The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
F.
A. von Hayek
Economics and Knowledge
1
Scientism and the Study of
Society
Content |
|
XI – “Purposive” Social
Formations
XII – “Conscious” Direction and the
Growth of Reason [HHC: titles added to numbered items] |
Economica, New Series,
11 (41 Feb. 1944, 27-39. |
XI – “Purposive” Social
Formations
IN the concluding portions of this
article we have to consider certain practical attitudes which spring from the
theoretical views already discussed. Their most characteristic common feature
is a direct result of the inability, caused by the lack of a cormpositive theory
of social phenomena, to grasp how the independent action of many men can produce
coherent wholes, persistent structures of relationships which serve important
human purposes without having been designed for that end. This produces a “pragmatic”
2 interpretation of social institutions which treats all
social structures which serve human purposes as the result of deliberate design
and denies the possibility of an orderly or purposeful arrangement in anything
which is not thus constructed.
This view receives strong support
from the fear of employing any anthropomorphic conceptions, so characteristic of
the scientistic attitude. This fear
has produced an almost complete ban on the use of the concept of “purpose” in
the discussion of spontaneous social growths, and it often drives positivists
into an error similar to that they wish to avoid: having learnt that it is
erroneous to regard everything that behaves in an apparently purposive manner as
created by a designing mind, they are led to believe that no result of the
action of many men can show order or serve a useful purpose unless it is the
result of deliberate design. They
are thus driven back to a view which, is essentially the same as that which,
till the eighteenth century, made man think of language or the family as having
been “invented” or the state having been created by an explicit social contract,
and in opposition to which the compositive theories of social structures were
developed.
As the terms of ordinary language
are somewhat misleading, it is necessary to move with great care in any
discussion of the “purposive” character of spontaneous social formations. The risk of being lured into an
illegitimate anthropomorphic use of the term purpose is as great as that of
denying that the term purpose in this connection designates something of
importance. In its strict original
meaning “purpose” indeed presupposes an acting person deliberately aiming at a
result. The same, however, as we
have seen before, 3 is true of other concepts like “law” or “organization”,
which we have nevertheless been constrained, by the lack of other suitable
terms, to adopt for scientific use in a non-anthropomorphic sense. In the same way we may find the term
“purpose” indispensable in a carefully defined sense.
The character of the problem may
usefully first be described in the words of an eminent contemporary philosopher
who, though elsewhere, in the strict positivist manner, he declares that “the
concept of purpose must be entirely excluded from the scientific treatment of
the phenomena of life”, yet admits the existence of “a general principle which
proves frequently valid in psychology and biology and also elsewhere: namely
that the result “of unconscious or instinctive processes is frequently exactly
the same as would have arisen from rational calculation”
4
This
states one aspect of the problem very clearly: namely, that a result, if it were
deliberately aimed at, could be achieved only in a limited number of ways, and
that it is actually achieved by one of those methods, although nobody has
consciously aimed at it. But it
still
1.
The first two parts of this article appeared
in Economica for August, 1942, and February, 1943.
2.
On this concept of the “pragmatic”
interpretation of social institutions as for the whole of this section compare
Carl Menger, Untersuchungen über die Methode der Sozialwissenschaften,
1883 (L.S.E. reprint 1933), book II, chapter 2, which is still the most
comprehensive and most careful survey known to me of the problems here
discussed.
3. See Part I of this article, Economica, August, 1942, p. 721.
4. Cf
lvi. Schlick, Fragen der Ethik, Vienna, 1930, p. 72.
27
leaves open the question why the
particular result which is brought about in this manner should be regarded as
distinguished above others as desirable and therefore deserve to be described as
the “purpose”.
If we survey the different fields in
which we are constantly tempted to describe phenomena as “purposive” though they
are not directed by a conscious mind, it becomes rapidly clear that the “end” or
“purpose” they are said to serve is always the preservation of a “whole”, of a
persistent structure of relationships, whose existence we have come to take for
granted before we understood the nature of the mechanism which holds the parts
together. The most familiar
instances of such wholes are the biological organisms. Here the conception of the “function” of
an organ as an essential condition for the persistence of the whole has proved
to be of the greatest heuristic value. It is easily seen how paralysing an
effect on research it would have had if the scientific prejudice had effectively
banned the use of all teleological concepts in biology and, e.g., prevented the
discoverer of a new organ from immediately asking what “purpose” or “function”
it serves. 1
Though in the social sphere we meet
phenomena which in this respect raise analogous problems, it is, of course,
dangerous to describe them for that reason as organisms. The limited analogy provides as such no
answer to the common problem, and the loan of an alien term tends to obscure the
equally important differences. We
need not labour here the now familiar facts that the social wholes, unlike the
biological organisms, are not given to us as natural units, fixed complexes
which ordinary experience shows us to belong together, but are recognisable only
by a process of mental reconstruction; or that the parts of the social wholes,
unlike those of a true organism, can exist away from their particular place in
the whole and are to a large extent mobile and exchangeable. Yet, though we must avoid overworking the
analogy, certain general considerations apply equally in both cases. As in the biological organisms so in
spontaneous social formations we often observe the parts to move as if their
purpose were the preservation of the wholes. We find again and again that if it
were somebody’s deliberate aim to preserve the structure of those wholes, and if
he had the knowledge and the power to do so, he would have to do it by causing
precisely those movements which in fact are taking place without any such
conscious direction.
In the social sphere these
spontaneous movements which preserve a certain structural connection between the
parts are, moreover, connected in a special way with our individual purposes:
the social wholes which are thus maintained are the condition for the
achievement of many of the things we individually aim at, the environment which
makes it possible even to conceive of most of our individual desires and which
gives us the power to achieve them.
