Index
I. Introduction
II. A system of education: “the
great touchstone”
III. The erroneous calculation:
England and Wales
IV. The erroneous calculation:
Australia
V. Benthamism revisited:
differences among the faithful
VI. The continuing legacy
References
Notes
HHC: Index added
|
I- Introduction
Down to the
mid-20th century, economists in Britain and America did not
typically challenge the common assumption of political
science that political man pursued, not his own, but the
public interest. Subsequently the fledgling discipline of
public choice (or the economics of politics) explicitly
treated political and economic man as one and the same. Man
is now assumed to be an egoistic, rational, utility
maximizer in both settings. One implication is that it is
no longer adequate for economists to assume that progress
consists simply in persuading some government to accept
their analysis and implement appropriate advice. Everybody
now concedes that benevolent government does not exist. The
political machinery is seen, in fact, largely as operated by
interest groups, vote-maximizing politicians and
self-seeking bureaucracies. Similarly, it has for some time
been unsatisfactory for economists to believe that simply by
exposing market imperfections they have automatically
demonstrated a normative case for government intervention.
Theories of government failure are now at least as numerous
as theories of market failure.
Public choice
in Britain and America has been a belated development
compared, for instance, with Italy, Sweden and Germany. Its
relative neglect in the U.K. has been attributed by Buchanan
(1978) to Benthamite Utilitarianism which provided idealized
objectives for governmental policy to the neglect of
institutional structure. The British, “held on longer than
most people to the romantic notion that government seeks
only to do good in
1
some hazily
defined Benthamite sense, and, furthermore, to the
hypothesis that government could, in fact, accomplish most
of what it set out to do”. [1]
Buchanan
emphasizes the importance of separating the economic
analysis of politics into constitutional and
post-constitutional stages, and his main focus is upon the
former. If liberty, predictability and the rule of law are
to be protected, the greatest care and imagination is
required in the act of creating the basic constitutional
rules of the political ‘game’. In this setting, however,
the portrayal of Bentham’s efforts as being inimical to
public choice is undeserved. Bentham’s work, after all led
to profound reforms of the legal framework. These included
fundamental law reform in various branches; reform in
colonial governments; legalization of trade unions; free
speech and free press; a civil service appointed and
promoted on merit; general registration of titles to
property; and reform of local government.
One purpose of
this paper is to show that Buchanan’s critique of Bentham
has more validity in the post-constitutional dimension of
public choice, that is in the sense of attempting to ‘do
something’ by way of urging legislation on day-to-day
affairs within the existing rules of the constitution. The
historical context chosen is educational legislation. It
will be maintained that, while Bentham himself may have been
prompted partly by his own ‘genuine’ vision of the public
interest, and partly by prejudice against organized
religion, he underestimated the potential for distortionary
self-interested behavior of others, including subsequent
disciples, administrators, and fellow travellers. And it is
such behavior that is predictable in the new economics of
politics (which includes the economics of bureaucracy).
The paper
outlines the strong controlling power of the Utilitarians
over the 19th century evolution of national systems of
education in Britain and
2
Australia. It
will be shown that much of their political influence
depended on their use of flawed statistical reasoning. And
the fact that their success in shaping events was due
largely to such use of unscientific empirics is paradoxical
in view of their claimed new reliance on legislation that
was scientific.
While
Utilitarianism enjoyed stunning success in the short run, in
the long run it was increasingly compromised by forces
within democracy. As predicted by the modern economics of
bureaucracy, the eventual dominant objective of public
school systems is not to implement the greatest happiness
but to transfer wealth to educators. As the nineteenth
century progressed the Benthamite administrative apparatus
appeared to take on a life of its own. And several
latter-day Benthamites in office can be reasonably
interpreted as having begun to serve more than one master.
Section II
juxtaposes the basic educational doctrines of Bentham and
his followers with a summary of modern public choice
propositions. Section III describes the Benthamite use of
erroneous statistics when advising on educational deficiency
and examines the historical consequences. Section IV offers
a new investigation of the influence of the Benthamites on
events in Australia where the statistical ‘evidence’ was
used with more dramatic effect than in England and Wales.
Section V re-examines internal differences between the
Benthamites and, in particular, in the context of the
mid-century debate on free trade in education between James
Kay Shuttleworth and Robert Lowe. Section VI presents
concluding comments.
II. A system of
education: “the great touchstone”
In public
choice literature the government party in control of the
legislature has an objective function which includes not
only the probability of being
3
reelected, but
also “variables such as personal pecuniary gains, personal
power, [its] own image of history, the pursuit of lofty
personal ideals” and the party’s ‘personal view of the
common good’. [2] The Benthamite view of the common good
stemmed from its central utilitarian pleasure/pain
philosophy. Bentham’s basic proposition was that all human
beings desire the greatest amount of happiness. A corollary
was that good conduct of life would lead to this. Good
conduct in turn implied behavior that was intelligent. A
Benthamite government party was accordingly expected to
attempt to design efficient institutions so that the course
of action most advantageous to an individual would be always
beneficial to others. Actions which harmed others were to
be discouraged by penalties which brought predictable
personal injury to the actors. The fact that in real life
people committed ‘evil’ actions (i.e. actions which are
undesired) arose simply from ignorance of the true results
of their actions or, in other words, from faulty
anticipation. And because he did not believe in a
pre-established or providential harmony, but in a harmony
that could be engineered by ‘rational’ planning, Bentham
needed the control of education as the main instrument. The
powers of government were to be used widely and purposefully
to make people see for themselves that what was happening
through legislation was in their own interest.
In the hands of
his leading disciple, James Mill, Bentham’s ‘pleasure/ pain’
system of education received practical development. Of the
circumstances that affected an individual’s happiness, Mill
gave greatest attention to the physical. In his article on
education in the Encyclopaedia Britannica in 1818 he
stressed that bad health influenced the state of a person’s
mind and one of the most important duties of schools was to
make scientific observations and recordings on such
influences. Good food and the right air and temperature
were also emphasized, and this foreshadowed the
4
thoroughgoing
specification for school architecture to be made by Edwin
Chadwick and James Kay later in the century. But beyond
this the most important conditioning of children concerned
instruction in how to attain happiness and follow moral
ideals.
A government’s
ability to inculcate its own set of ideals, however, is
obviously a function of voter support. Under simple
majority rule, for example, it will be able to indulge in
the ‘luxury’ of implementing its own personal view of the
common good only if it has generous vote surplus, as with
say a majority of 75 percent. The governing party is,
nevertheless, always constrained by the threat of entry by
an opposition part or parties. To reduce such vulnerability
it can employ several discriminatory tactics. [3] These
include the attempt to “seek to alter the preferences of
citizens so as to reduce the differences that exist between
them and thus make them more homogeneous”. [4] The seizure
of the high ground of education policy was thus crucial to
the Benthamites. Once ‘conditioned’ by them, the population
would have the benefit of proper training to pursue its own
happiness automatically.
