The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Robin Cowan (a), Paul A.
David (b) & Dominique Foray (c)
The Explicit Economics of Knowledge: Codifcation and Tacitness
Content |
|
Abstract
1. Introduction: What’s All this Fuss over Tacit
Knowledge About?
2. How the Tacit Dimension Found a Wonderful New
Career in Economics
2.1 The Roots in the Sociology of Scientific
Knowledge, and Cognitive Science
2.2 From Evolutionary Economics to Management Strategy
and Technology Policy 3. Codification and Tacitness Reconsidered 4. A Proposed Topography for Knowledge Activities 5. Boundaries in the Re-mapped Knowledge Space and
Their Significance 6. On the Value of This Re-mapping 6.1 On the Topography Itself 6.2 On Interactions with External Phenomena |
7. The Economic Determinants of Codification 7.1 The Endogeneity of the Tacitness - Codification
Boundary 7.2 Costs, Benefits and the Knowledge Environment 7.3 Costs and Benefits in a Stable Context 7.4 Costs and Benefits in the Context of Change 8. Conclusions and the Direction of Further Work Acknowledgements References HHC: Index added
Industrial and Corporate Change, 9 (2), 2000 , 211-253 |
page 2
3.
Codification and Tacitness Reconsidered
It will be easiest for us to start not with concept of tacit
knowledge but at the opposite and seemingly less problematic end of the field,
so to speak, by
12. See, for example,
Kealey (1996) on industrial secrecy as the suitable ‘remedy’ for the problem of
informational spillovers from research, and the critique of that position in
David (1997).
224
asking
what is to be understood by the term ‘codified knowledge’. Its obvious reference is to codes, or
to standards - whether of notation or of rules, either of which may be promulgated
by authority or may acquire ‘authority’ through frequency of usage and common
consent, i.e. by defacto acceptance.
Knowledge that is recorded in some codebook serves inter
alia as a storage depository, as a reference point and possibly as an
authority. But information written in a
code can only perform those functions when people are able to interpret the
code; and, in the case of the latter two functions, to give it more or less
mutually consistent interpretations. Successfully reading the code in this last
sense may involve prior acquisition of considerable specialized knowledge
(quite possibly including knowledge not written down anywhere). As a rule, there is no reason to presuppose
that all people in the world possess the knowledge needed to interpret the
codes properly. This means that what is
codified for one person or group may be tacit for another and an utterly
impenetrable mystery for a third. Thus
context - temporal, spatial, cultural and social - becomes an important
consideration in any discussion of codified knowledge.
In what follows, we make extensive use of the notion of a
codebook. We use ‘codebook’ both to
refer to what might be considered a dictionary that agents use to understand
written documents and to apply it also to cover the documents themselves. This implies several things regarding
codification and codebooks. First,
codifying a piece of knowledge adds content to the code-book. Second, codifying a piece of knowledge draws
upon the pre-existing contents of the codebook. This creates a self-referential situation,
which can be particularly severe when the knowledge activity takes place in a
new sphere or discipline. Initially,
there is no codebook, either in the sense of a book of documents or in the
sense of a dictionary. Thus initial
codification activity involves creating the specialized dictionary. Models must be developed, as must the
vocabulary with which to express those models. When models and a language have been
developed, documents can be written. Clearly,
early in the life of a discipline or technology, standardization of the
language (and of the models) will be an important part of the collective
activity of codification. When this ‘dictionary’
aspect of the codebook becomes large enough to stabilize the ‘language’, the
‘document’ aspect can grow rapidly [for a further discussion of this issue see
Cowan and Foray (1997)]. But new
documents will inevitably introduce new concepts, notation and terminology, so
that ‘stabilization’ must not be interpreted to imply a complete cessation of
dictionary-building.
