The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy On the Metaphysics of TechnologyDraft HHC, June 2004 last revised November 2004 © |
Content
A.01 The philosophy
of technology has a long and troubled history.
The word ‘technology’ itself entered the English language in 1859 according
to the Merriam Webster Dictionary deriving from the Greek techne meaning Art and logos meaning Reason, i.e., reasoned art. The Oxford English Dictionary says it was re-coined
at that time by Sir Richard Francis Burton (OED, technology, 1 b)
[A],
Victorian explorer and translator of the Kama Sutra (1883), the Arabian
Nights (1885) and the Perfumed Garden
(1886). A.02 Techne, however, dates back to the ancient Greeks for whom it
signified all the Mechanical Arts excepting medicine and music. As such, it was suitable only for the lower
classes not for the upper class who practiced the
Liberal Arts of ‘free’ men. It was here
in ancient A.03 Until this
etymological consummation a philosophy of technology was not conceptually possible. Before 1859 there was art, craft and
mechanics; afterwards, there was also technology. While attempts had been made to formulate
philosophies of mechanics and manufacture, they remain essentially footnotes in
history including Ernst Kapp (1808-1896) who in 1877
(Idhe 1991, 3) became “the little-known originator of
the term ‘philosophy of technology’”. (Mitcham 1994,
20-21) This group of thinkers is,
however, treated by Mitcham as the root of an
‘engineering tradition’ in the philosophy of technology (Mitcham
1994). A.04 It was Karl Marx,
however, (1818-1883) who produced the first true philosophy of technology
combining ‘the means of production’ with a humanist critique rather than
glorification of Victorian progress. While
Adam Smith expressed concerns about the psychological and sociological impact
of the division and specialization of labour that
characterizes technology (Rothschild 2001, 97), it was Marx who named the devil
– alienation. Arguably Marxism is nothing
but a philosophy of technology, one admittedly with a political agenda and
hence an ‘ideology’, i.e., “a
systematic scheme of ideas, usu. relating to politics or society, or to the
conduct of a class or group, and regarded as justifying actions.” (OED, ideology, 4). A.05 Marx also appropriated the term ‘praxis’,
a word which has a similarly chequered past. It was
coined by the alchemist, metaphysician and subsequent saint, Albert Magnus,
about 1255 C. E. He derived it from a
Greek noun of action meaning “doing, acting, action, practice.” (OED, praxis, Epistemology) It was re-coined by Cieszkowski
in 1838 to mean “the willed action by which a theory or philosophy… becomes a
social actuality.” It was then adopted
by Marx in 1844 for whom it explained “how knowledge could give power” not
through thought like Hegel but through the will. (OED, praxis,
1 c) To Marx, technology was the praxis
that explained how knowledge gives power and why ‘the means of production’
could not remain in private hands. A.06 This Marxian connection inevitably tainted
reception of subsequent philosophies of technology in ‘capitalist circles. This hesitancy to embrace technology as
embodied knowledge was amplified by developments in the philosophy of science leading
to the logical and empirical positivism of the A.07 Arguably the
‘new philosophy of science’ began with Thomas Kuhn’s 1962 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Ironically it was not until after publication that
Kuhn realized “that logical positivism had moved on from its extreme
A.08 The English-speaking world, in effect,
ignored the philosophy of technology because of its Marxist connotations and the
inability to express technology and praxis in logical propositional terms. In A.09 Heidegger’s work, however, was not well
received in the Anglosphere partially because it was
not written in English and partially because of his early support of Hitler and
the Nazi party. Accordingly, it took
time for his and the thought of other European scholars, e.g., Husserl, Merleau-Ponty
and Foucault (Idhe 1991) to break into
English-speaking consciousness. As evidence, consider that the American Philosophy
of Science Association was founded in 1934 while the Society for Philosophy and
Technology was founded some fifty years later in 1983 (Idhe
1991, 4) A.10 Given the
triumph of liberal democracy over the Nazi and by 1989 of Markets over Marx, it
is appropriate to pick the bones of the defeated to glean the good and leave
the gutted husk to bleach in the sun of a second Enlightenment – to the victor
goes the spoils! To do so, however,
requires an appreciation of the metaphysics of technology, an understanding of
why in the hands of Marx it became such a powerful ideology and why it is still
passionately viewed as either the last best hope of humanity or a Faustian
bargain with a lower class devil. A.11 If technology
has had a troubled history traveling from ancient slave to Marxian master of
the universe, it is as nothing compared to ‘metaphysics’ whose woes have moved
in the opposite temporal direction.