The Utilitarian
party’s main competitor in the field of education was seen
to be organized religion. Mill and Bentham made no secret
of their preference for a secular education. Of the two,
however, Bentham was by far the more hostile to the
Established Church, which he condemned as a downright enemy
to educational progress. The most severe attack appeared in
his ‘Church of Englandism’ in 1818 in which he accused the
Church of being jealous of the Quaker, Lancaster, for his
success with his new schools in which the Bible only was
used: “... the Bible might prevail over the Catechism and
the Church of England might thus be brought to an end” [5]
The moment
legislation establishing the first government funding of
education came (in 1833) the Benthamites were prompt with
their protests.
5
They objected
strongly to the fact that religious societies had been given
the responsibility for allocating the subsidies and
especially to the fact that in practice, the established
denominational schools were receiving the largest share.
The final pages of the Report of the Poor Law Commission
(1834) written by Nassau Senior and Edwin Chadwick, echoed
the complaint: “We believe, that if the funds now destined
to the purposes of education, many of which are applied in a
manner unsuited to the present wants of society, were wisely
and economically employed, they would be sufficient to give
all the assistance which can be prudently afforded by the
State”. Because, however, the radical education movement
challenging the established church comprised Nonconformists,
it was not expedient for Benthamites openly to oppose
religious instruction per se in schools. The result was a
compromise whereby they frequently allied themselves with
nonconformism in demanding non-denominational teaching only.
This was the main platform of the (Nonconformist) British
and Foreign School Society in contrast to the National
Society for Promoting the Education of the Poor sponsored by
the established church.
The
Utilitarians emphasized the need for centralization and the
economies of large scale, as explained in Bentham’s vast
educational treatise Chrestomathia (Bowring, 1962,
Vol. ii). In his capacity as a member of the Newcastle
Commission on Popular Education, later in the century,
Nassau Senior confidently quoted the evidence of Inspector
Tufnell on this matter:
In the large
school there is the subdivision of labour of teachers. In
the Central London District School, for example, there is
the headmaster with a large salary, and two under masters,
and eight pupil-teachers. These masters have not all the
same talents or capacities, but are often appointed for
their specialities. [6]
6
The ‘hard line’
Utilitarian doctrine maintained that denominational schools
were typically too small to take advantage of scale
economies. The Utilitarian program that developed later
included an urgent need for a trained inspectorate and a
system of publicly operated normal schools for the training
of teachers.
On the question
of economics the main argument offered was that since
education reduced crime there would be a positive net payoff
to society from investment of public funds. Chapter XX of
Part III of Bentham’s Principles of Penal Law was the
source of this particular argument. But again the most
relevant teaching that would reduce crime, according to the
Benthamites, could best be conducted in their own specially
designed schools.
Encouraged by
the success of the Reform Act in 1832, the year of Bentham’s
death, and by their representation in the new House of
Commons, the spokesman for the Utilitarians, J.A. Roebuck,
voiced all aspects of Benthamite educational philosophy,
beginning with the argument about crime reduction.
We all of us
seem to feel the necessity of supervising our Criminal Code
- our Code of Prison Discipline - Our Poor-Laws; but all
these are only offshoots of, or adjustments to, a system of
Education. That is the great touchstone, the mainspring of
the whole. We allow crime and misery to spring up, and then
attempt, by a vast cumbrous machinery, to obviate the
mischief. We punish, we do not prevent... [7]
The anxiety of
the younger generation of Benthamites to eliminate the
competition, even from the Nonconformist schools, now became
explicit. Roebuck argued before the House not only the
benefits of a general education but also “why the Government
should itself supply this education”. Only government
supplied schooling could efficiently teach how violation of
its
7
laws could best
be avoided. As for what we call today ‘consumer
sovereignty’, Roebuck argued that families were not in the
best position to choose. To pursue pleasure and avoid pain
efficiently required guidance: “The people at present are
far too ignorant to render themselves happy”. [8]
Not all the
Utilitarians would have agreed with Roebuck’s call for
government supplied schooling. John Stuart Mill, for
example, uttered his famous warning that “A general state
education is a mere contrivance for moulding people to be
exactly like one another” (Mill, 1962, p. 239).
The Benthamites
frequently acknowledged that low income families were
purchasing education for themselves. But this itself was a
problem in the eyes of the Utilitarians because, as Roebuck
insisted, the education chosen was of the ‘wrong’ kind. And
despite his dislike of the homogenizing tendencies of state
education, John Stuart Mill expressed the same kind of view:
... persons
requiring improvement, having an imperfect or altogether
erroneous conception of what they want, the supply called
forth by the demand will be anything but what is really
required. (J.S. Mill, 1969, p. 953).
What is so
striking is that Benthamism, which generally embraced the
classical economic free trade doctrine, was driven to make
such a notable exception in the case of education. Was it
recognized that there may be logical inconsistencies in this
stance? John Stuart Mill especially tried boldly to grapple
with this question. Asserting in his Principles that
“in this case the laissez faire principle breakes
down entirely” (Mill 1969, p. 957), he maintained that this
was because (a) children cannot choose for themselves wisely
and (b) they are, in any case, without the means to do so.
By the same logic, however, the laissez faire
principle breaks down also in
8
the case of
feeding, clothing and sheltering of children, because here
too there are the same impediments to responsible choosing
by dependent minors. The fact that, as a policy matter,
Mill and his colleagues treated education differently from
food and clothing is ostensibly inconsistent.
If society
places on parents the duty of feeding and clothing children
why precisely does it not similarly allot them the
responsibility for children’s education? J.S. Mill answered
that this question switches attention to a separate issue:
“whether the government... should leave absolutely in [the
parents’] power the conduct and interests of somebody else”.
It is arguable, however, that what most people have in mind
is not the granting of absolute power to parents but a
fiduciary power to be removed in cases where abuse can be
shown. Safeguards for education can be treated as a part of
a comprehensive system of child abuse laws. Today this
system includes, besides education, protection against
malnutrition, welfare payments to families with dependent
children, and stringent rules about divorce when young
children are involved. Child abuse laws, of course, are
also designed to monitor, control and discipline delinquent
parents who give their children inadequate clothing and
shelter. But ultimately insistence on this line of
reasoning would apparently have been rejected by Mill
because he believed, that in the case of education, the
parents, as distinct from the children, (a) could not choose
wisely and (b) in any event did not have the means to do so.
But if adults cannot thus be relied on, Mill’s system is
clearly paternalistic. He was not so different from other
Utilitarians after all.