There is nothing more mysterious in
the fact that, e.g., money or the price system enable man to achieve things
which he desires, although they were not designed for that purpose, and hardly
could have been consciously designed before that growth of civilisation which
they made possible, than that, unless man had tumbled upon these devices, he
would not have achieved the powers he has gained. The facts to which we refer when we speak
of “purposive” forces being here at work are the same as those which create the
persistent social structures which we have come to take for granted and which
form the condition of our existence. The spontaneously grown institutions are
“useful” because they were the conditions on which the further development of
man was based - which gave him the powers which he used. If in the form in which Adam Smith put it
the phrase that man in society “constantly promotes ends which are no part of
his intention” has become the constant source of irritation of the
scientistically-minded, it describes nevertheless the central problem of the
social sciences. As it was put a
hundred years after Smith by Carl Menger, who did more than any other writer to
carry beyond Smith the elucidation of the meaning of this phrase, the question
“how it is possible that institutions which serve the common welfare and are
most important for its advancement can arise without a common will aiming at
their creation” is still “the significant, perhaps the most significant, problem
of the social sciences.”
2
1. On the use of teleological concepts in biology compare
the careful discussion in J. H. Woodger, Biological Principles, 1929, particularly the section
on “Teleology and Causation “, pp. 429-455 ; also the earlier
discussion in the same work (p. 291)
on the so-called “scientific habit of thought’s causing the “scandal”
of biologists not taking organisation seriously and “in their haste to become
physicists, neglecting their business.”
2. Untersuchungen, etc.,
p. 163 {HHC: extensive German footnote not
reproduced} [If for the ambiguous and
somewhat question-begging term “social welfare” we substitute in this statement
“institutions which are necessary conditions for the achievement of man’s
conscious purposes” it is hardly saying too much that the way in which such
“purposive wholes “are formed and preserved is the specific problem of social
theory, just as the existence and persistence of organisms is the problem of
biology.]
HHC:
[bracketed] displayed on page 29 of
original.
That the nature and even the
existence of this problem is still so little recognised’ is closely connected
with a common confusion about what we mean when we say that human institutions
are made by man. Though in a sense
man-made, i.e., entirely the result of human actions, they may yet not be
designed, not be the intended product of these actions. The term institution itself is rather
misleading in this respect, as it suggests something deliberately instituted.
It would probably be better if this
term were confined to particular contrivances, like particular laws and
organisations, which have been created for a specific purpose, and if a more
neutral term like “formations” (in a sense similar to that in which the
geologists use it, and, corresponding to the German Gebilde) could be
used for those phenomena, which, like money or language, have not been so
created.
From the belief that nothing which
has not been consciously designed can be useful or even essential to the
achievement of human purposes, it is an easy transition to the belief that since
all “institutions” have been made by man, we must have complete power to
refashion them in any way we desire.
2 But, though this conclusion at first sounds like a
self-evident commonplace, it is, in fact, a complete non sequitur, based
on the equivocal use of the term “institution”. It would be valid only if all the
“purposive” formations were the result of design. But phenomena like language or the
market, money or morals, are not real artifacts, products of deliberate
creation. 3 Not only have they not been designed by any mind, but
they are also preserved by, and depend for their functioning on, the actions of
people who are not guided by the desire to keep them in existence. And as they are not due to design but
rest on individual actions which we do not now control, we can at least not take
it for granted that we can improve upon, or even equal, their performance by any
organisation which relies on the deliberate control of the movements of its
parts. In so far as we learn to
understand the spontaneous forces, we may hope to use them and modify their
operations by proper adjustment of the institutions which form part of the
larger process. But there is all
the difference between thus utilising and influencing spontaneous processes and
an attempt to replace them by a mechanism relying on conscious
control.
We flatter ourselves undeservedly if
we represent human civilisation as entirely the product of conscious reason or
as the product of human design, or when we assume that it is necessarily in our
power deliberately to re-create or to maintain what we have built without
knowing what we were doing. Though
our civiisation is the result of a cumulation of individual knowledge, it is not
by the explicit or conscious combination of all this knowledge in any individual
brain, but by its embodiment in symbols which we use without understanding them,
in habits and institutions, tools and concepts,
4 that man in society is constantly
able to profit from a body of knowledge neither he nor any other man completely
possesses. Many of the greatest
things man has achieved are not the result of consciously directed thought, and
still less the product of a deliberately co-ordinated effort of many
individuals, but of a process in
1.
How much intellectual progress has been
obstructed here by political passions is readily seen when we compare the
discussion of the problem in the economic and political science with, say, the
study of language where, what in the former is still disputed, is a commonplace
nobody dreams of questioning.
2.
Menger speaks in this connection rightly of
“a pragmatism which, against the wishes of its representatives, leads inevitably
to socialism.” (Untersuchungen,
etc., p. 208.) To-day this view is most
frequently found in the writings of the American “Institutionalists” of which
the following (taken from Professor W. H. Hamilton’s article on “Institution” in
the Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, Vol. VIII, pp. 87-89) is a good
example: “The tangled thing called capitalism was never created by design or cut
to a blueprint; but now that it is here, contemporary schoolmen have
intellectualised it into a purposive and self-regulating instrument of general
welfare”. From this it is only a
few steps to the demand “that order and direction should be imposed upon an
unruly society.”
3.
A typical example of the treatment of social
institutions as if they were true artifacts, in a characteristic scientistic
setting, is provided by J. Mayer, Social Science Principles in the Light of
Scientific Method, Durham, N. C., 5945, p. so, where society is explicitly
“designated as an ‘artificial creation’, much as an automobile or steel mill is,
that is to say, made by the artifice of man”.
4. The best illustration, perhaps, of
how we constantly make use of the experience or knowledge acquired by others, is
the way in which, by learning to speak, we learn to classify things in a certain
manner without acquiring the actual experiences which have led successive
generations to evolve this system of classification. There is a great deal of knowledge which
we never consciously know implicit in the knowledge of which we are aware,
knowledge which yet constantly serves us in our actions, though we can hardly be
said to “possess” it.
29
which the individual plays a part
which he can never fully understand. They are greater than any individual
precisely because they result from the combination of knowledge more extensive
than a single mind can master.