Putting the two troubles together as ‘the metaphysics of technology’ is
like the Victorian marriage of Sentiment (expressed through Art) and Reason. This
time, however, it is a ménage à trios of Sensation, Reason and Revelation. Technology, today, is about sensation and the
manipulation of the physical world (including the worlds internal and external
to the human body) to suit human purpose.
The god-like powers of genomics to re-create or clone the body itself
raises issues addressed by metaphysics defined as “the study of phenomena
beyond the scope of scientific inquiry” (OED, metaphysics, n, I & II 1 b) Ethics is a ‘Humanity’ not a
science. It is not a question of ‘can
do’ but of ‘should do’. This
questioning forms the root of what Mitcham calls ‘the
humanist tradition’ in the philosophy of technology (Mitcham
1994) A.12 While such questioning catches sight of
one facet of the metaphysics of technology, another is caught by the definition
of metaphysics as: “the branch of philosophy that deals with the first
principles of things or reality, including questions about being, substance,
time and space, causation, change, and identity.” (OED, metaphysics, n, I 1 a) In
Heidegger’s existential phenomenology the hammer is one with us in action. It becomes transparent as ‘other’, or as Polanyi put it, tools form “part of ourselves,
the operating persons. We pour ourselves
into them and assimilate them as parts of our own existence”. (Polanyi [1958] 1962, 59). ‘Being’ human is a succession of coordinated intentional
acts involving retention of the past to provide purpose or aim, and, protention of the future to achieve tacit performance, i.e., with no cognitive impediment. Being human is about manipulating the worlds
of mind and matter. It is our
nature. For Idhe,
this nature is expressed as ‘instrumental realism’ (Idhe
1991); for Baird, as ‘thing knowledge’. (Baird 2004) A.13 It is ironic
that Heidegger’s hammer - the basis of contemporary philosophy of technology -
is paralleled in the philosophy of science by Polanyi’s
hammer and ‘tacit knowledge’ which has become part of the lexicon of the
knowledge-based economy. (American National Standards
Institute and the Global Knowledge Economics Council 2001). Both
were German-speaking but I can find no reference that they knew each other or
each other’s work. Heidegger published his article ‘The Question
Concerning Technology’ in 1949; Polanyi published his
first edition of Personal Knowledge
in 1958. Heidegger had, however, first
mentioned the hammer metaphor in his 1927 book Being and Time. (Idhe 1991) A.14 A problem,
however, remains: how does one prove tacit knowledge? This is reflected in another definition of
metaphysics as “used by logical positivists and some other linguistic
philosophers for: any proposition or set of propositions of a speculative
nature, considered to be meaningless because not empirically verifiable.” (OED,
metaphysics, n, I 1 d) A.15 The final facet of the metaphysics of technology is captured in Christopher Marlowe’s definition of metaphysics in his 1604 play Faustus as “occult or magical lore”. (OED, metaphysics, n, II 3) Beyond the alchemy of modern technology to transmute matter, space, time and mind, there is the question of Good and Evil, of God and the Devil. Faustus appeared on stage just a year before Sir Francis Bacon began the Scientific Revolution with publication Of the Proficience and Advancement of Learning Divine and Humane (1605). The plot of Faustus follows the bargain struck between the Devil (a.k.a. Technology) and ‘Natural Man’ whose gives up his soul and place in heaven in return for dominion over the earth - here and now! A.16 Marx’s philosophy of technology like
Epicurus’ and Bentham’s philosophies was
‘god-less’. It trumpeted technology as
the true saviour of humanity; God need not
apply. This ideology created a schism in
Western thought the intensity of which became, by the mid-20th century, as
potentially apocalyptic as the European Religious Wars of the 16th and 17th
centuries, e.g., the fifteen minute
nuclear warning. It was, of course, out
of this earlier conflict that the Scientific Revolution emerged. This Revolution was underpinned by Robert
Boyle’s metaphysical compromise that after the Creation God withdrew from the
physical world allowing – Protestant or Catholic – the opportunity to discover His
Laws of Nature by putting the question using the instruments of the new ‘experimental philosophy’. (Jacob 1978) God
continued, however, to rule the realm of the human soul (moral philosophy) and the
third realm of angels (metaphysics).