With regard to
poor law administration after 1834, Benthamism was
translated into practical policy by Edwin Chadwick with
personal advice from the Mills and Nassau Senior. Appointed
secretary to the Poor Law Commission, Chadwick set out to
combat what he held to be the inefficiency and corruption
9
of local
agencies. The new Benthamite policy characteristically
favored strong centralized administration, trained
inspectors and able civil servants whose appointment and
promotion depended on success in examinations. The test of
examinations, incidentally, was eventually applied later to
the government subsidy in the form of Robert Lowe’s system
of ‘payments by results’ wherein teachers were paid salaries
in proportion to the examination successes of their
students.
Also appointed
to the Poor Law Commission soon after, and this time as an
assistant commissioner, was James Kay (later
Kay-Shuttleworth). According to the Dictionary of National
Biography it was Kay’s experience among the poor ‘and his
grasp of economic science’ that brought him to the attention
of the government. Kay was introduced by Senior to Chadwick
and the Mills with whom there was much subsequent
intellectual discourse. Chadwick delegated Kay to produce
reports on the training of pauper children and these, with
Chadwick’s clear approval, were published by the government
in 1841. Kay’s enthusiasm and success with the educational
work of the Commission presumably led to his appointment as
the First Secretary of the Committee of the Privy Council on
Education in 1839.
In the British
educational histories Kay enjoys the same kind of reverence
as does Horace Mann in America, both being regarded as the
founding fathers of their respective public systems of
education. One can also view their actions, however, as
being consistent with the predictions of today’s bureaucracy
theory. It states that, whereas the usual bureau urges
monopoly status, avowedly to avoid wasteful duplication, the
actual winning of the monopoly position frees it from
competitive pressures to be efficient, in which case waste
is ultimately increased. The monopoly bureau in fact
becomes more and more difficult to monitor because the
funding agency is denied an
10
alternative
source of information by which to gauge its efficiency.
Meanwhile the growing fog of obscurity surrounding the
allocation of the enlarging budget enables the senior
bureaucrat to increase his salary and/or the perquisites of
his job. Motivated primarily at all times to try to secure
an expansion of the bureau’s budget, the senior
administrator enjoys progressive increases in his personal
position because of the growth of the numbers of junior
bureaucrats for whom he is responsible. [9]
One of the
mysteries of British educational history concerns the
apparent secrecy surrounding the setting up of what soon
became, in effect, the department of education. Originally
called the Privy Council Committee on Education, its first
secretary, as mentioned previously, was James Kay. One of
the immediate consequences of the work of the Committee was
the effective erosion of the power of the denominations in
allocating government funds to schools. This event provoked
much controversy and opposition from the established church.
Kay successfully survived this period, however, and his
Committee proceeded to purchase increasing influence over
independent schools by offering subsidies in return for
school inspection and regulation.
Arguments for
increases in total subsidy expenditure depended upon
evidence of their need. The main evidence produced was in
the form of new statistical calculations of ‘educational
destitution’. The first government investigation on this
score was conducted by Lord Kerry in 1833. Local
non-government statistical societies, meanwhile, were now
beginning to appear with their own independent calculations
pertaining to particular towns. Among these was the
Manchester Statistical Society of which Kay was the founder.
Its criticisms of the Kerry Report received wide attention
and this too added to Kay’s personal reputation.
11
At first sight
Kay’s Manchester Statistical Society (MSS) seems to have
been motivated by the desire to deliver newly reported
objective facts as a firm foundation for Benthamite
scientific legislation. Further examination, however,
throws considerable doubt on the objectivity of the MSS
findings. One problem is that its definition of efficient
schooling contained a primary emphasis on the presence of
moral instruction, and this of course involves profound
individual value judgments. But the second problem, upon
which we concentrate, relates to the Benthamites’ dubious
quantitative measure of educational deficiency. A full
explanation in its British setting will be followed by an
examination of the Australian experience.
III. The
erroneous calculation: England and Wales
In 1838 a
Select Committee was appointed to inquire into the state of
education in England and Wales. Dr. Kay, then at the Poor
Law Commission, and also in his capacity of founder member
and treasurer of the MSS, was the chief witness. The
exchange between him and a member of the Select Committee,
William Gladstone, brings out the problems with the MSS
calculations. As a preliminary it is necessary to point out
that not all members of the Benthamite coterie were
unenthusiastic about the role of religion. And although
some of them appeared to support the nonconformist world
only when it suited, others gave evidence of steadfast
religious devotion. Kay appears to have been one of the
latter group. It is important to notice, nevertheless, that
the bigger the demonstrated size of educational deficiency
and the greater the evidence that it was concentrated in the
small scale private schools, the greater the case for
supersession by a special government department of education
financed by a generous budget.
12
Simply wanting
to know how much education existed in the towns in 1838, the
Committee, asked Kay, via (the devout) Mr. Gladstone, the
direct and apparently innocent question:“Can you form an
estimate of the amount of deficiency in the means of
education in any given district, say for instance, the
district of Manchester?” Promptly switching attention to
issues of quality, Kay replied: “If by education I am to
understand what I have previously described, sound religious
instruction, correct moral training, and a sufficient extent
of secular knowledge suited to their station in life, I
should scarcely say that it exists within the limits of my
observation.” Chairman: “You think it is not afforded by
any schools at present efficiently?” Kay: “Not
efficiently.” [10]
Another
enthusiast for large scale economies in schooling, Kay had
an almost doctrinaire dislike of small schools, which were
usually the entirely self-supporting establishments called
‘common day schools’. The large monitorial Lancastrian and
National (Charity) schools, on the other hand, were among
his favorites at this period. In reaching its conclusions
as to the quality and quantity of schooling, the 1838
Committee evidently relied heavily on Kay’s evidence, and
that of his Manchester Statistical Society. That it was
particularly in the small private schools that poor quality
teaching was complained of by the Committee is therefore not
very surprising.
But Gladstone
seems to have been the only member of the Committee to have
clearly perceived that Kay was confusing questions of
quality with those of quantity. [11]
Gladstone:
“Separating from your view at present all those
considerations which appear to attach rather to the quality
than to the quantity of education, and looking simply to the
question of quantity,
13
can you form an
idea of what number of children there are in the town and
neighbourhood of Manchester, upon any given population,
that are entirely without education of any kind, however
defective?”(italics supplied).
Kay:
“The Report of the Committee of the Manchester Statistical
Society states that one-third of the children between 5-15
are not receiving instruction of any kind whatever;
[12] and the report also proceeds to state, that the
education given in the common day schools and dame schools,
and certain other schools appears to be either altogether
inefficient or very indifferent”(italics supplied).