The meaning of ‘codification’ intersects with the recent
literature on economic growth. Much of
modern endogenous growth theory rests on
225
the
notion that there exists a ‘world stock of knowledge’ and, perhaps, also a
‘national knowledge-base’ that has stock-like characteristics. This is true particularly of those models in
which R&D is seen as both drawing upon and adding to ‘a knowledge stock’
which enters as an input into production processes for other goods. How ought we to characterize this, or indeed
any related conceptualization of a world stock of knowledge? Implicit in this literature is that this
stock is codified, since part or all of it is assumed to be freely accessible
by all economic agents in the system under analysis. Unpacking this idea only partially suffices to
reveal some serious logical difficulties with any attempt to objectify ‘a
social stock of knowledge’, let alone with the way that the new growth theory
has sought to employ the concept of an aggregate knowledge stock. [13]
The ‘new growth theory’ literature falls squarely within the
tradition emphasizing the public-goods nature of knowledge. So, one may surmise that the world stock of
knowledge surely has to be the union of private stocks of codified knowledge:
anything codified for someone is thereby part of the world knowledge stock. Such reasoning, however, may involve a fallacy
of composition or of aggregation. One
might reasonably have thought that the phrase ‘world knowledge stock’ refers to
the stock available to the entire world. But if the contextual aspect of knowledge and
codification (on which, see supra) is to be taken seriously, the world
stock of codified knowledge might better be defined as the intersection of
individuals’ sets of codified knowledge - that being the portion that is
‘shared’ in the sense of being both known and commonly accessible. It then follows that the world stock of
knowledge, being the intersection of private stocks, whether codified or tacit,
is going to be very small. [14]
The foregoing suggests that there is a problem in principle
with those models in the ‘new growth theory’ which have been constructed around
(the formalized representation of) a universal stock of technological knowledge
to which all agents might contribute and from which all agents can draw
costlessly. That, however, is hardly the
end of the difficulties arising from the
13. See Machlup (1980,
pp. 167-169) for a discussion of ‘the phenomenological theory of knowledge’
developed by Schutz and Luckmann (1973, chs 3-4). The latter arrive at a concept described by
Machlup as: ‘the fully objectivated [sic) knowledge of society, a social
stock of knowledge which in some sense is the result of a socialization of
knowledge [through individual interactions involving private stocks of
subjective but inter-subjectively valid knowledge) and contains at the same
time more and less than the sum of the private stocks of subjective
knowledge... This most ingenious phenomenological theory of the stock of
knowledge in society is not equipped to deal with... the problem of assessing
the size of the stock and its growth.’
14. It is clear that the
availability of two operators - union and intersection - when combined with two
types of knowledge - tacit and codified - leads to a situation in which ‘the
world stock of knowledge’ is going to take some further defining.
226
primacy
accorded to the accumulation of ‘a knowledge stock’ in the recent literature on
endogenous economic growth. The
peculiarities of knowledge as an economic commodity, namely, the heterogeneous
nature of ideas and their infinite expansibility, have been cast in the
paradigm ‘new economic growth’ models as the fundamental non-convexity,
responsible for increasing returns to investment in this intangible form of
capital. Heterogeneity implies the need
for a metric in which the constituent parts can be rendered commensurable, but
given the especially problematic nature of competitive market valuations of
knowledge, the economic aggregation problem is particularly vexatious in this
case.
Furthermore, the extent to which the infinite expansibility
of knowledge actually is exploited therefore becomes a critical matter in
defining the relevant stock - even though in most formulations of new growth
theory this matter has been glossed over. Critics of these models’ relevance have quite
properly pointed out that much technologically relevant knowledge is not
codified, and therefore has substantial marginal costs of reproduction and reapplication;
they maintain that inasmuch as this so-called ‘tacit knowledge’ possesses the
properties of normal commodities, its role in the process of growth approaches
that of conventional tangible capital. [15]
If it is strictly complementary with the
codified part of the knowledge stock, then the structure of the models implies
that either R&D activity or some concomitant process must cause the two
parts of the aggregate stock to grow pari passu. Alternatively, the growth of the effective
size of the codified knowledge stock would be constrained by whatever governs
the expansion of its tacit component. Pursuing
these points further is not within the scope of this paper, however; we wish
merely to stress once again, and from a different perspective, that the nature
of knowledge, its codification or tacitness, lurks only just beneath the
surface of important ideas about modern economic growth.
Leaving to one side, then, the problematic issue of defining
and quantifying the world stocks of either codified knowledge or tacit
knowledge, we can now turn to a fundamental empirical question regarding tacit
knowledge. Below,
15. This view could be
challenged on the grounds that knowledge held secretly by individuals is not
distingushable from labor (tangible human capital) as a productivity input,
but, unlike tangible physical capital, the existence of undisclosed knowledge
assets cannot be ascertained. Machlup (1980,
p. 175), in the sole passage devoted to the significance of tacit knowledge,
adopts the latter position and argues that: ‘Generation of socially new
knowledge is another non-operational concept as long as generation is not
complemented by dissemination.... Only if [an individual) shares his knowledge
with others can one recognize that new knowledge has been created. Generation of knowledge without dissemination
is socially worthless as well as unascertainable. Although “tacit knowledge” cannot be counted
in any sort of inventory, its creation may still be a part of the production of
knowledge if the activities that generate it have a measureable cost.’
