The Competitiveness of Nations

in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy

H.H. Chartrand

May 2002

AAP Homepage

Eugene F. Miller

Positivism, Historicism, and Political Inquiry (Web 2)

American Political Science Review

Volume 66, Issue 3

Sept. 1972, 796-817

Index

Introduction [Web 1]

Epistemological Issues That Divide Positivism and Historicism

The Revolt Against Positivism in the Philosophy of Science [Web 2]

The Growth of Historicism in American Political Science [Web 3]

Conclusion: Beyond Positivism and Historicism in Political Inquiry [Web 4]

 

The Revolt Against Positivism in the Philosophy of Science

Thus far we have been concerned with the most general issues of epistemology that have arisen in the struggle between positivism and historicism during the past century.  It is in light of this struggle over epistemological principles, I believe, that we must understand the origin and significance of the cleavage that has developed recently within the philosophy of science regarding the nature of scientific inquiry.  Logi-

13.  See Mannheim’s essay entitled “On the Interpretation of Weltanschauung,’” in Essays on the Sociology of Knowledge, pp. 33-83; and Hodges, Wilhelm Dilthey, pp. 11-36, 68-87.  For a valuable collection of Mannheim’s writings that contains a lengthy and penetrating introduction to his thought, see Kurt H. Wolff, ed., From Karl Mannheim (New York: Oxford University Press, 1971).

801

cal positivism was formulated in the 1920s with the express aim of remaking philosophy in conformity with what was presumed to be the logic and epistemology of modern natural science.  For the next three decades the most influential statements on the nature of science came from members of the Vienna Circle or their followers.  From the beginning there were those, such as Karl Popper, who dissented at least in part from the position of the logical positivists, but the positivistic interpretation of scientific inquiry dominated philosophy of science until recently.  In the 1950s, however, there developed substantial opposition to their interpretation; and by the mid-1960s a philosopher of science, Dudley Shapere, could describe the developments in his field as follows:

In the past decade, a revolution - or at least a rebellion - has occurred in the philosophy of science.  Views have been advanced which claim to be radically new not only in their doctrines about science and its evolution and structure, but also in their conceptions of the methods appropriate to solving the problems of the philosophy of science, and even as to what those problems themselves are. 13

As Shapere goes on to indicate, this revolution in the philosophy of science is directed against the view of science associated with logical positivism or logical empiricism.  But what alternative epistemological position did the antipositivists adopt?  I shall argue that their theory of knowledge is fundamentally historicist.  The recent developments in the philosophy of science must be understood in light of the century-long struggle between positivism and historicism.  Positivism, having steadily lost ground in the field of philosophy generally, came under siege finally in its last stronghold, the philosophy of science.  I shall attempt to establish the historicist nature of the antipositivist revolt in the philosophy of science by examining the two principal sources of influence upon it: (1) developments in philosophy that are associated with the later work of Wittgenstein, and (2) the new interpretation of the history of science.

Ludwig Wittgenstein entered Cambridge in 1912 to study philosophy under Bertrand Russell, who had argued that a new and more rigorous language was needed for discussing the world of nature.  Russell envisioned a scientific language whose basic propositions would each denote some object of sense experience, some atomic fact, and whose syntax would conform to the new rules of mathematical logic that he and Whitehead had worked out in Principia Mathematica.  Wittgenstein developed a position much like Russell’s in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.  This work, which was completed in 1918 and published a few years later in both German and English, sets forth a theory of language that was to influence profoundly the members of the Vienna Circle.  Wittgenstein agrees with Russell that the reform of philosophy will require a restructuring of language according to the logic of the Principia.  This language will be built from elementary propositions, whose signs correspond to objects in the real world.  All complex significant propositions will be constructed by logical operations from these elementary propositions and depend on them for their truth or falsity.

Two crucial assumptions underlie Wittgenstein’s early position.  First, he holds that there is but one ideal language into which philosophical discourse must be cast, but he is unwilling to argue that the logical form of his ideal language has a necessary basis in reason or in nature.  Indeed, the ground of language cannot be discussed meaningfully because all language about language is merely tautologous.  Second, he holds that an unambiguous correspondence can be established between the unit-propositions of the ideal language and the “atomic facts” that are given in experience.  These propositions are said to derive their meaning from the units of experience to which they correspond.