Gladstone:
“In reference to the first part of your answer, do you
imagine that they have arrived at that statement by
calculating the number of children between 5 and 15 in the
population, and then ascertaining the number of children who
attend schools, of any kind, and given the difference as the
amount of deficiency which exists?’
Kay:“Certainly”.
Gladstone:
“Do you imagine that the average number of children who
attend schools in Manchester continue in attendance for
anything like the period of 10 years?”
Kay:
“In the Sunday Schools the great mass of the children
continue pretty regularly in attendance; and I have personal
experience of the quality of instruction conveyed in the
Sunday schools of Manchester which, as far as religious
instruction is concerned, may be stated to be the best
instruction which exists of this nature.”
14
Gladstone:
“But do you think that the generality of the children who go
to school at all in Manchester continue at school, week-day
or Sunday, for anything like so long a period of 10 years?”
Kay:
“I think the great portion of the Sunday scholars do.”
Gladstone:
“Do you think that any considerable proportion of the day
scholars continue at school for 10 years?’
Kay:
“I do not think that any very considerable proportion of day
scholars do.”
Gladstone:
“Then will not the calculation be inaccurate if it has been
upon the supposition, that those who are at school continue
at school from the age of five to the age of fifteen?”
Kay:
“Certainly; it can only refer to the number who were at
school at the period when the calculations were made....”
Eventually
Gladstone asked: “Do you think that the daily instruction at
this moment provided in Manchester is sufficient to supply
all the children of Manchester between the ages of five and
thirteen?”
Kay’s
evasiveness persisted to the end:
Kay:
“If the instruction conveyed were of the quality that I
would desire, I should say that its extent was
insufficient for that purpose.” (italics supplied.) [13]
15
To find the
number of children who, in Gladstone’s words, were “entirely
without education of any kind, however defective,” we need a
specific survey to elicit the de facto school entering and
leaving ages. Crucial information pertinent to this
variable did not appear until 1839 with the results of an
intensive house-to-house survey in 1838 of Manchester’s
neighbor - Pendleton, a typical town of the Industrial
Revolution.
The MSS had at
last, in the Pendleton case, found one of the most
appropriate methods of reporting a more accurate and
comprehensive picture of educational quantity. It concluded
“That not more than 2 to 3 percent... of the juvenile
population are at present left entirely destitute of
instruction…” [14] Of the school-goers, ... one-third
appear to remain less than three years; one-third from three
to five years; and one-third remain above five years”
(Report p. 74). These facts seem to have been carefully
obtained. The investigators acknowledged the difficulty of
checking the accuracy of the personal statements from each
household, “but wherever anything in these statements threw
upon their report the slightest suspicion of inaccuracy, the
cases have been classed as not ascertained” (p. 73). On the
reasonable assumption that conditions in Manchester were
similar to those in Pendleton, Kay’s answer to Gladstone to
the effect that one-third of the Manchester children were
entirely destitute of education was a gross overstatement.
But by now (1839), and relying on the earlier ‘evidence’
the government education bureau had already been
established.
Gladstone’s
implied criticism of Kay’s statistical reasoning does not
appear to have widely registered. [15] The same reasoning
continued to be the applied methodology after 1839 within
Kay’s ‘education department’ in attempts at measurement in
several other towns besides Manchester.
16
The most
substantial influence of Kay’s ‘Erroneous Calculation’
occurred, indeed, at the time of Britain’s major piece of
19th century educational legislation: the W.E. Forster Act
of 1870. When presenting his Bill, Forster avoided the 1861
Newcastle Commission’s findings that the vast majority of
children were already receiving a schooling despite the
absence of both compulsion and zero pricing. Instead he
referred to an ad hoc investigation of four industrial towns
hurriedly sponsored by members of his education bureaucracy.
Drawing upon this he told Parliament:
It is
calculated that in Liverpool the number of children between
five and thirteen who ought to receive an elementary
education is 80,000; but, as far as we can ascertain, 20,000
of them attend no school whatever, while at least another
20,000 attend schools where they get an education not worth
having. [16]
Forster’s
figures involve the same fallacy of misplaced school-age
base that featured Kay’s Manchester Statistical Society’s
Report on Manchester in 1834. Only one participant in the
Parliamentary Debate in 1870, Lord Robert Montagu, seems to
have perceived some error.
The right hon.
gentleman alluded to the case of Liverpool, where he said
there were 80,000 children between the ages of five and
thirteen. Of these he said that 20,000 were in no school;
and 20,000 went to inferior schools. The (Newcastle)
Commissioners thought that for the children of the working
class, six years schooling would be sufficient. Now, as
there are eight years between five and thirteen, if every
one of those children were to attend school for six years,
three-fourths of the number ought to be at school in each
year; and according to the showing of the right hon.
gentleman, there were three-fourths of the number at school.
17
The real
conclusion of Forster’s figures therefore was that
... every child
which should be at school was at school, but one quarter
were at bad schools, which perhaps might be improved. [17]
It is
consistent with the economic theory of bureaucracy that
bureaucrats would have a self-interest in presenting the
prevailing quantity of schooling in as bad a light as
possible. This strategy would strengthen the case for
further intervention which would increase both the budget
and the importance of the bureau. The enquiries on the four
towns were conducted for the education department by
Inspectors J.G. Fitch and D.R. Fearon. The school-age
fallacy appears in various forms throughout their reports.
Fearon used a school age of 5-13. Fitch, ‘to avoid
dogmatic statement’ used various ones: 3-13, 3-15, or 5-13.
We learn also from these reports the detailed basis of the
bureau’s judgment that the education of 20,000 students in
Liverpool was ‘not worth having’. The number of children
‘effectively taught’ were represented by the numbers passing
the inspector. To qualify to be examined by the inspector
however, the child must have attended that same school
for at least 200 times in the course of the year. In
practice very many who could have passed were not able to
for ‘physical’ reasons. Many left school before the
examination-day and could not be brought back for the
inspection. Others were prevented on the day by sickness or
accident. There were still others who had not been in
that particular school for 200 times because they had
migrated from another school or another part of the country.
These could have scored well in class examinations had the
system allowed them to be inspected.
The Education
Department seems to have been keenly working for its own
expansion. There was expectation of its involvement in a
vast new school building agenda and thereafter in a bigger
scale of inspection. The building program in fact soon
materialized in the school board construction ‘boom’
18
after 1870 when
public schools (in the American sense) were first
introduced. As it transpired the authorities did not
succeed in getting the school leaving age raised very much
in the ten years after 1870, even with the growth of public
school accommodation. The only general effect of a
subsequent Act of 1880, for instance, was to enforce
complete attendance of children between 5 and 9 years
inclusive.