227
we
address explicitly whether some situations, described as rife with tacit
knowledge, really are so, but for the moment we can make an important point
without entering into that issue.
Some activities seem to involve knowledge that is unvoiced -
activities which clearly involve knowledge but which refer only seldomly to
texts; or, put another way, which clearly involve considerable knowledge beyond
the texts that are referred to in the normal course of the activity. [16]
Thus
we can ask why is some knowledge silent, or unvoiced? There are two possible explanations: the
knowledge is unarticulable or, being capable of articulation, it remains
unvoiced for some other reason.
Why would some knowledge remain unarticulable? The standard economist’s answer is simply that
this is equivalent to asking why there are ‘shortages’, to which one must reply
‘there are no shortages’ when there are markets. So, the economist says, knowledge is not
articulated because, relative to the state of demand, the cost and supply price
is too high. Articulation, being social
communication, presupposes some degree of codification, but if it costs too
much actually to codify, this piece of knowledge may remain partly or wholly
uncodified. Without making any
disparaging remarks about this view, we can simply point out that there is some
knowledge for which we do not even know how to begin the process of
codification, which means that the price calculation could hardly be undertaken
in the first place. Recognition of this
state of affairs generates consensus on the uncodifiable nature of the
knowledge in question. We raise this to
emphasize the important point in what follows that the category of the
unarticulable (which may be coextensive with the uncodifiable) can safely be
put to one side. That, of course,
supposes there is still a lot left to discuss.
It is worth taking note of the two distinctions we have just
drawn, and the degree to which they define coextensive sets of knowledge. Knowledge that is unarticulable is also
uncodifiable, and vice versa: if it is (not) possible to articulate a thought
so that it may be expressed in terms that another can understand, then it is
(not) possible to codify it. This is the
source of the statement above that articulation presupposes codifiability. It is not the case, though, that codifiability
necessitates codification; a paper may be thought out fully, yet need not
actually be written out. Operationally,
the codifiability of knowledge (like the articulable nature of a thought)
cannot be ascertained independently from the actions of codification and
articulation. But, when we consider the
question of the status of knowledge with reference to multiple contexts, the
preceding strictly logical relations (implied by a single, universal
16. We note that
activities involving ‘unvoiced knowledge’ are often assumed to involve thereby
tacit knowledge. We argue below that
this is too hasty.
228
context)
are not exhaustive categories. Thus we
see the possible emergence of an additional category: codified (sometime,
somewhere) but not articulated (now, here). [17]
This observation implies that care needs
to be taken in jumping from the observed absence of codified knowledge
in a specified context to the conclusion that only some non-codifiable (i.e.
tacit) knowledge is available or employed.
It is within the realm of the codifiable or
articulable-yet-uncodified that conventional price and cost considerations come
into play in an interesting way, for within that region there is room for
agents to reach decisions about the activity of codification based upon its
costs and benefits. We shall discuss the
factors entering into the determination of that knowledge-status more fully
below.
4. A Proposed
Topography for Knowledge Activities
We now proceed to examine a new knowledge topography, from
which it will soon be evident that the realm of ‘the tacit’ can be greatly
constricted, to good effect. The new
topography we propose is meant to be consulted in thinking about where various
knowledge transactions or activities take place, rather than where knowledge of
different sorts may be said to reside. We
should emphasize that as economists, and not epistemologists, we are
substantively more interested in the former than in the latter.
By knowledge activities we refer to two kinds of activities:
the generation and use of ‘intellectual (abstract) knowledge’; and the
generation and use of ‘practical knowledge’, which is mainly knowledge about
technologies, artifacts (how to use this tool or this car, or how to improve
their performances) and organizations.
Given that definition, we need to clarify the distinction
between knowledge embodied in an artifact and codified knowledge about an
artifact. The distinction between
embodied and disembodied knowledge is a nice way for economists to capture
features of intersectoral flows (of technologies), particularly in an input-output
framework. Therefore, the fact that knowledge
is embodied in a machine tool is not to be conflated with the codification problem.