It has been unfortunate that those
who have recognised this so often draw the conclusion that the problems it
raises are purely historical problems, and thereby deprive themselves of the
means of effectively refuting the views they try to combat. In fact, as we have seen,
1 much of the
older “historical school” was essentially a reaction against the type of
erroneous rationalism we are discussing. If it failed it was because it treated
the problem of explaining these phenomena as entirely one of the accidents of
time and place and refused systematically to elaborate the logical process by
which alone we can provide an explanation. We need not return here at any length to
this point already discussed. 2
Though the explanation of the way in which the parts of
the social whole depend upon each other will often take the form of a genetic
account, this will be at most “schematic history” which the true historian will
rightly refuse to recognise as real history. It will deal, not with the particular
circumstances of an individual process, but only with those steps which are
essential to produce a particular result, with a process which, at least in
principle, may be repeated elsewhere or at different times. As all explanations, it must run in
generic terms, it will deal with what is sometimes called the “logic of events”,
neglect much that is important in the unique historical instance, and be
concerned with a dependence of the parts of the phenomenon upon each other which
is not even necessarily the same as the chronological order in which they
appeared. In short, it is not
history, but compositive social theory.
One curious aspect of this problem
that is rarely appreciated is that it is only by the individualist or
compositive method that we can give a definite meaning to the much abused
phrases about the social processes and formations being in any sense “more” than
“merely the sum” of their parts, and that we are enabled to understand how
structures of interpersonal relationships emerge, which make it possible for the
joint efforts of individuals to achieve desirable results no individual could
have planned or foreseen. The
collectivist, on the other hand, who refuses to account for the wholes by
systematically following up the interactions of individual efforts, and who
claims to be able directly to comprehend social wholes as such, is never able to
define the precise character of these wholes or their mode of operation, and is
regularly driven to conceive of these wholes on the model of an individual
mind.
Even more significant of the
inherent weakness of the collectivist theories is the extraordinary paradox that
from the assertion that society is in some sense “more” than merely the
aggregate of all individuals their adherents regularly pass by a sort of
intellectual somersault to the thesis that in order that the coherence of this
larger entity be safeguarded it must be subjected to conscious control, i.e., to
the control of what in the last resort must be an individual mind. It thus comes about that it is in
practice regularly the theoretical collectivist who extols individual reason and
demands that all forces of society be made subject to the direction of a single
master-mind, while it is the individualist who recognises the limitations of the
powers of individual reason and consequently advocates freedom as a mean to the
fullest development of the powers of the inter-individual
process.
XII - “Conscious” Direction and the Growth of
Reason
The universal demand for “conscious”
control or direction of social processes is one of the most characteristic
features of our generation. It
expresses perhaps more clearly than any of its other clichés the peculiar spirit
of the age. That anything is not
consciously directed as a whole is regarded as itself a blemish, a proof of its
irrationality and of the need completely to replace it by a deliberately
designed mechanism. Yet few of the
people who use the term “conscious” so freely seem to be aware what it precisely
means; most people seem to forget that .“conscious” and “deliberate” are terms
which have meaning only when applied to individuals, and that the demand for
conscious control is therefore equivalent to the demand for control by a single
mind.
This belief that processes which are
consciously directed are necessarily superior to any spontaneous process is an
unfounded superstition. It would be
truer to say as Professor Whitehead has argued in another connection, that on
the contrary “civilisation advances by extending the number of important
operations we can
1. See Part II of this article, Economica, February, 2943, pp. 50 et seq.
2. Ibid., pp. 54-58. Cf. also Part I, p. 289, and Meager,
Untersachungen, etc., pp. 164 et
seq.
30
perform without thinking about
them.” 1 If it is true that the spontaneous interplay of social
forces sometimes solves problems no individual mind could consciously solve, or
perhaps even perceives, and if they thereby create an ordered structure which
increases the power of the individuals without having been designed by any one
of them, they are superior to conscious action. Indeed, any social processes which
deserve to be called “social” in distinction to the action of individuals are
almost ex definitione not conscious. In so far as such processes are capable
of producing a useful order which could not have been produced by conscious
direction, any attempt to make them subject to such direction would necessarily
mean that we restrict what social activity can achieve to the inferior capacity
of the individual mind. 2
The full significance of this demand
for universal conscious control will be seen most clearly if we consider it
first in its most ambitious manifestation, even though this is as yet merely a
vague aspiration and important mainly as a symptom: this is the application of
the demand for conscious control to the growth of the human mind itself. This audacious idea is the most extreme
result to which man has yet been led by the success of reason in the conquest of
external nature. It has become a
characteristic feature of contemporary thought and appears in what on a first
view seem to be altogether different and even opposite systems of ideas. Whether it is the late L. T. Hobhouse who
holds up to us “the ideal of a collective humanity self-determining in its
progress as the supreme object of human activity and the final standard by which
the laws of conduct should be judged”,
3 or Dr.
Joseph Needham who argues that “the more control consciousness has over human
affairs, the more truly human and hence super-human man will become”,
4 whether it is the strict followers of Hegel who
adumbrate the master’s view of Reason becoming conscious of itself and taking
control of its fate, or Dr. Karl Mannheim who thinks that “man’s thought has
become more spontaneous and absolute than it ever was, since it now perceives
the possibility of determining itself”,
5 the basic
attitude is the same. Though,
according as these doctrines spring from Hegelian or positivist views, those who
hold them form distinct groups who mutually regard themselves as completely
different from and greatly superior to the other, the common idea that the human
mind is, as it were, to pull itself up by its own boot-straps, springs from the
same general approach: the belief that by studying human Reason from the outside
and as a whole we can grasp the laws of its motion in a more complete and
comprehensive manner than by its patient exploration from the inside, by
actually following up the processes in which individual minds
interact.
This pretension to be able to
increase the powers of the human mind by consciously controlling its growth is
thus based on the same theoretical view which claims to be able fully to explain
this growth, a claim which implies the possession of a kind of super-mind on the
part of those who make it; and it is no accident that those who hold these
theoretical views should also wish to see the growth of mind thus
directed.
It is important to understand the
precise sense in which the claim to be able to “explain” existing knowledge and
beliefs must be interpreted in order to justify the aspirations based on it.
For this purpose it would not be
sufficient if we possessed an adequate theory which explained the principles
on which the processes operate to which the growth of mind is due. Such knowledge of the mere principles
(either a theory of knowledge or a theory of the social processes involved)
might assist in creating conditions favourable to that growth, but could never
provide a justification for the claim to direct it. This claim presupposes that we are able
to arrive at a substantive explanation of why we hold the particular views we
hold, of how our actual knowledge is determined by specific conditions. It is this which, the “sociology
of
1.
A. N. Whitehead, An Introduction to
Mathematics (
2.