One result of
the failure to raise the school leaving age significantly
was that the extra schools (the new board schools) that the
Forster’s Act established resulted in excess government
school capacity. [18] To resolve this embarrassment the
authorities had one remaining political stratagem: education
in the board schools was to be declared free of charge.
According to one historian: “The abolition of fees in Board
Schools in 1891 was the death blow to the private schools...
By 1895 there were [in Nottingham] only 24 [private]
schools with 489 children and the number continued to
decline until 1898 when there were thirteen schools with 270
pupils”. [19] But this crowding out of the private by the
government schools seems to have been a Benthamite objective
from the beginning of the century.
IV. The
erroneous calculation: Australia
The most
interesting actor on the Australian scene was none other
than Robert Lowe who was once described by Dicey as “the
last of the Utilitarians”. Lowe was later to become the
education secretary in England who introduced the notorious
‘Revised Code’ concerning government subsidization of
non-government schools. Arriving in Sydney in 1840 where he
set up a law practice, he was appointed to the legislature
of New South Wales (hereafter N.S.W.) in 1842. One of his
earliest tasks was to head an official enquiry into the
condition
19
of education.
In his report he complained: “The very essence of a
denominational system is to leave the majority uneducated in
order thoroughly to imbue the minority with peculiar tenets”
(Griffiths 1957, p. 74). He also insisted that where the
population was small and scattered, denominational schools
were uneconomical and inefficient, propositions that clearly
followed the Benthamite ‘prescription package’. Lowe
proceeded to engage in a battle with the denominational
elites that appears indeed to have been far more acrimonious
than the equivalent struggle Kay was experiencing in
England. [20]
Like the other
English Benthamites, Lowe’s argument rested heavily on The
Erroneous Calculation. It appears early in his Report as
follows:
There are about
25,676 children between the ages of four and fourteen years;
of these, only 7,642 receive instruction in public schools,
and 4,865 in private ones, leaving about 13,000 children who
as far as your Committee know, are receiving no education
at all. (Italics supplied, Griffiths, 1957.)
In practice few
children in N.S.W. in the 1840s would ever remain in school
for ten years (4-14 yrs). Again using the British 1851
Census figure as a rough guide, suppose on average they
received five years of schooling. In this, more realistic
case, the number “receiving no education at all” in 1842
would have been close to zero.
Whether Lowe
was aware of the fallacious nature of his statistics it is
not easy to say. [21] But his numerical conclusion of
13,000 totally unschooled children was used relentlessly by
him as ‘evidence’ of the educational failure of the
denominational system. A few weeks after presenting his
1844 Report, Lowe told a special meeting on education called
by the Mayor:
Gentlemen,
there are thirteen thousand children in this colony growing
up without a knowledge of the God who made them, or of the
Saviour who died
20
for them. We
come forward with a proposition to arrest this evil, to
check this plague, to substitute light for darkness,
religion for atheism, and we are met by ... overstrained
objections. [22]
Another
component of the Benthamite package included in Lowe’s
Report was the argued need for central administration plus
inspection. “Your Committee are not prepared to recommend
the establishment of Local Boards of Education, conceiving
that a central Board, with an efficient system of
inspection, will produce results more uniform and
satisfactory” (Griffiths 1957, p.75). And finally there was
an emphasis on the importance of the training of teachers:
The foundation
of a Normal or Model School in Sydney, for the training of
schoolmasters, appears to your Committee to be an
indispensable step. (Griffiths 1957, p.75.)
Back in England
the Benthamite enthusiasm for teacher training had become so
strong that, with the cooperation of his friend E.C.
Tufnell, and from their private resources, James Kay had
established the first training college for teachers at
Battersea in 1839-40. Pupil teachers were transferred from
the Norwood Pauper School and became the first students of
the college. At first, Kay lived in and superintended the
entire working of the institution, but the whole endeavor
was soon supported with government aid.
One of the
‘star’ pupils from Kay’s Battersea college was William
Wilkins who, in 1851, was invited to become Master of a
model school in Sydney. He eventually introduced into it
the pupil-teacher system and reorganized the school as a
prototype for a national system. By 1854 there were over
fifty national schools and Wilkins was appointed their
Inspector and Superintendent. [23] More than any other
member of the Benthamite group, Wilkins seems to fit the
role of career bureaucrat who becomes fully aware that the
pressure he applies to further an ideology is not
inconsistent with progress in his own career and
remuneration.
21
Wilkins
developed a friendship with Henry Parkes a journalist and
politician who claimed to be devoted to the cause of public
education and one who had been a campaign manager for Robert
Lowe’s political election periods. In 1854 Wilkins
succeeded in getting himself appointed as one of three
Commissioners to investigate elementary schools and he soon
became the dominant spokesman. In the final report of the
Commission in December 1855, there appears a clear example
of the influence of Wilkins’ mentor Kay in England. The
Report complained that only one-half of the approximately
50,000 children ‘of an age to be in school’ (presumably
5-14) were at school. Wilkins’ Report failed to observe
that, realistically, if the average de facto school
duration of children was five years then nearly all children
must have been receiving an education. Indeed ‘The
Erroneous Calculation’ seems here to be the most egregious
of all because later in the Wilkins’ Report it is regretted
that “We are under the impression that the average time
spent at school by each child cannot far exceed two years”.
(!)
The Report also
observed that the average school fee was sixpence for each
child per week. The Benthamite dislike of positive priced
free trade in education for the working class appears in the
complaint that “in very many instances, the rivalry between
schools has tended to cause a reduction in the rate of
school fees; and we regard this circumstance as one of the
worst results of the present competition of systems ... the
rivalry of systems tends to divide, and consequently weaken
every endeavour for the promotion of education” (Griffiths,
1957, p. 92). The Benthamite desire for uniformity is also
revealed in the Report’s later conclusion that the
‘piecemeal character’ of education was a serious defect.
“There should be but one system, specially adapted to the
wants of the community, and controlled and administered by
one managing body”.
22
In 1866 Wilkins
prepared Henry Parkes for the task of introducing the most
radical of all legislation on N.S.W. schooling: the
Public Schools Act. All possible evidence was mustered
to show the weaknesses of the denominational system and the
earlier arguments of Lowe and Wilkins were rehearsed to good
effect. According to Barcan (1988), Wilkins even urged his
inspectors to inform local supporters of the desperate
financial position of the government schools. It should be
noticed that, by this time, most denominational schools were
receiving subsidies, although to a much smaller amount than
the National (government) schools.
The Public
Schools Act of 1866 created a Council of Education.
Henry Parkes was elected its Chairman and Wilkins its
Secretary. This new government regime discriminated
promptly and severely against denominational establishments.
