The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
H.H. Chartrand
May 2002
Eugene F. Miller
Positivism, Historicism, and Political
Inquiry
American Political Science
Review
Volume 66, Issue
3
Sept. 1972,
796-817
Index
Epistemological Issues That Divide Positivism and
Historicism
The Revolt Against Positivism in the Philosophy of
Science
The Growth of Historicism in American Political
Science
Conclusion: Beyond Positivism and Historicism in
Political Inquiry
Conclusion: Beyond Positivism and
Historicism in Political Inquiry
This essay has examined the controversy between
behavioral and postbehavioral views of political inquiry in light of the larger
dispute in modern philosophy over the character of human knowledge. We have seen that while behavioralism
continues to be the dominant approach in American political science, its
epistemological foundations have been dealt a severe, if as yet unperceived,
blow by critics of positivism. It
remains uncertain whether or not positivism, in some modified form, will
continue to provide the guiding principles for political inquiry or, if not,
where the new epistemological and methodological principles will come from.
An increasing number of political
scientists, in formulating their opposition to behavioralism, are drawing upon
one variety or another of the antipositivist theory of knowledge that may be
called historicism. Yet the
capacity of this theory of knowledge to sustain a science of politics is, to say
the least, problematical. Its
principles lead to an epistemological relativism that renders questionable that
very possibility of science or philosophy as understood in the Western
tradition.
The conviction that neither positivism nor historicism
can provide a satisfactory basis for political inquiry lies behind the renewed
interest in traditional approaches to political philosophy. 58 Positivism and historicism have been
allied in their opposition to traditional political philosophy, whose goal was
knowledge of the good or just political order. Positivism bases its opposition on the
claim that value-judgments cannot be verified empirically, while historicism
insists that values are but individual or social creations, with no support in
nature. It is possible,
nonetheless, for proponents of positivism and historicism to support a
reappraisal of earlier thought; for on some points of epistemology, each of
these positions finds itself allied with traditional political philosophy in
opposition to the other. Historicism agrees with tradition, in
opposition to positivism, that evaluation is essential to understanding and, in
particular, that the human things cannot be understood apart from judgments of
good and bad. Conse-
58. Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin have been the
most influential figures in the effort to restore political philosophy. For Strauss, see especially Natural
Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), What is
Political Philosophy? (Glencoe, Ill.:Free Press, 1959), The City and Man
(Chicago: Rand McNally, 1964), “Relativism” in Relativism and the Study
of Man, ed. Helmut Schoeck and James W. Wiggins (Princeton: D. Van
Nostrand, 1961), pp. 135-157, and “Philosophy as Rigorous Science and Political
Philosophy,” Interpretation, 2 (Summer, 1971), 1-9. For Voegelin, see especially The New
Science of Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952); Order
and History, 3 vols. (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press,
1956-1957); and Anamnesis (Munich: Piper, 1966). A fourth and final volume of Order and
History is in preparation. For
useful accounts of Voegelin’s thought, see Gregor Sebba, “Order and Disorders of
the Soul: Eric Voegelin’s Philosophy of History,” Southern Review, 3, New
Series (Spring, 1967), 282-310; William C. Havard, “The Changing Pattern of
Voegelin’s Conception of History and Consciousness,” Southern Review, 7,
New Series (January, 1971), 49-67; Dante Germino, “Eric Voegelin’s
Anamnesis,” Southern Review, 7 New Series (January, 1971), 68-88; and
Ellis Sandoz, “The Foundations of Voegelin’s Political Theory,” Political
Science Reviewer, 1 (FaIl, 1971), 30-73.
Both Strauss and Voegelin have defended political
philosophy against the positivist critique. Strauss has gone on to identify
historicism, rather than positivism, as the dominant force in contemporary
thought and the leading contemporary opponent of political philosophy. His own work in classical political
philosophy may properly be seen as a rebuttal of both the theoretical
historicism of Hegel, which claims that political philosophy as quest for
knowledge has been superseded by complete knowledge of the historical whole, and
the relativistic historicism of Heidegger, which holds that views of the good
must always be relative to groundless choice or to a dispensation of fate. Voegelin’s stand with respect to
historicism has not been as clear-cut as Strauss’s although, he, too, is sharply
critical of the thought of Heidegger as well as that of Hegel. In formulating his own position, Voegelin
has drawn in some measure from the historicist tradition. He has held, for example, that political
science in its full grandeur is philosophy of history and that the conditions of
a civilization set limits to the capacity of its members to discern the truth
about reality. Stanley Rosen has
drawn attention to these aspects of Voegelin’s thought in his review of Order
and History in Review of Metaphysics, 12 (December, 1958), 257-276.
I would contend, however, that the
thrust of Voegelin’s thought is away from historicism, at least in the sense of
epistemological relativism. Of
decisive importance is his view that man may, by the analysis of the experience
of existence, grasp the truth about the order of being and, in light of this
knowledge, rank the symbolic representations of reality that various
civilizations have produced. There
are, of course, other important differences between Strauss and Voegelin, such
as their disagreement as to whether Political philosophy can or should be
guided by revelation. Political
theory or philosophy as Voegelin conceives it would probably be looked upon by
Strauss as a type of political theology.
816
quently, the scientific method, as reconstructed by
positivism, cannot disclose what is human about man and society. Positivism agrees with tradition, in
opposition to relativistic epistemologies, that reliable knowledge of nature is
possible in at least some areas. The traditional view had been that the
mind can grasp nature as it is and, on the basis of such knowledge, apprehend
what ought to be. Positivism came
to deny that there can be genuine knowledge of what is good and just, or of the
standards (“ideals,” “values”) that ought to guide political choice, but it
continued to insist on the possibility of knowing the factual world as it is.
By questioning the possibility of
objective knowledge of both facts and values, historicism takes a radical step
beyond positivism as well as beyond traditonal theories of knowledge. It undercuts both positivistic approaches
to political science and traditional political philosophy. Whatever their shortcomings might have
been, traditional approaches to political philosophy, especially the ancient or
classical approaches, encouraged a discriminating study of man and politics
while preserving the possibility of reliable knowledge. The study of political philosophy in its
traditional forms may thus contribute to the formulation of a mode of political
inquiry that will do justice to the proper aspirations of positivism and
historicism while avoiding their characteristic pitfalls.
In discussing the ‘postbehavioral revolution” in
political science, David Easton takes note of each of the positions that I have
described. I would argue, however,
that there are two fundamental errors in
59.
60.
61. I have examined the development of Easton’s thought,
including his somewhat ambiguous position with respect to historicism, in “David
Easton’s Political Theory,” Political Science Reviewer, 1 (Fall, 1971),
184-235. It is noteworthy that
Ludwig von Bertalanify, the leading figure in the establishment of general
system theory, has developed a “perspectivistic” theory of knowledge, which
adopts some of the central premises of historicism but seeks to preserve, in a
limited sense, the possibility of absolute knowledge of reality. See Bertalanffy’s “An Essay on the
Relativity of Categories,” General Systems, 7 (1962), 71-83
817