It cannot be objected to this that what is
meant by conscious control is not control by a single mind but by a concerted and
“co-ordinated” effort of all, or all the best minds instead of by their
fortuitous interplay. This phrase
about the deliberate co-ordination merely shifts the task of the individual mind
to another stage but leaves the ultimate responsibility still with the
co-ordinating mind. Committees and
other devices for facilitating communications are excellent means to assist the
individual in learning as much as possible; but they do not extend the capacity
of the individual mind. The
knowledge that can be consciously co-ordinated in this manner is still limited
to what the individual mind can effectively absorb and digest. As every person with experience of
committee work knows, its fertility is limited to what the best mind among the members can
master; if the results of the discussion are not ultimately turned into a
coherent whole by an individual mind, they are likely to be inferior to what
would have been produced unaided by a single mind.
3. L. T. Hobhouse, Democracy and
Reaction, 1904, p.
108.
4. J.Needham, Integrative Levels. A Revaluation of the
Idea of Progress (Herbert Spencer
Lecture),
5. K. Mainnheim, Man and Society in an Age of
Reconstruction, 1940, p.
213.
31
knowledge” and the various other
derivatives of the “materialist interpretation of history” undertake when, e.g.,
they “explain” the Kantian philosophy as the product of the material interests
of the German bourgeoisie in the late 18th century, or whatever other similar
theses they present. We cannot
enter here into a discussion of the reasons why even with respect to views now
regarded as errors, and which on the basis of our better present knowledge we
may in a sense be able to explain, that method does not really provide an
explanation. The crucial point is
that to attempt this with respect to our present knowledge involves a
contradiction: if we knew how our present knowledge is conditioned or
determined, it would no longer be our present knowledge. To assert that we can explain our own
knowledge is to assert that we know more than we do know, a statement which is
non-sense in the strict meaning of that term.
1 There may, perhaps, be sense in the statement that to a
greatly superior mind our present knowledge would appear as “relative” or
conditioned in a certain manner by assignable circumstances. But the only conclusion we should
be entitled to draw from this would be one opposite to that of the “boot-strap
theory of mental evolution”; it would be that on the basis of our present
knowledge we are not in a position successfully to direct its growth. To draw any other conclusion than this,
to derive from the thesis that human beliefs are determined by circumstances the
claim that anyone should be given power to determine these beliefs, involves the
claim that those who are to assume that power possess some sort of super-mind.
Those who hold these views have
indeed regularly some special theory which exempts their own views from the same
sort of explanation and credits them, as a specially favoured class, or simply
as the “free-floating intelligentsia”, with the possession of absolute
knowledge.
While in a sense this movement
represents thus a sort of super-rationalism, a demand for the direction of
everything by a super-mind, it prepares at the same time the ground for a
thorough irrationalism. If truth is
no longer discovered by observation, reasoning and argument, but by uncovering
hidden causes which, unknown to the thinker, have determined his conclusions, if
whether a statement is true or false is no longer decided by logical argument
and empirical tests, but by examining the social position of the person who made
it, when in consequence it becomes the membership of a class or race which
secures or prevents the achievement of truth, and when in the end it is claimed
that the sure instinct of a particular class or a people is always right, reason
has been finally driven out. 2
This is no more than the natural result of a doctrine
which starts out with the claim that it can intuitively recognise wholes in a
manner superior to the rational reconstruction attempted by compositive social
theory.
If it is true, moreover, as in their
different ways both individualists and collectivists contend, that social
processes can achieve things which it is beyond the power of the individual mind
to achieve and plan, and that it is from those social processes that the
individual mind derives what power it possesses, the attempt to impose conscious
control on these processes must have even more fatal consequences. The presumptuous aspiration that “reason”
should direct its own growth could in practice only have the effect that it
would set limits to its own growth, that it would confine itself to the results
which the directing individual mind can already foresee. Though this aspiration is a direct
outcome of a certain brand of rationalism, it is, of course, the result of a
misunderstood or misapplied rationalism which fails to recognise the extent to
which individual reason is a product of inter-individual relationships. Indeed, the demand that everything,
including the growth of mind, should be consciously controlled, is itself a sign
of the inadequacy of the understanding of even the general character of the
forces which constitute the life of the human mind and of human society. It is the extreme stage of these
self-destructive forces of our modern “scientific” civilisation, of that abuse
of reason whose development and consequences will be the central theme of the
following historical studies.
It is because the growth of the
human mind presents in its most general form the common problem of all the
social sciences that it is here that minds most sharply divide, and two
fundamentally different and irreconcilable attitudes manifest themselves. On the one hand the essential humility of
individualism, which endeavours to understand as well as possible the principles
by which the efforts of individual men have in fact been combined to produce our
civilisation, and from this understanding hopes to derive the power to create
conditions favourable to further growth; and, on the other hand, the hybris of
collectivism which aims at conscious direction
1.
See Part II of this article, Economica, February, 1943, pp. 36 and 6o
seq.
2.
Interesting illustrations of the length to
which these absurdities have been carried will be found in E. Gruenwald, Das
Problem der Soziologie des Wissens, Vienna, 1934, a posthumously published
sketch of a very young scholar which still constitutes the most comprehensive
survey of the literature of the subject.
of all forces of society. The individualist approach, in awareness
of the constitutional limitations of the individual mind,
1 attempts to
show how man in society is able, by the use of various resultants of the social
process, to increase his powers with the help of the knowledge implicit in. them
and of which he is never aware; it makes us understand that the only “reason”
which can in any sense be regarded as superior to individual reason does not
exist apart from the inter-individual process in which, by means of impersonal
media, the knowledge of successive generations and of millions of people living
simultaneously is combined and mutually adjusted, and that this process is the
only form in which the totality of human knowledge ever exists. The collectivist method, on the other
hand, not satisfied with the partial knowledge of this process from the inside,
which is all the individual can gain, bases its demand for conscious control on
the assumption that it can comprehend this process as a whole and make use of
all knowledge in a systematically integrated form. It leads thus directly to political
collectivism; and though logically methodological and political collectivism are
distinct, it is not difficult to see bow the former leads to the latter and how,
indeed, without methodological collectivism political collectivism would be
deprived of its intellectual basis: without the pretension that conscious
individual reason can grasp all the aims and all the knowledge of “society” or
“humanity”, the belief that these aims are best achieved by conscious central
direction loses its foundation. Consistently pursued it must lead to a
system in which all members of society become merely instruments of the single
directing mind and in which all the spontaneous social forces to which the
growth of the mind is due are destroyed.