Restrictions, for example, were placed on church schools
that were close to public institutions. The full cost of
initiating denominational schools, moreover, fell on the
local (voluntary) supporters whereas the equivalent costs
for the public schools was covered by the Council via funds
from compulsory taxation. The effect on Church school
enrollments was devastating. Whereas denominational schools
had contained 55 percent of all pupils in 1867, the
proportion had fallen to 38 percent by 1872 (Barcan 1988, p.
119).
It seems no
exaggeration to say, once more, that ‘The Erroneous
Calculation’ was a main cause, if not the key influence, in
the passing of the educational legislation. Combined with
the rhetoric of Parkes, a consummate politician, it seems to
have impressed all sides of the debate. According to Austin
(1961), Parkes’ speech on the second reading is generally
regarded as his greatest. It is interesting to note,
however, that Barcan (1988, p. 147) believes that Parkes
“collected his interesting educational ideas from other
23
people... and
especially William Wilkins”. Parkes’ friend Robert Lowe had
undoubtedly been another important influence. The following
is a key extract from Parkes’ speech:
The children
under 14 years of age in the country at the latest date to
which our statistics come was 150,845... Of this number
there were attending schools 53,452, leaving the enormous
number of 97,393 with no education whatever...(Griffiths,
p. 117, italics supplied)
Parkes failed
to remind his audience that his figure of 150,845
individuals under 14 years of age included those who were
too young for schooling. If we take this subset to be up to
5 years, and assuming the same number in each 0-5year of
this group, we arrive at a gross school age base of 92,828.
This is the number of children from 5 to 13 year olds, a
span of 9 years. What is missing next is information on the
average school duration. If we assume, for instance, an
average de facto school life of 5.2 years the number ‘with
no education whatsoever’ would have been zero. But in any
case still further appeal to the data is necessary. The
statistics could be biased, for instance, because of greater
numbers in the 0-4 year cohorts than in the 5-13 cohorts.
But whatever the final figure, Parkes’ claim that there
were nearly 100,000 ‘with no education whatever’ is totally
invalid. This erroneous statistic nevertheless was paraded
at every opportunity.
I think then I
have made out a case for interference. If we are here with a
population little over 400,000, and if one-quarter of the
whole are children in a state of educational destitution,
with no provision at all for their instruction, I think it
will be admitted that I have unanswerably made out a case
for interference ... No higher duty can engage the ability
of Parliament than supplying these hundred thousand unhappy
children with the means of instruction ...
24
And the same
‘ghost army’ of 100,000 educationally destitute is made to
do service in Parkes’ final flight of rhetoric.
The voices of a
hundred thousand children appeal to you and implore you not
to allow any secondary consideration to impair your generous
exercise of power in saving them from neglect and
ignorance... They will come after us in the field and in
the workshop, in the school and in the church, in the
judgment seat and within these walls is a mighty wave of
intelligence that must receive its temper from you, but
whose fire you will not be here to control. (Griffiths, p.
117, 1887.)
V. Benthamism
revisited: differences among the faithful
It has been
observed (Ekelund and Hebert 1990, p. 215) that the
individual who more than any other bridged the gap between
utilitarian theory and bureaucratic practice was Edwin
Chadwick. Bentham had prescribed a set of penalties and
rewards to promote the public interest, and this was
avowedly seen simply as the summation of individual
interests. In fact, however, Chadwick found the concept of
public interest much more complex than it first seemed. The
practical solution, for him, was to define improvements in
the public interest simply as actions that reduce economic
waste. And according to Chadwick’s ‘preventive principle’
the administrator should anticipate and then prevent waste
from occurring in the first place.
Chadwick’s main
focus was upon well specified and imaginative contracts
relating to all the public services. In the case of
policemen, for instance, he recommended that their wages
should be based on productivity. But because of the
difficulty of measuring police output (the services of
prevention), Chadwick argued that relative wages be based
“on the comparison of crimes
25
committed in
one police jurisdiction with those committed in other
jurisdictions where property was similarly situated”
(Ekelund and Hebert, 1990, p. 217).
Among the later
generations of Utilitarians it seems appropriate to classify
Robert Lowe as a ‘Chadwick-style Benthamite’. Appointed as
Vice-President to the Privy Council Committee on Education
in 1861, he appears to have been instructed by Gladstone to
effect economies in the government’s education budget. The
new Vice-President found a central office of education that
was particularly complicated. There were 7,000 certificated
teachers and 15,000 pupil teachers employed in
(nongovernment) schools and all were paid by government post
office orders sent directly to their private addresses.
Lowe was soon convinced that the main failure was the
absence of some machinery for testing the results of
the teachers’ employment. Like Chadwick on the subject of
policemens’ pay, Lowe wanted teachers to be rewarded
according to their productivity.
In cooperation
with R. Lingen, Lowe proceeded to produce the famous Revised
Code. One key provision in it was as follows:
The managers of
schools may claim one penny per scholar for every attendance
after the first 100, at the morning or afternoon meetings.
One-third part of the sum thus claimable is forfeited if
the scholar fails to satisfy the inspector in reading,
one-third if in writing, and one-third if in arithmetic
respectively.
For introducing
this ‘payment by results’ plan, Lowe was attacked from
nearly all quarters and especially by the newly organized
teaching bodies. The main objection was that the Revised
Code encouraged ‘cramming’ and spread the belief that the
most important rudiments of education were the three Rs.
26
Attention was
diverted from the moral function of the school and from the
importance of manual skills and physical exercises.
It is
interesting that in one place Lowe referred to the reform in
terms of introducing some ‘free trade’ into education. He
seems, however, to have been using the concept in a special
way. If he really wanted free trade in the usual sense of
market competition he could have suggested implementing an
educational voucher system; for this would certainly have
re-established consumer sovereignty. Like most Benthamites,
however, he distrusted parental choice among the working
class. In his view it was the government of the day who was
the key ‘consumer’ and an economizing government was
interested in keeping down waste by arranging for supply by
competitive tender.
The Revised
Code debate revealed apparently sharp differences between
the leading Benthamite educational leaders. James Kay, now
Sir James Kay Shuttleworth, was indeed one of Lowe’s
sharpest critics. On the analogy with free trade, however,
they seem to have been arguing at cross purposes. Kay
Shuttleworth retorted:
No fallacy is
more transparent or more monstrous than that which assumes
that knowledge, or whatever training is got in schools, is a
natural want, certain to assert itself like the want of
food, or clothing, or shelter, and to create a demand. The
fact is the very reverse of this assumption... All
statesmen who have wished to civilize and instruct a nation
have to create this appetite. (Frank Smith, p. 269).
Kay
Shuttleworth’s main complaint was that moral and
psychological education was, if anything, more important
than the three Rs. [24] There appears an emphasis here on
the traditional and idealistic aim of Bentham himself in
27
wanting to
teach people all avenues to happiness simultaneously. Lowe,
the practical ‘Chadwick-style Benthamite’ on the other hand
could not see any way of testing the success of teachers in
producing moral or psychological ‘output’ much as he wanted
to do this.