These two assumptions, and with them Wittgenstein’s entire position, are obviously vulnerable to attack.  If there is no rational or onto-logical ground for the particular linguistic structure that he advances, then what basis is there for assigning it a privileged or ideal status?  The choice of one language rather than another, insofar as it is not simply arbitrary, might arise from convention or agreement. Furthermore, one may doubt that experience as given falls neatly into elementary units which convey an unambiguous meaning.  It might be that experience is always open to several possible meanings and that our choice of a language, or a set of concepts, predetermines the particular meaning that we will assign to experience.

By the early 1930s Wittgenstein had come to question his own early views and, indeed, to argue explicitly against them on these very grounds.  He gives up the notion that factual language must have a uniform structure, modelled on the language of logic.  He moves to the view that there are many alternative languages, or “language games,” including, for example, the simple language of a child, the ordinary

13. “Meaning and Scientific Change,” in Robert G. Colodny, ed., Mind and Cosmos (Pittsburgh; University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966), pp. 41-42.

802

language of everyday life, and the sign-systems of logic and mathematics.  Furthermore, Wittgenstein gives up the theory that language is an exact picture of reality, deriving its meaning from the experience that it depicts.  The meaning of words is determined not by private experiences, which in principle are always open to many possible interpretations, but by conventional usage.  In effect, he reverses his original view that language receives its meaning from experience and takes the position that experience receives its meaning from language.  As many commentators have pointed out, the concepts of language function for the later Wittgenstein in much the same way as the a priori categories of the mind function for Kant, that is, they determine the construction of meaningful objects from unformed experience.  We know the world only as ordered and articulated by a language; and the only facts or objects belonging to this world are those which our language recognizes. 14

Wittgenstein moved in his intellectual development from a position that is favorable to positivism to one that is fundamentally historicist.  Language, he came to hold, cannot be regarded as an isolated structure, separate from other expressions of human life and action.  Our linguistic activities are part of a total cultural-linguistic tradition, or “form of life,” that serves as the basis of society.  In his later period Wittgenstein treated the various forms of life which have developed historically as irreducible ultimates, beyond which reasoning and inquiry cannot penetrate: “What has to be accepted, the given, is - so one could say - forms of life.” 15  Human thought is relative to a language and to concepts which themselves depend on the given form of life.  There is no possibility of going beyond or transcending in any meaningful way the various forms of life.  As Stanley Rosen has pointed out, Wittgenstein’s later position resembles the view of the German historicists that “life” is at the bottom of the Weltanschauungen that emerge from the historical process and determine the character of human thought:

What it means to think, and hence to mean, is decided within the context of an already understood language, more specifically a language in a given historical stage, an all-encompassing horizon of intentions which must be accepted as the basis for analysis or use-specification - a Lebensform.  The Lebensform is Wittgenstein’s equivalent to the nineteenth-century conception of Weltanschauung, a word he uses once to ask whether it is not what “earmarks the form of account we give, the way we look at things.”  The inaccessibility of the Lebensform to theoretical evaluation replaces the earlier impossibility of speaking about logical form.  In the present case, the Lebensform is equivalent to the language or language game, that is, to custom or use.  In both stages of his teaching, Wittgenstein denies the possibility of a logos or theoretical account of speech, in both cases because he identifies the horizon of speech as that about which one must remain silent.  Formerly, however, one had to remain silent about logical form, or what may be called the natural order of the world.  Now one must be silent about the foundations - because there is no natural order of the world.  There is no physis, so far as philosophy is concerned, but only nomos. 16

A second major influence shaping the anti-positivist revolution in the philosophy of science has been the new interpretation of the history of science.  It seems likely that philosophers of science turned to history for guidance about the nature of science after they came to accept the radical historicity of the human mind and thus to doubt that science has an absolute basis in epistemology or logic.  By the early 1930s the Polish logician Kasimir Ajdukiewicz had concluded, on the basis of his historicist theory of language, that science itself must be understood in terms of history. 17  Ajdukiewicz held that all knowledge, including systems of science, embodies concepts that are part of a language and have meaning only when used according to the rules of that language.  The commitment to