2
It may indeed prove to be far the
most difficult and not the least important task for human reason rationally to
comprehend its own limitations. It
is essential for the growth of reason that as individuals we should bow to
forces and obey principles which we cannot hope fully to understand yet on which
the advance and even the preservation of civiisation depends.
3 Historically this has been achieved by the influence of
the various religious creeds and by traditions and superstitions which made men
submit to those forces by an appeal to his emotions rather than his reason.
The most dangerous stage in the
growth of civilisation may well be that in which man has come to regard all
these beliefs as superstitions and refuses to accept or to submit to anything
which he does not rationally understand. The rationalist whose reason is not
sufficient to teach him those limitations of the powers of conscious reason, and
who despises all the institutions and customs which have not been consciously
designed, would thus become the destroyer of the civilisation built upon them.
This may well prove a hurdle which
man will repeatedly reach, only to be thrown back into
barbarism.
It would lead too far here more than
briefly to refer to another field in which this same characteristic tendency of
our age shows itself: that of morals. Here it is against the observance of any
general and formal rules whose rationale is not explicitly demonstrated
that the same kind of objections are raised. But the demand that every action should
be judged after full consideration of all its consequences and not by any
general rules is due to a failure to see that the submission to general rules,
couched in terms of immediately ascertainable circumstances, is the only way in
which for man with his limited knowledge freedom can be combined with the
essential minimum degree of order. Common acceptance of formal rules is
indeed the only alternative to direction for a common purpose man has yet
discovered. The general acceptance
of such a body of rules is no less important because they have not been
rationally constructed. It is at
least doubtful whether it would be possible in this way to construct a new moral
code that would have any chance of acceptance. But so long as we have not succeeded in
doing so, any general refusal to accept existing moral rules merely because
their expediency has not been rationally demonstrated (as distinguished from the
case when the critic believes he has discovered a better moral rule in a
particular instance and is willing to brave public disapproval in testing it) is
to destroy one of the roots of our civilisation. 4
1. Cf. Part I of this article, Economica, August, 1942, pp. 280 and 290.
2.
It is, perhaps, not so obvious as to make it
unnecessary to mention it, that the fashionable disparagement of any activity
which, in science or the arts, is carried on “for its own sake “, and the demand
for a “conscious social purpose” in everything, is an expression of the same
general tendency and based on the same illusion of complete knowledge as those
discussed in the text.
3. Some further aspects of the big
problems here just touched upon are discussed in my Road to Serfdom.
1944, particularly chapters
VI and XIV.
4. It is characteristic of the spirit
of the time, and of positivism in particular, when A. Comte speaks (Système
de Politique Positive, Vol. I, p. 356) of “La supferiorité necessaire de la
morale démontrée sur in morale révélée”, characteristic especially in its
implied assumption that a rationally constructed moral system is the only
alternative to one revealed by a higher being.
33
The ideal of conscious control of
social phenomena has made its greatest influence felt in the economic field.
The present popularity of “economic
planning” is directly traceable to the prevalence of the scientistic ideas we
have been discussing. As in this
field the scientistic ideals manifest themselves in the particular forms which
they take in the hands of the applied scientist and especially the engineer, it
will be convenient to combine the discussion of this influence with some
examination of the characteristic ideals of the engineers. We shall see that the influence on
current views about problems of social organisation of his technological
approach, or the engineering point of view, is much greater than is generally
realised. Most of the schemes for a
complete remodelling of society, from the earlier utopias to modem socialism,
bear indeed the distinct mark of this influence. In recent years this desire to apply
engineering technique to the solution of social problems has become very
explicit; 1 “political engineering” and “social engineering” have
become fashionable catchwords which are quite as characteristic of the outlook
of the present generation as its predilection for “conscious” control; in Russia
even the artists appear to pride themselves on the name of “engineers of the
soul”, bestowed upon them by Stalin.
These phrases suggest a confusion about the fundamental differences
between the task of the engineer and that of social organisations on a larger
scale which make it desirable to consider their character somewhat more
fully.
We must confine ourselves here to a
few salient features of the specific problems which the professional experience
of the engineer constantly bring up and which determine his outlook. The first is that his characteristic
tasks are usually in themselves complete: he will be concerned with a single
end, control all the efforts directed towards this end, and dispose for this
purpose of a definitely given supply of resources. It is as a result of this that the most
characteristic feature of his procedure becomes possible, namely that, at least
in principle, all the parts of the complex of operations are preformed in the
engineer’s mind before they start, that all the “data” on which the work is
based have explicitly entered his preliminary calculations and been condensed
into the “blue-print” that governs the execution of the whole scheme.
2 3 The engineer, in other words, has complete control of
the particular little world with which he is concerned, surveys it in all its
relevant aspects and has to deal only with “known quantities”. So far as the
solution of his engineering problem is concerned, he is not taking part in a
social process in which others may take independent decisions, but lives in a
separate world of his own. The
application of the technique which he has mastered, of the generic rules he has
been taught, indeed presupposes such com-
1. Once again one of the best
illustrations of this tendency is provided by K. Mannheim, Man and Society in
an Age of Reconstruction, 1940,
particularly pp. 240-244,
where he explains that “functionalism made its first appearance in the
field of the natural sciences, and could be described as the technical point of
view. It has only recently been
transferred to the social sphere … Once this technical approach was transferred
from natural sciences to human affairs, it was bound to bring about a profound
change in man himself. The
functional approach no longer regards ideas and moral standards as absolute
values, but as products of the social process which can, if necessary, be
changed by scientific guidance combined with political practice … The extension of the doctrine of
technical supremacy which I have advocated in this book is in my opinion
inevitable … Progress in the technique of organisation is nothing but the
application of technical conceptions to the forms of co-operation. A human being, regarded as part of the
social machine, is to a certain extent stabilised in his reactions by training
and education, and all his recently acquired activities are co-ordinated
according to a definite principle of efficiency within an organised
framework.”