Knowledge about the production and the
use of artifacts, however, falls within our set of issues about codification:
does the use of this new tool require the permanent reference to a set of
codified instructions or not? We can put
this point in a slightly different way. From
the perspective
17.
In understanding these distinctions it is important to remember that we are
discussing knowledge activities, and the kinds of knowledge used in them. Thus we can observe activities in which the
knowledge has been codified at some point in history but is not articulated in
current endeavors.
229
of
a producer, any artifact, from a hammer to a computer, embodies considerable
knowledge. The artifact often is an
exemplar of that knowledge, and can sometimes be thought of as a ‘container’ or
‘storage vessel’ for it, as well as the means through which the knowledge may
be marketed. From the point of view of
the user, however, this is not necessarily the case. While any user will admit that the producer
needed a variety of kinds of knowledge to produce the artifact, this is of
little practical interest. The knowledge
of interest to the purchaser of a hammer or a PC, whether codified or not - and
indeed that often is the issue - is how to use the artifact, rather than the
knowledge that was called upon for its design and fabrication. Of course, the latter may bear upon the
former.
Part of the reason for this interpretation of what is to be
located in our topography is simply that discussions about ‘where knowledge
resides’ are difficult to conduct without falling into, or attempting to avoid,
statements about the relative sizes of the stocks of tacit and codified
knowledge, and their growth rates. By
and large, pseudo-quantitative discussions of that sort rarely turn out to be
very useful; indeed, possibly worse than unhelpful, they can be quite
misleading. Although there is no
scarcity of casual assertions made regarding the tendency toward increasing
(relative) codification, the issue of the relative sizes of the constituent
elements of the world stocks of scientific and technological knowledge resists
formal quantitative treatment. That is
to say, we really cannot hope to derive either theoretical propositions or
empirical measures regarding whether or not the relative size of the codified
portion must be secularly increasing or decreasing, or alternatively, whether
there is a tendency to a steady state. The
fundamental obstacle is the vagueness regarding the units in which ‘knowledge’
is to be measured.
To begin, we shall consider a topological tree structure in
which distinctions are drawn at four main levels. A tripartite branching on the uppermost level
breaks the knowledge transaction terrain into three zones: articulated (and
therefore codified), unarticulated and unarticulable. Setting the third category aside as not very
interesting for the social sciences, we are left with the major
dichotomy shown in Figure 1:
(a) Articulated (and thus codified). Here knowledge is recorded and referred to by ‘the group’, which is to say, ‘in a socio-temporal context’. Hence we can surmise that a codebook exists, and is referred to in the usual or standard course of knowledge-making and -using activities.
(b)
Unarticulated. Here we refer to knowledge that is not invoked explicitly
in the typical course of knowledge activities. Again, the concept of a context or group is
important.
230
In
case (a) a codebook clearly exists, since this is implicit in knowledge being
or having been codified. In case (b) two
possible sub-cases can be considered. In
one, knowledge is tacit in the normal sense - it has not been recorded either
in word or artifact, so no codebook exists. In the other, knowledge may have been
recorded, so a codebook exists, but this book may not be referred to by members
of the group - or, if it is, references are so rare as to be indiscernible to
an outside observer. Thus, at the next
level, ‘unarticulated’
231
splits
into two branches: (b. 1) in the situation indicated to the left, a source or
reference manual does exist but it is out of sight, so we say the situation is
that of a displaced codebook; and (b.2) to the right lie those
circumstances in which there truly is no codebook, but in which it would be
technically possible to produce one.
(b. 1) When a codebook exists, we still may refer to the
situation in which knowledge is unarticulated because within the group context
the codebook is not manifest; it is not explicitly consulted, nor in
evidence, and an outside observer therefore would have no direct indication of
its existence. The contents of the
codebook in such situations have been so thoroughly internalized, or absorbed
by the members of the group, that it functions as an implicit source of
authority. To the outside observer, this
group appears to be using a large amount of tacit knowledge in its
normal operations. [18]
A ‘displaced codebook’ implies that a codified body of
common knowledge is present, but not manifestly so. Technical terms figure in descriptive discussion
but go undefined because their meaning is evident to all concerned; fundamental
relationships among variables are also not reiterated in conversations and
messages exchanged among members of the group or epistemic community. [19] In
short, we have just described a typical state of affairs in what Kuhn (1962)
referred to as ‘normal science’; it is one where the knowledge base from which
the researchers are working is highly codified but, paradoxically, its
existence and contents are matters left tacit among the group unless some
dispute or memory problem arises. We may
analogously describe ‘normal technology’ as the state in which knowledge about
artifacts is highly codified but the codebook is not manifest.