14. For Wittgenstein’s early position, see his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. C. K. Ogden (London: Kegan Paul, 1922).  His later views are developed principally in two posthumous works, Philosophical investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (New York: Macmillan, 1953) and Preliminary Studies for the “Philosophical Investigations”: Generally Known as the Blue and Brown Books (New York: Harper, 1958).  For studies of Wittgenstein’s thought, see, in addition to Urmson’s Philosophical Analysis, David Pole, The Later Philosophy of Wittgenstein (London: Athlone Press, 1958); Ernst K. Specht, The Foundations of Wittgenstein’s Late Philosophy, trans. D. E. Walford (New York: Barnes and Noble, 1969); and E. D. Klemke, ed., Essays on Wittgenstein (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1971).  It should be noted that the constructivist theory of language is by no means exclusive to Wittgenstein.  Similar views were developed at about the same time by Cassirer and by the Polish logician Kasimir Ajdukiewicz, whom I discuss later.  Among social scientists, Edward Sapir and Benjamin Lee Whorf developed the influential hypothesis that all views of reality are determined in a largely unconscious manner by the linguistic systems of groups or cultures.  See Max Black, “Linguistic Relativity: The Views of Benjamin Lee Whorf,” Philosophical Review, 68 (April, 1959), 228-238.

15. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, p. 226.

16. Rosen, Nihilism, p. 9.

17. See Ajdukiewicz, “The Scientific World-Perspective,” in Herbert Feigl and Wilfrid Sellars, eds., Readings in Philosophical Analysis (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1949), pp. 182-188.

803 Index

a language and to its conceptual apparatus determines the interpretation that we will place on the data of experience.  Consequently, there are a variety of “world-perspectives,” corresponding to the various linguistic and conceptual systems, but never a complete “world-picture.”  Judgments of truth or falsity are always relative to a particular world-perspective.  Even the epistemologist is unable to decide between the competing claims of different world-perspectives, for he also is imprisoned in a conceptual apparatus which dictates his judgments.  Ajdukiewicz thus recommends that the epistemologist give up his effort to establish criteria for right thinking about the world and turn his attention instead to “the history of science”:

He should give his attention to the changes which occur in the conceptual apparatus of science and in the corresponding world-perspectives, and should seek to ascertain the motives which bring these changes about.  Perhaps this sequence of world-perspectives permits of being conceived as a goal-directed process which advances as though someone consciously wished to achieve the goal by means of the sequence.  The task involved in such a conception of the history of science constitutes the sound kernel of the geisteswissenschaftlichen (culture-theoretical) understanding of the evolution of science. 18

Contemporary historians of science, proceeding from historicist assumptions that are very close to those of Ajdukiewicz, consider and reject the suggestion that the history of science might be intelligible as a goal-directed process.  The basic document for understanding the new interpretation of the history of science is Thomas Kuhn’s monograph, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 18  Kuhn holds that the common textbook image of science has been called into question by recent studies in the history of science; and his purpose is to make explicit the decisive transformation in the image of science that these historical studies require.  What Kuhn calls the textbook image of science is, in effect, the one that has traditionally been associated with positivism.  It holds that scientific development takes place incrementally or cumulatively within an open community.  As knowledge accumulates, it is incorporated into ever more inclusive theories, which are accepted or rejected according to their ability to withstand empirical testing.  This process of development-by-accumulation is seen to move steadily toward the ultimate goal of a true and objective account of nature.  Kuhn, by contrast, describes the evolution of science in much the same way that the historicist describes the historical process, namely, as a mere sequence of epochs, each with its distinctive worldview, no one of which can claim to represent a closer approximation to the truth about the whole than any other.

In Kuhn’s account, a scientific community, during a period of “normal science,” is governed by a pervasive “paradigm.”  Kuhn’s definitions of “paradigm” and his descriptions of its influence are somewhat vague and ambiguous, but the similarity of this concept to the older notion of Weltanschauung is unmistakable.  The paradigm is a scientific community’s “historical perspective,” its “way of seeing the world,” its comprehensive set of beliefs and commitments - conceptual, theoretical, instrumental, methodological, and even “quasi-metaphysical.”  The paradigm guides and determines the selection of problems, the evaluation of data, and the acceptance of hypotheses and theories.  By taking first principles for granted in this manner, “normal scientists” are able to explore a small range of relatively esoteric problems in great depth and detail, but the price, Kuhn emphasizes, is a high degree of rigidity and narrowness within the scientific community itself.  Young scientists are trained to accept the paradigm uncritically by textbooks that ignore or depreciate alternative outlooks.  Problems are avoided, even socially relevant ones, if they cannot be stated in terms of the conceptual and instrumental tools that the paradigm supplies.  Discoveries or inventions that would call the paradigm into question are suppressed.  Scientists with dissenting views are read out of the profession and their work is ignored.

