
A broad policy implication following from this is that for
an economy
10. In subsequent work,
von Hippel (1994) generalizes the idea of stickiness so that it covers all
situations in which there is an appreciable cost of transferring information,
relevant for innovative activities. In
principle, at least, von Hippel’s use of the notion of ‘stickiness’ makes no
distinction between transfer costs consisting of pure rents imposed by the
owners of intellectual property rights, on the one hand, and real social
resource costs such as those entailed in physically transporting an expert for
the purpose of demonstrating the proper use of a novel product or process in a
distant location.
222
to
have a strong, innovative manufacturing sector, it is necessary also to have
correspondingly strong applied and basic research activities situated in close
proximity to the production operations themselves. The new innovation strategy perspective that
has now formed around the concept of tacitness in the business management
literature is illustrated by the following passage (Kay, 1999, p. 13):
Since ‘knowledge that’ - the characteristic
discoveries of natural science - is easily transmitted, one solution [to the
problem of creating ‘knowledge-based competitive advantages’] is to continually
innovate and stay one step ahead. And
that kind of innovative capacity depends on knowledge that isn’t ‘knowledge
that’, but ‘knowledge how’ - i.e. tacit knowledge. Tacit knowledge can take many forms, but it
cannot be written down. It is unique to
an organization - and therefore cannot be copied... The benefits of such tacit
knowledge arise only through a culture of trust and knowledge-sharing within an
organization .
Such considerations apply not only to scientific and
engineering know-how, but also, and perhaps more strongly, to marketing, and
internal management knowledge pertaining to business organizations, all of
which have strongly contextual elements that make them ‘natural’ contributors
to what von Hippel (1994) refers to as ‘sticky information’.
Thus, a notion that took its origins in the psychology of
visual perception and human motor skills has been wonderfully transmuted, first
from an efficient mode of mental storage of knowledge into a putative
epistemological category (having to do with the nature of the knowledge
itself), from there into a phenomenon of inarticulable inter-organizational
relationships and finally to one of the keys to corporate, and perhaps also
national, competitive advantage!
A corollary of arguments in the latter vein is that the case
for granting public subsidies and tax concessions to private companies that
invest in R&D would seem to be much weakened, were it not for the
difficulties caused these firms by the circulation of their research personnel.
[11]
Scientific and engineering staff are able to carry critical tacit
knowledge off to potential rival firms
11. We can observe that
the more things change the more they stay the same. We have moved from the view that the problem
to be solved arises from the fact that a firm’s knowledge is easily
appropriated by other firms. Acknowledging
the importance of tacit knowledge, and thus that the initial problem may not be
so severe, we face a ‘new problem’ stemming from the fact that a firms knowledge
workers are easily appropriated by other firms. In both cases the general issue remains, however
- fluidity of knowledge or information (whether transmitted through codified
knowledge or labor mobility) is good for the economy but may be bad for the
individual firm that bears the costs of enlightening its competitors.
223
that
offer them better terms of employment, including equity ownership in ‘start
ups’ of their own. In the logic of this
approach, recognition of the criticality of tacit knowledge argues for further
strengthening of trade secrecy protections, to block those ‘leakages’ and
altogether eliminate the market failure rationale for governmental support of
the performance of R&D by the private sector. [12]
That leaves the way open for those who
wish to mount an essentially ‘techno-mercantilist’ argument for R&D
subsidies, grounded on the idea that the country can benefit from job-creation,
etc., if its firms win the race to be first to launch new products in
international markets. It is, in effect,
a new strategic trade policy argument, grounded on the claim that tacit
knowledge permits national appropriation of the direct and indirect benefits of
monopolizing international product niches by being ‘first to invest’.
We see a need to put the economics of tacit and codified
knowledge on analytically firmer and terminologically more precise foundations
than those upon which most of the recent literature presently rests. The foregoing account of the wonderful career
that has thrust ‘the tacit dimension’ into the science and technology policy
limelight serves, at least, to identify a number of issues that are of
sufficient importance to warrant much more careful consideration. The notion that the economic case for public
support of science and engineering should now be based upon the inherently
tacit and ‘craft’ nature of research activities certainly is rather
paradoxical. Taken at face value, it
would suggest that intellectual property protection is unjustified, since, in
the ‘natural’ state of things, there are no ‘externalities’ of new knowledge. By implication, the patent system’s exchange
of monopoly of use for ‘disclosure’ allows the patentee to retain the tacit
knowledge without which the information contained in the patent really is
useless.
But, before rushing to discard everything we know about the
economics of R&D, scientific skepticism instructs us to pause and ask
whether the epistemological foundations of these new propositions really are
all that solid. We should therefore
question whether the economic functioning and attributes of tacit and codified
knowledge are well understood by those who would invoke those matters in the
context of current innovation policy debates.