Lowe is the
more interesting in that, as we have seen, he started out in
Australia with inordinate zeal to reduce the educational
influence of denominational church schooling. And his
uncritical use of ‘The Erroneous Calculation’ seems to be
explained as an expedient aimed at preparing the way for the
crowding out of the schools that parents were choosing. His
early enthusiasm for a ‘national system’ certainly seems to
have been based on the earlier Benthamites’ romantic or
idealistic view of government. By the 1860s, however, Lowe
had received much personal experience within public office
and he began to compromise his earlier hostility to
organized religion. If indeed he was the last of the
Utilitarians he was exceptional in recognizing in the
political process the strong possibility and danger of what,
modern public choice analysis calls ‘rent seeking’. Thus in
1865, after he had relinquished his education office, Lowe
explained that a main cause of the hostility he had invited
in that capacity was that
The Revised
Code swept away the vested interests of some 10,000
teachers, who had begun to consider themselves as government
employees, having a claim on augmentation grants for the
rest of their lives. [25]
Evidently Kay
had created a growing political constituency in the shape of
a cadre of teachers who had been trained in his normal
schools (teacher training colleges). And he had already
argued that “The first business of the State is to improve
the lot of the teacher”. [26]
One final point
of interest concerning Lowe is that he sharply divided the
population into the working class, which needed the guidance
of Benthamite
28
paternalism,
and the middle class which didn’t. In the case of the
middle class he was wholeheartedly in favor of free trade in
the usual sense of the term. Since parents at this level
were sophisticated and responsible choosers, consumer
sovereignty could here ride supreme. [27] The case of the
working class was different and it is summed up in Lowe’s
famous comment on the extension of the franchise to the
masses by the Reform Act of 1867. There was now an
urgent need, he insisted, “to compel our future masters to
learn their letters”. But this probably referred not
literally to learning their ABCs, for most people were
already doing that. The message pointed instead to the
correct uses of literacy especially in the sense of learning
right moral and social conduct. In a much earlier comment
written in Australia there appears a parallel argument:
“There are large numbers of children growing up in
ignorance, and if we do not educate them, other people will.
Large drafts of criminals are coming over here and they
will educate their children...” [28]
Lowe would have
been in full agreement with Nassau Senior’s advice to the
Newcastle Commission on Popular Education in 1861:
We may look
forward to the time when the labouring population may be
safely entrusted with the education of their children; but
no Protestant Country believes that this time has come, and
I see no reason to hope for it until generation after
generation has been better and better educated... until
England becomes what no country has ever yet become, an
Utopia inhabited by a self-educated and well-educated
labouring population.
VI. The
continuing legacy
It has been
suggested that the historical encroachment of a public (or
‘national’) system of government schools upon a previously
prevailing market
29
system has been
‘more concerned with morals than minds’. [29] Several
elites were certainly anxious to exert their own particular
form of influence on the bulk of the population. This paper
has argued that among British elites the Benthamites were
especially triumphant from the 1830s to at least 1870. And
although professing to be heralding a new social science
approach to legislation, their competitive zeal to obtain
positions of influence led them to the use of statistical
reasoning that, to another and later century, looks to have
all the marks of expedient propaganda.
At the end of
the twentieth century the British authorities are insisting
that parental choice and freedom is essential and must be
reestablished. According to McLean (1988), Britain’s
Education Act of 1988, shifted the role of central
government from provider and manager of public education to
legal arbiter and protector of consumer rights. For
instance, given a stipulated minimum in favor, parents in
England and Wales can now ‘opt out’ of the current local
education system by reorganizing their schools under
individual trusts run by managements of parent governors.
The trusts will be directly financed by the central
government. But this pressure to bypass local authorities
is seen by McLean, not as a new departure, but a
resuscitation of the ‘social contract’ philosophy of
governmental responsibility for social services that
prevailed between 1830 and 1870, a philosophy, according to
him, that derives largely from Bentham, J.S. Mill and Nassau
Senior.
McLean appears
wrong in some respects and right in others. He is mistaken
in linking the 19th century period to a social contract.
The masses appear to have been manipulated rather than
consulted by the 19th century Utilitarians; and
consultation, after all, is the essence of any social
contract. On the other hand McLean is undoubtedly correct
in drawing some parallel between 19th century Benthamism and
the structure of 1988 British
30
Education Act.
For despite its claim to be a movement for parental choice,
the initial four clauses of the Act place extraordinary, and
in some cases unprecedented, powers with the Secretary of
State.
The second
clause provides that for every maintained (government)
school the teaching (programs of study) shall follow
precisely that laid down by central government. This clause
fulfills the highest aspiration of the 19th century founder
of the English public system, James Kay (and of course his
disciple in Australia, William Wilkins). The first and
third clauses establish and describe a National Curriculum
such that government leaders will determine, for instance,
whether French is better than German, or the new maths is
better than the old, an arrangement that, in principle, was
close to the heart of John Stuart Mill. Bentham would have
been pleased that nowhere in the description of the National
Curriculum is there any mention of religious education.
Finally Robert Lowe would no doubt approve of the provision
whereby methods of assessment (examination) will follow
those laid down by the central government. He would have
been disappointed, however, by the absence of any ‘payment
by results’. In addition he (and Senior) might be somewhat
surprised that over a century after he had expressed the
need “to compel our future masters to learn their letters”,
government compulsion and provision still dominates.
Parents who,
under the new British legislation, opt out to have their
school controlled by themselves, will face many problems.
Meaningful choice and competition requires a positive
priced system, but the British authorities, just like the
19th century Benthamites, dislike it. The charging of fees
by maintained schools is forbidden under the 1988 Act. This
fact more than any brings into question McLean’s argument
that the British central government has now become a
protector of consumer rights.
31
Clearly many
aspects of Benthamism in education retain a firm hold. It
certainly seems to have ingrained itself into the very bones
of the British civil service from which successive
ministries of education receive constant advice and
guidance. This is not to say that there is at present any
obvious official desire to promulgate or implement Bentham’s
central pleasure/pain philosophy. What remains is the
machinery of Benthamism, the mechanisms of central
administration, curricula selection and examination. Many
writers in the field of public choice conclude that those
who benefit most from a government school system are the
suppliers of education since they have been granted the
privileges of protected incomes and jobs. The Benthamites
did not want free trade in working class education. But the
absence of internal free trade implies monopoly. And to the
economist at least, this is in fact the chief inherited
legacy.