By contrast to the positivistic understanding of scientific development, which stresses incremental or cumulative progress, Kuhn describes the historical pattern of scientific development as a noncumulative shift from one paradigm to another.  He emphasizes that a drastic change in the character of scientific inquiry comes about when one paradigm or set of presuppositions is abandoned and another takes its place.  Scientists follow new criteria in selecting problems, interpreting data, and assessing theories.  The old criteria and the body of knowledge established through them are, in effect, given up

18. Ajdukiewicz, p. 188.

19. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970).  Dudley Shapere has examined this work and called attention to its relativistic implications in Philosophical Review, 73 (July, 1964), 383-394.  Kuhn replies to Shapere and other critics in a “Postscript” to the second edition of his work.  He reaffirms that a theory cannot be true in the sense of accounting for nature or reality as it is (p. 206).

804

rather than being incorporated into the new stage.

Kuhn’s historicism comes clearly into view in his attempt to explain why these “scientific revolutions” occur.  If there is to be a scientific revolution, scientists must become aware of some anomalous fact that the present paradigm cannot explain.  In this time of crisis for normal science, new theories are invented to account for the anomaly, one of which eventually gains wide acceptance as the core of a new paradigm.  It would be a mistake, however, to say that theories or paradigms are accepted or rejected in terms of their congruence with empirical data.  To those who hold that scientific theories are rejected when they are falsified or contradicted by experience, Kuhn replies that the paradigm shapes observation itself, reducing the likelihood that scientists will even perceive data that are contrary to expectations that the paradigm itself engenders.  Also, facts are always present that do not “fit” the accepted theory, but these are seldom regarded as serious anomalies during periods of normal science.  To those who hold that new theories are accepted when they are confirmed by experience, Kuhn replies that it is always possible to place more than one theoretical construction upon a given collection of data.  Clearly there are forces at work in scientific revolutions that are more fundamental than the confrontation of the scientist with the data of experience.  Kuhn compares paradigm shifts to the perceptual transformations that occur when one looks at the ambiguous pictures used in gestalt experiments.  The perceptual data themselves are not decisive in the mind’s interpretation of the data.  It would be a mistake also to believe that paradigms are accepted or rejected on rational or logical grounds.  Inasmuch as paradigms are “incommensurable,” they cannot be judged by common criteria.  In short, a change in paradigms cannot be explained as a deliberate choice, based on either empirical or rational grounds.  In the final analysis, “[a]n apparently arbitrary element, compounded of personal and historical accident, is always a formative ingredient of the beliefs espoused by a given scientific community at a given time.” 20 What is arbitrary is, of course, inexplicable.

Let us recall Ajdukiewicz’s suggestion that the history of science might be intelligible as a goal-directed process.  Ajdukiewicz had obviously been reluctant to break completely with the positivistic belief in the progressive character of scientific development.  Kuhn admits that within a period of normal science there can be progress, judging by the criteria of the prevailing paradigm, toward the solution of technical problems or puzzles.  He doubts, however, that the succession of changes from one paradigm to another has brought scientists closer to the truth about nature.  He asks: “Does it really help to imagine that there is some one full, objective, true account of nature and that the proper measure of scientific achievement is the extent to which it brings us closer to that ultimate goal?” 21  Kuhn doubts that this question can be answered affirmatively; and the reason for his doubts is clear.  Just as the older historicists could admit no standpoint outside of a particular worldview for grasping the truth about nature or history, Kuhn can admit no standpoint outside a particular paradigm.  There is no trans-paradigmatic basis for assessing the truth of the competing paradigms or for apprehending nature as it is.  It is no wonder that he tells us that the decision for a particular paradigm “can only be made on faith.” 22

Having examined the sources of the contemporary revolt against positivism in the philosophy of science, let us look briefly at the position of those philosophers who are identified with this revolt.  Among the leaders are Stephen Toulmin, Michael Scriven, Norwood R. Hanson, Paul Feyerabend, and, in social science, Peter Winch.  The grounds of their opposition to the positivist view of science have been treated in detail by Dudley Shapere, who, while critical of their work, nonetheless recognizes its fundamental importance. 23  It is clear from Sha-

20. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, p. 4.