Identification of the zone in which knowledge is codified
but the existence of codification is not manifest is an extremely important
result. But it poses a very difficult
empirical problem (or perhaps a problem of observation). This point is crucial in understanding the
economic problem raised by the management of knowledge in various situations:
when the codebook is displaced and knowledge is highly codified, new needs for
knowledge transfer or storage (or knowledge transactions generally) can be
fulfilled at a rather low cost (the cost of making the existing codebook
manifest), whereas when there is no
18. Here we may remark
that the ability to function effectively, possibly more effectively with the
codebook out of sight (e.g. to pass closed-book exams), often is one criterion
for entry, or part of the initiation into the group. Not being truly an initiated ‘insider’ is
generally found to be a considerable impediment to fully understanding the
transactions taking place among the members of any social group, let alone for
would-be ethnographers of ‘laboratory life’.
19. This often infuriates
outsiders, who complain vociferously about excessive jargon in the writings and
speeches of physicists, sociologists, economists, psychologists and...
232
codebook
at all, the cost will be very high (the cost of producing a codebook, which
includes costs of developing the languages and the necessary models).
This suggests that it would be useful to reconsider closely
the many recent empirical studies that arrive at the conclusion that the key
explanation for the observed phenomenon is the importance of tacit knowledge. That perhaps is true, but it is quite
difficult to document convincingly; most of such studies fail to prove that
what is observed is the effect of ‘true tacitness’, rather than highly codified
knowledge without explicit reference to the codebook. By definition, a codebook that is not manifest
will be equally not observed in that context, so it is likely that simple
proxies for ‘tacitness’ (such as whether communication of knowledge takes place
verbally in face-to-face transactions rather than by exchanges of texts) will
be misleading in many instances. Differentiating
among the various possible situations certainly requires deep and careful case
studies.
(b.2) When there is
no codebook, we again have a basic two-way division, turning on the existence
or non-existence of disputes. There may
be no disagreements. Here there is
stabilized uncodified knowledge, collective memory, convention and so on. This is a very common situation with regard to
procedures and structures within organizations. The IMF, for example, has nowhere written that
there in only one prescription for all the monetary and financial ills of the
world’s developing and transition economies; but, its advisers, in dispensing
‘identikit’ loan conditions, evidently behaved as if such a ‘code’ had been
promulgated. Such uncodified-but-stable
bodies of knowledge and practice, in which the particular epistemic community’s
members silently concur, will often find use as a test for admission to the
group or a signal of group membership to outside agents.
Where there are disagreements and no codebook is available
to resolve them within the group, it is possible that there exist some rules or
principles for dispute resolution. Elsewhere,
such ‘procedural authority’ may be missing. This is the chosen terrain of individual
‘seers’, such as business management gurus like Tom Peters, and others who
supply a form of ‘personal knowledge about organizational performance’. Equivalently, in terms of the outward
characteristics of the situation, this also might describe the world of ‘new
age’ religions - in contradistinction to structured ecclesiastical
organizations that refer to sacred texts.
There is, however, another possibility, which creates a
three-fold branch from node b.2: it may be the case that when disagreements
arise there is some procedural authority to arbitrate among the contending
parties. Recall that the situation here,
by construction, is one in which the relevant knowledge is
233
not
codified, and different members of the organization/group have distinct bodies
of tacit knowledge. When these sources
of differences among their respective cognitive contexts lead to conflict about
how to advance the group’s enterprise or endeavor, the group cannot function
without some way of deciding how to proceed - whether or not this has been
explicitly described and recorded. Clearly, once such a procedure is formalized
(codified), we have a recurrence of a distinction paralleling the one drawn at
the top of the tree in Figure 1, between codified and ‘unarticulated’. But this new bifurcation occurs at a meta-level
of procedures for generating and distributing knowledge, rather than
over the contents of knowledge itself. We
can, in principle, distinguish among different types of groups by using the
latter meta-level codified-tacit boundary. So the whole taxonomic apparatus may be
unpacked once again in discussing varieties of ‘constitutional’ rules for
knowledge-building activities. But that
would carry us too far from our present purposes.