2.
The best description of this feature of the
engineering approach by an engineer which I have been able to find occurs in a
speech of the great German optical engineer Ernst Abbe : “{HHC: extensive German footnote not
reproduced}” (quoted by Franz Schnabel, Deutsche Geschichte im
neunzehnten Jahrhundert, vol. III, 1934, p. 222 - a work which is
a mine of information on this as on all other matters of the intellectual
history of Germany in the nineteenth century).
3. It would take too long here to
explain in any detail why, whatever delegation or division of labour is possible
in preparing an engineering ‘blueprint’, is very limited and differs in
essential respects from the division of knowledge on which the impersonal social
processes rest. It must suffice to
point out that not only must the precise nature of the result be fixed which
anyone who has to draw up part of an engineering plan must achieve, but also
that, in order to make such delegation possible, it must be known that the
result can be achieved at no more than a certain maximum
cost.
plete knowledge of the objective
facts; those rules refer to objective properties of the things and can be
applied only after all the particular circumstances of time and place have been
assembled and brought under the control of a single brain. His technique, in other words, refers to
typical situations defined in terms of objective facts, not to the problem of
how to find out what resources are available or what is the relative importance
of different needs. He has been
trained in objective possibilities, irrespective of the particular conditions of
time and place, in the knowledge of those properties of things which remain the
same everywhere and at all times and which they possess irrespective of a
particular human situation.
It is important, however, to observe
that the engineer’s view of his job as complete in itself is, in some measure, a
delusion. He is in a position to
treat it as such in a competitive society because he can regard the assistance
from society at large on which he counts as one of his data, as given to him
without having to bother about it. That he can buy at given prices the
materials and the services of the men he needs, that if he pays his men they
will be able to procure their food and other necessities, he will usually take
for granted. It is through basing
his plans on the data offered to him by the market that they are fitted into the
larger complex of social activities; and it is because he need not concern
himself how the market provides him with what he needs that he can treat his job
as self-contained. So long as
market prices do not change unexpectedly he uses them as a guide in his
calculations without much reflection about their significance. But, though he is compelled to take them
into account, they are not properties of things of the same kind as those which
he understands. They are not
objective attributes of things but reflections of a particular human situation
at a given time and place. And as
his knowledge does not explain why those changes in prices occur which often
interfere with his plans, any such interference appears to him due to irrational
(i.e., not consciously directed) forces and he resents the necessity of paying
attention to magnitudes which appear meaningless to him. Hence the characteristic and
ever-recurrent demand for the substitution of in natura
1
calculation for the “artificial” calculation in terms of
price or value, i.e., of a calculation which takes explicit account of the
objective properties of things.
The engineer’s ideal which he feels
the “irrational” economic forces prevent him from achieving, based on his study
of the objective properties of the things, is usually some purely technical
optimum of universal validity. He
rarely sees that his preference for these particular method its merely a result
of the type of problem he has most frequently to solve, and justified only in
particular social positions. Since
the most common problem the builder of machines meets is to extract from given
resources the maximum of power, with the machinery to be used the variable under
his control, this maximum utilisation of power is set up as an absolute ideal, a
value in itself. 2 But there is, of course, no special merit in economising
one of the many
1 The most persistent advocate of
such in natura calculation is, significantly, Dr. Otto Neurath, the
protagonist of modern “physicalism” and “objectivism”.
2. Cf. the characteristic passage in
B. Bavinck, The Anatomy of Modern Science (translated from the 4th German
edition by H. S. Hatfield), 2932, p. 564: “When our technology is still at work
on the problem of transforming heat into work in a manner better than that
possible with our present-day steam and other heat engines .., this is not
directly done to cheapen production of energy, but first of all because it is an
end in itself to increase the thermal efficiency of a heat engine as much as
possible. If the problem set is to
transform heat into work, then this must be done in such a way that the greatest
possible fraction of the heat is so transformed … The ideal of the designer of
such machines is therefore the efficiency of the Carnot cycle, the ideal process
which delivers the greatest theoretical efficiency”.
It is easy to see why this approach,
together with the desire to achieve a calculation in natura, leads
engineers so frequently to the construction of systems of “energetics” that it
has been said, with much justice, that “dam Characteristikum der Weltanschauung
des Ingenieurs ist die energetische Weltanschauung” (L. Brinkmann, Der
Ingenieur, Frankfurt, 2908, p. i6). We have already referred (Part II of this
article, Economica, February, 2943,
p. 40) to this characteristic manifestation of scientistic “objectivism” and
there is no space here to return to it in greater detail. But it deserves to be recorded how
widespread and typical this view is and how great the influence it has
exercised. E. Solvay, G.
Ratzenhofer, W. Ostwaldt, P. Geddes, F. Soddy, H. G. Wells, the “Technocrats”
and L. Hogben are only a few of the influential authors in whose works
“energetics” play a more or less prominent rôle. There are several studies of this
movement in French and German (Nyssens, L’ênergetique, Brussels, 1908; G.
Barnich, Principes de politique positive basée sur l’ênergetique sociale de
Solvay, Brussels, 1918; G. Helm, Die Energetik in ibrer geschichtlichen
Entwicklung, Berlin, 1898 ; Schnehen, Energetiscbe Weltanschauung,
1907). A. Dochmann, F. W. Osiwald’s Energetik,
The section from the work of Bavinck
from which a passage has been quoted above condenses the gist of the enormous
literature, mostly German, on the “philosophy of technology” which has had a
wide circulation and of which the best known is F. Zschimmer, Philosophie der
Technik, 3rd ed., Stuttgart, 1933.
[This
literature is very instructive as a psychological study, though otherwise about
the dreariest mixture of pretentious platitudes and revolting nonsense which it
has ever been the ill fortune of the present author to peruse. Its common feature is the enmity towards
all economic considerations, the attempted vindication of purely technological
ideals, and the glorification of the organisation of the whole of society on the
principle on which a single factory is run. (On the last point see particularly F.
Dessauer, Philosophic der Technik,
Bonn, 1927, p. 229.) It would be
unfair, however, not to mention here the brilliant study in which an eminent
American engineer has very clearly shown the limitations of the application of
engineering technique to problems of social organisation: D. C. Coyle, “The
Twilight of National Planning,” Harper’s
Magazine, October, 1935.]