21. Kuhn, p. 171.

22. Kuhn, p. 158.

23. Shapere, “Meaning and Scientific Change,” pp. 41-85.  In this essay, Shapere focuses particularly on the writings of Paul Feyerabend, which are cited extensively, along with pertinent writings by other anti-positivists, in the footnotes.  For other accounts of this cleavage, along with useful bibliographical information, see Israel Scheffler, Science and Subjectivity (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1967); Achinstein and Barker, eds., The Legacy of Logical Positivism; Peter Achinstein, Concepts of Science (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1968); Edward MacKinnon, S. J., “Epistemological Problems in the Philosophy of Science, I, II,” Review of Metaphysics, 22 (September and December, 1968), 113-137, 329-358; and Carl R. Kordig, “The Theory-Ladenness of Observation,” Review of Metaphysics, 24 (March, 1971), 448-484.  There are several excellent series in which one may survey recent debate over the nature of science, including Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh Series in the Philosophy of Science, and Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science.  The most recent volume of the Minnesota Studies, Analyses of Theories and Methods of Physics and Psychology, ed. Michael Radner and Stephen Winokur (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1970), contains several articles on theory that take note of recent controversy.

805

pere’s account that the antipositivist position has much in common with the philosophical views of the later Wittgenstein and with views of the history of science such as Kuhn’s.  Their overall interpretation of science is fundamentally historicist, or, as Shapere prefers to say, relativistic.  Shapere identifies as the chief substantive characteristic of the antipositivist reaction “the view that, fundamental to scientific investigation and development, there are certain very pervasive sorts of presuppositions” which vary from one scientific theory or tradition to another.  We are reminded of the view that all thought and experience are determined by a Weltanschauung (Dilthey, Mannheim) or by the customary language and Lebensform (Wittgenstein) or by a paradigm (Kuhn).  Shapere identifies three distinctive features of the new philosophy of science that follow from this principle.  First is “a presupposition theory of meaning,” according to which the meanings of all scientific terms, whether factual or theoretical, are determined by the underlying paradigm or theory or set of presuppositions.  This theory of meaning contradicts the positivist thesis that the meaning of scientific terms is derived directly or indirectly from experience and, indeed, that experience is the absolute ground by which the meaningfulness of any statement about the world must be judged.  This presupposition theory of meaning is based, of course, on the assumption that presuppositions or theories will inevitably shape perception itself and determine what will count as a fact.  A second feature of antipositivist philosophy of science is : a presupposition theory of problems that will define the domain of scientific inquiry, and of what can count as an explanation in answer to those problems.”  By holding that the very character of explanation varies from one context to another, the antipositivists take issue with the positivist view that all scientific explanation must conform to the same formal model, namely, the “deductive-nomological” model, according to which there can be no explanation without a general law.  In the third place, the antipositivists adopt “a presupposition theory of the relevance of facts to theory, of the degree of relevance (i.e., of the relative importance of different facts), and, generally, of the relative acceptability or unacceptability of different scientific conclusions (laws, theories, predictions).”  This thesis contradicts the positivist view that all scientific theory must be tested against experience according to some standard principle of verifiability, confirmability, or falsifiability.

We see that the antipositivist movement in the philosophy of science has reinterpreted modern science, including natural science, in light of the characteristic assumptions of historicism.  It suggests that the guiding presuppositions of scientific inquiry are variable from one context to another and are ultimately arbitrary inasmuch as they have no absolute basis in reason or experience.  Even some opponents of this movement have come to agree with certain of its basic assumptions, for example, the assumption that modern science rests on arbitrary presuppositions. 24  Yet if modern science rests on presuppositions that are finally arbitrary, one must wonder if there is any basis whatever for defending it as superior in principle to the modes of inquiry that its proponents have, from the outset, repudiated.

Index

Previous Page

Next Page

AAP Homepage