The pattern of
British educational institutions, and those in other parts
of the world, might have been much different had the
ordinary public been acquainted with some of the elementary
propositions in the new economics of politics, especially
those which relate to the tendency of bureaucratic growth
and control. And things would no doubt have been
substantially different if the 19th century public had been
more aware of, and resistant to, flawed numerical reasoning
in the shape of the Benthamites’ Erroneous Calculation. Mr.
Gladstone recognized the flaw but didn’t pursue it further.
It remains a mystery why.
32
References
Barcan,
Alan. 1988. Two Centuries of Education in New South Wales,
Kensington, N.S.W. University Press.
Bentham,
Jeremy. 1818, Church of Englandism and its Catechism
examined, London: Effingham Wilson.
Birchenough,
Charles. 1927. History of Elementary. Education in
England and Wales. University Tutorial Press, London.
Bowring, J.
(ed.). 1962. The Works of Jeremy Bentham, 11 Vols.,
New York: Russell and Russell.
Buchanan,
James. M. 1978. “History of the Neglect of ‘Public Choice’
in the U.K.” in The Economics of Politics, Institute of
Economic Affairs, London.
Breton, A.
1974. The Economic Theory of Representative Government.
Chicago: Aldine.
Dicey, A.V.
1914. Law and Public Opinion in England, 2nd ed.
London: Macmillan.
Ekelund,
Robert B. and Robert F. Hebert. 1990. A History of
Economic Theory and Method, 3rd edition, New York:
McGraw Hill.
Griffiths,
D.C. 1957. Documents on the Establishment of Education in
New South Wales 1789-1880. Australian Council for
Educational Research, Melbourne.
Hyams, B.K.,
and B. Bessant. 1972. Schools for the People?
Camberwell: Longman, Australia.
Knight,
Ruth. 1966. Illiberal Liberal, Robert Lowe in New South
Wales, University of Melbourne, Melbourne.
33
McLean,
Martin. 1988. “The Conservative Education Policy in
Comparative Perspective: Return to an English Golden Age or
Harbinger of International Policy Change?” British
Journal of Educational Studies, Vol. XXXVI, No. 3, Oct.,
pp. 200-217.
Lowe,
Robert. 1868. Middle Class Education: Endowment or Free
Trade? London: Bush.
Mill, James.
1813. “Progress in Education”, Edinburgh Review.
Mill, J.S.
1962. On Liberty, Fontana edition. London: Collins.
. 1969. Principles of Political Economy, Ashley
edition, Augustus M. Kelly, New York.
Mueller,
Dennis C. 1989. Public Choice II, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Senior,
Nassau. 1861. Suggestions on Popular Education,
London: J. Murray.
Smith,
Frank. 1923. The Life and Work of Sir James
Kay-Shuttleworth, London: John Murray.
Turney, C.
1969. “William Wilkins - Australia’s Kay-Shuttleworth” in
Pioneers of Australian Education, ed. C.Turney, Sydney:
Sydney University Press.
Wardle,
David. 1971. Education and Society in Nineteenth Century
Nottingham, Cambridge University Press.
West, Edwin
G. 1971. Education and the State, Institute of Economic
Affairs, London.
1975.
Education and the Industrial Revolution, London:
Batsford.
34
Notes
Correspondence may be addressed to the author, Department of
Economics, Carleton University, Ottawa, Ontario, Canada K1S
5B6.
1. Buchanan
(1978), p. 4.
2. A. Breton
(1974), p. 124.
3. Breton,
(1974), p. 143.
4. Op.
Cit.
5. Bentham,
(1818), p. 10.
6. Nassau
Senior (1861).
7. Hansard
Vol. X, Cols. 139-166, July 1833.
8. Ibid.
9. Mueller
(1989), pp. 251, 252.
10. Report
of the Select Committee on Education, 1838, Paras 100 and
101.
11. The
following dialogue is reported in paragraphs 102-113 of the
1838 Select Committee Report.
12. Actually
the edition of the Manchester Report that was published in
the previous year had cautiously stated in a footnote with
very small print that the Committee ‘have not drawn the
inference which various commentators have attributed to
them, that this proportion of the youthful population
continued permanently destitute of schooling ... The
Committee possess no data for stating what number of
children have never enjoyed the advantage of attending
school’. (Italics in original) Report p. 18. Despite this
rider the Society persisted with the habit (subsequently
echoed in innumerable educational reports) that
35
the
difference between the numbers found by surveys to be in
schools and the census of the 5-15 year olds represented the
numbers who were ‘receiving no instruction in schools
whatsoever’ - to use its precise words (p. 3).
13. It is
interesting to speculate whether Gladstone, a man of
religious solemnity, was more swayed by the accusation of
poor quality (i.e. amoral) teaching rather than poor
quantity.
14. The
Report appears in the Journal of the Statistical Society,
London II 1839, 65-83.
15. Firm
opposition to the MSS methodology was expressed, however, by
members of the Bristol Statistical Society, Jnl. Stat. Soc.,
II (1839), p. 252 (esp. the footnote); The 1851 Census
special inquiry into education reported that working-class
children received on average four and two-thirds years of
schooling (West, 1975, p. 27).
16.
Forster’s Speech, 17 February 1870. See Volume 199 of
Hansard (third series), cols. 438-466.
17.
Parliamentary Debate, Education Bill, First Reading,
17th February 1870, Lord Montagu, Hansard Vol. 199
(third series).
18. By 1875
school accommodation in the public sector had grown to
2,871,000 places but only 1,678,000 pupils were in
attendance (Report for 1875).
19. David
Wardle, Education and Society in Nineteenth Century
Nottingham, 1971, p. 169.
20. In a
letter written in 1863 from England to a friend in
Australia, Lowe wrote: “It is curious that I never took any
lively interest in the question of popular education; and
yet both here and in Australia it has been forced upon me by
force of circumstances, which I could not control, and has
ended in both cases in involving my innocence and
inexperience in a tremendous row.” Knight, 1966, p. 84.
36
21. Knight
(1966) quotes a contemporary opinion that Lowe’s talents
matched those of his contemporary at Oxford, Mr. Gladstone,
and the latter, as shown above, seems to have been alert to
this kind of fallacy in statistical reporting.
22. D.C.
Griffiths, 1957.
23. Turney
(1969).
24. Frank
Smith, The Life and Work of Sir James Kay-Shuttleworth.
John Murray, London 1923.
25. Hansard
CLXXVII, 869.
26.
Birchenough (1927), p. 426.
27. The
arguments for the middle class are contained in Lowe’s book
Middle Class Education: Endowment or Free Trade? London
1868. Lowe reveals himself in this book to have been
influenced as much by Adam Smith as by Bentham.
28. Knight
(1966) p. 83-84 (italics supplied).
29. Katz
(1976).
37