HHC:
[bracketed] displayed on page 36 of original.
35
factors which limit the possible
achievement, at the expense of others. The engineer’s “technical optimum” proves
frequently to be simply that method which it would be desirable to adopt if the
rate of interest were zero - or the supply of capital unlimited, which would
indeed be a position in which we would aim at the highest possible rate of
transformation of current input into current output. But to treat this as an immediate goal is
to forget that such a state can be reached only by diverting for a long time
resources which are wanted to serve current needs to the production of
equipment. In other words, the
engineer’s ideal is based on the disregard of the most fundamental economic fact
which determines our position here and now, the scarcity of
capital.
The rate of interest is, of course,
only one, though the least understood and therefore most disliked, of those
prices which act as impersonal guides to which the engineer must submit if his
plans are to fit into the pattern of activity of society as a whole, and against
the restraint of which he chafes because they represent forces whose
rationale he does not understand. It is one of those symbols in which the
whole complex of human knowledge and wants is automatically (though by no means
faultlessly) recorded and to which the individual must pay attention if he wants
to keep in step with the rest of the system. If, instead of using this information in
the abridged form in which it is conveyed to him through the price system, he
were to try in every instance to go back to the objective facts and take them
consciously into consideration, this would be to dispense with the method which
makes it possible for him to confine himself to the immediate circumstances and
to substitute for it a method which requires that all this knowledge be
collected in one centre and explicitly and consciously embodied in a unitary
plan. The application of
engineering technique to the whole of society requires indeed that the director
possess the same complete knowledge of the whole society that the engineer
possesses of his limited world. Central economic planning is nothing but
such an application of engineering principles to the whole of society based on
the assumption that such a complete concentration of all relevant knowledge is
possible.1
Before we proceed to consider the
significance of this conception of a rational organisation of society it will be
useful to supplement the sketch of the typical outlook of the engineer by an
even briefer sketch of the functions of the merchant or trader. This will not only further elucidate the
nature of the problem of the utilisation of knowledge dispersed among many
people, but also help to explain the dislike which not only the engineer but our
whole generation shows for all commercial activities, and the general preference
that is now accorded to “production” compared to the activities which, somewhat
misleadingly, are referred to as “distribution”.
Compared with the work of the
engineer that of the merchant is in a sense much more “social”, i.e., interwoven
with the free activities of other people.
He contributes a step towards the achievement now of one end, now of
another and hardly ever is concerned with the complete process that serves a
final need. What concerns him is
not the achievement of a particular final result of the complete process in
which he takes part, but the best use of the particular means of which he knows.
His special knowledge is almost
entirely knowledge of particular circumstances of time or place, or, perhaps, a
technique of ascertaining those circumstances in a given field. But though this knowledge is not of a
kind which can be formulated in generic propositions or acquired once and for
all, and though in an age of Science it is for that reason regarded as knowledge
of an inferior kind, it is for all practical purposes no less important than
scientific knowledge. And while it
is perhaps conceivable that all theoretical knowledge might be combined in the
heads of a few experts and thus made available to a single central authority, it
is this knowledge of the particular, of the
1.
That this is fully recognised by its
advocates is shown by the popularity among all socialists from Saint-Simon to
Marx and Lenin, of the phrase that the whole of society should be run in
precisely the same manner as a single factory is now being run. Cf. V. I. Lenin, The State and
Revolution (1917),
“Little Lenin
Library,” 1933, p. 78. “The
whole of society will have become a single office and a single factory with
equality of work and equality of pay”; and for Saint-Simon and Marx, Economica, February, 1941, p.28.
36
fleeting circumstances of the moment
and of local conditions, which will never exist otherwise than dispersed among
many people. The knowledge of when
a particular material or machine can be most effectively used or where they can
be most quickly or cheaply obtained is quite as important for the solution of a
particular task as the knowledge of what is the best material or machine for the
purpose. The former kind of
knowledge has little to do with the permanent properties of classes of things
which the engineer studies, but is knowledge of a particular human situation.
And it is as the person whose task
is to take account of these facts that the merchant will constantly come into
conflict with the ideals of the engineer, with whose plans he interferes and
whose dislike he thereby contracts.
The problem of securing an efficient
use of our resources is thus very largely one of how that knowledge of the
particular circumstances of the moment can be most effectively utilised; and the
task which faces the designer of a rational order of society is to find a method
whereby this widely dispersed knowledge may best be drawn upon. It is begging the question to describe
this task, as is usually done, as one of effectively using the “available”
resources to satisfy “existing” needs. Neither the “available” resources nor the
“existing” needs are objective facts in the sense of those with which the
engineer deals in his limited field: they can never be directly known in all
relevant detail to a single planning body. Resources and needs exist for practical
purposes only through somebody knowing about them and there will always be
infinitely more known to all the people together than can be known to the most
competent authority. 1 A successful solution can therefore not be based on the
authority dealing directly with the objective facts, but must be based on a
method of utilising the knowledge dispersed among all members of society,
knowledge of which in any particular instance the central authority will usually
know neither who possesses it nor whether it exists at all. It can therefore not be utilised by
consciously integrating it into a coherent whole, but only through some
mechanism which will delegate the particular decisions to those who possess it,
and for that purpose supply them with such information about the general
situation as will enable them to make the best use of the particular
circumstances of which only they know.
This is precisely the function which
the various “markets” perform. Though every party in them will know only
a small sector of all the possible sources of supply, or of the uses of, a
commodity, yet, directly or indirectly, the parties are so inter-connected that
the prices register the relevant net result of all changes affecting demand or
supply. 2 It is as such an instrument for communicating to all
those interested in a particular commodity the relevant information in an
abridged and condensed form that markets and prices must be seen if we are to
understand their function. They
help to utilise the knowledge of many people without the need of first
collecting it in a single body, and thereby make possible that combination of
decentralisation of decisions and mutual adjustment of these decisions which we
find in a competitive system.
In aiming at a result which must be
based, not on a single body of integrated knowledge or of connected reasoning
which the designer possesses, but on the separate knowledge of many people, the
task of social organisation differs fundamentally from that of organising given
material resources. The fact that
no single mind can know more than a fraction of what is known to all individual
minds sets limits to the extent to which conscious direction can improve upon
the results of unconscious social processes. Man has not deliberately designed this
process and has begun to understand it only long after it had grown up. But that something that not only does not
rely on deliberate control for its working, but has not even been deliberately
designed, should bring about desirable results, which we might not be able to
bring about otherwise, is a conclusion the natural scientist seems to find
difficult to accept.
It is because the moral sciences
tend to show us such limits to our conscious control, while the progress of the
natural sciences constantly extends the range of conscious control, that the
natural scientist finds himself so frequently in revolt
1.
It is important to remember in this
connection that the statistical aggregates which it is often suggested the
central authority could rely upon in its decisions, are always arrived at by a
deliberate disregard of the peculiar circumstances of time and
place.
2. Cf. in this connection the
suggestive discussion of the problem in K. F. Mayer, Goldwanderugen,
Jena, 1935, pp. 66-68, and also the present author’s article “Economics and
Knowledge” in Economica, February,
1937.
37
against the teaching of the moral
sciences. Economics, in particular, after being condemned for employing methods
different from those of the natural scientist, stands doubly condemned because
it claims to show limits to the technique by which the natural scientists
continuously extend our conquest and mastery of nature.
It is this conflict with a strong
human instinct, greatly strengthened in the person of the scientist and
engineer, that makes the teaching of the moral sciences so very unwelcome. As Bertrand Russell has well described
the position, “the pleasure of planned construction is one of the most powerful
motives in men who combine intelligence with energy; whatever can be constructed
according to a plan, such man will endeavour to construct … the desire to create
is not in itself idealistic since it is a form of the love of power, and while
the power to create exists there will be men desirous of using this power even
if unaided nature would produce a better result than any that can be brought
about by deliberate intention”.
1
This statement itself occurs, however, at the beginning
of a chapter, significantly headed “Artificially Created Societies”, in which
Russell himself seems to support these tendencies by arguing that “no society
can be regarded as fully scientific unless it has been created deliberately with
a certain structure to fulfil certain purposes.”
2 As this statement will be understood by most readers, it
expresses concisely that scientistic philosophy which through its popularisers
has done more to create the present trend towards socialism than all the
conflicts between economic interests which, though they raise a problem, do not
necessarily indicate a particular solution. Of the majority of the intellectual
leaders of the socialist movement, at least, it is probably true to say that
they are socialists because socialism appears to them, as A. Bebel, the leader
of the German Social Democratic movement defined it more than fifty years ago,
as “science applied in clear awareness and with full insight to all fields of
human activity.” 3 The proof that the programme of socialism actually
derives from this kind of scientistic philosophy must be reserved for detailed
historical studies. At present our
concern is mainly to show to what extent mere intellectual error in this field
may profoundly affect all prospects of humanity.
What all the people who are so
unwilling to renounce any of the powers of conscious control seem to be unable
to comprehend is that this renunciation of conscious power, power which must
always be power by men over other men, is for society as a whole only an
apparent resignation, a self-denial individuals are called upon to exercise in
order to increase the powers of the race, to release the knowledge and energies
of the countless individuals that could never be utilised in a society
consciously directed from the top. The great misfortune of our generation is
that the direction which has been given to its interests by the amazing progress
of the natural sciences is not one which assists us in comprehending the larger
process of which as individuals we form merely a part, and in appreciating how
we constantly contribute to a common effort without either directing it or
submitting to orders of others. To
see this requires a kind of intellectual effort different in character from that
necessary for the control of material things, an effort in which the traditional
education in the “humanities” gave at least some practice, but for which the now
predominant types of education seem less and less to prepare. The more our technical civilisation
advances and the more, therefore, the study of things as distinct from the study
of men and their ideas qualifies for the more important and influential
positions, the more significant becomes the gulf that separates two different
types of mind: the one represented by the man whose supreme ambition is to turn
the world round him into an enormous machine, every part of which, on his
pressing a button, moves according to his design; and the other represented by
the man whose main interest is the growth of the human mind in all its aspects,
who in the study of history or literature, the arts or the law, has learnt to
see the individuals as part of a process in which his contribution is not
directed but spontaneous, and where he assists in the creation of something
greater than he or any other single mind can ever plan for. It is this awareness of being part of a
social process, and of the manner in which individual efforts
interact,
1.
The Scientifiic Outlook, 1931, p. 211.
2.
Ibid., p. 211. The
passage quoted could be interpreted in an unobjectionable sense if “certain
purposes” is taken to mean not particular predetermined results but as capacity
to provide what the individuals at any time wish - i;e., if what is planned is a
machinery which can serve many ends and need not in turn be “consciously”
directed towards a particular end.
3. A. Bebel, Die Frau and der
Sozialismus, 13th ed, 1892, p. 376. “{HHC: German footnote not reproduced}”
Cf. also F. Ferri, Socialism and
Positive Science (translated from the Italian edition of 1894). The first clearly to see this connection
seems to have been lvi. Ferraz, Socialisme, Naturalisme et Positivisme,
Paris, 1877.
38
which the education solely in the
Sciences or in technology seems to fail so lamentably to convey. It is not surprising that many of the
more active minds among those so trained sooner or later react violently against
the deficiencies of their education and develop a passion for imposing on
society the order which they are unable to discover by the means with which they
are familiar.
In conclusion it is, perhaps,
desirable to remind the reader once more that all we have said here is directed
solely against a misuse of Science, not against the scientist in the special
field where he is competent, but against the application of his mental habits in
fields where he is not competent. There is no conflict between our
conclusions and those of legitimate science. The main lesson at which we have arrived
is indeed the same as that which one of the acutest students of scientific
method has drawn from a
survey of all fields of knowledge: it is that “the great lesson of
humility which science teaches us, that we can never be omnipotent or
omniscient, is the same as that of all great religions: man is not and never
will be the god before whom he must bow down.”
1
1. M. R.
Cohen, Reason and Nature, 1931, p. 449. It is significant that one of the leading
members of the movement with which we are concerned, the German philosopher
Ludwig Feuerbach, explicitly chose the opposite principle, homo homini Deus,
as his guiding maxim.
39