Of the founders of the Royal Society, perhaps the most prominent member who did
not accept this ‘Latitudinalist’ compromise (Jacob & Jacob 1980)
was A.17 The metaphysical
implications of instruments of experimental philosophy cannot be
understated. As Alfred North Whitehead
wrote: “The reason we are on a higher imaginative level is not because we have
a finer imagination, but because we have better instruments. In science, the most important thing that has
happened in the last forty years is the advance in instrumental design... a
fresh instrument serves the same purpose as foreign travel; it shows things in
unusual combinations. The gain is more
than a mere addition; it is a transformation.” (Idhe
1991, 67) A.18 The metaphysical
impact of such instruments, or their ‘artificial revelation’ (Price 1984, 9), penetrates
our daily ‘being’: Putting our faith in “the objectivity” of machines
instead of human analysis and judgment has ramifications far and wide. It is a qualitatively different experience to
give birth with an array of electronic monitors. It is a qualitatively different experience to
teach when student evaluations – “customer satisfaction survey instruments” -
are used to evaluate one’s teaching. It
is a qualitatively different experience to make steel “by the numbers,” the
numbers being provided by analytical instrumentation. (Baird 2004, 19) A.19 Differing technological ‘faiths’ fueled
the Market/Marxist schism and completed the epistemological fissioning
of the old Moral Philosophy -- the total of all the sciences of mind and
society (Schumpeter 1949: 141) – on one side into the disciplines and
sub-disciplines of sociology, political science, psychology and mainstream or
Market Economics, and on the other, into parallel Marxian epistemologies plus
the Command Economy of the means of production, i.e., of technology. It should
be noted that Bentham’s radical materialism was only restrained
by the terror of the French Revolution.
[C]
(Marshall 1920: 628, ft 2) Karl Marx, however, saw revolution as the only hope
for the working man and the final triumph of human reason in economic and
political life. In a sense Marx is Bentham’s heir, the son he never had in the flesh. Marx simply extended Bentham's
logic beyond the inhibiting fear of revolution. This connection was made by Keynes who wrote:
I
do now regard that as the worm which has been gnawing at the insides of modern
civilization and is responsible for its present moral decay. We used to regard the Christians as the
enemy, because they appeared as the representatives of tradition, convention
and hocus-pocus. In truth, it was the Benthamite calculus, based on an over-valuation of the
economic criterion, which was destroying the quality of the popular Ideal. Moreover, it was this escape from Bentham... which has served to protect the whole lot of us
from the final reductio ad absurdum of Benthamism known as Marxism (M. Keynes 1949: 96-7). A.20 With respect to Economics, the
ideological divide went as follows:
· conflicting views concerning the impact of
culture or stage of cultural development on economic behaviour
- yes for the Marxists, no for the Platonic mainstream;
· conflicting theories of value, specifically
whether labour was the only productive factor of
production as Marxists believed or, whether capital was also productive as the
mainstream contended;
· conflicting beliefs in the efficacy of
collectivist solutions to political economic problems such as the Party as
revolutionary vanguard and the dictatorship of the proletariat versus
individualist solutions such as pluralistic democracy and the market mechanism;
· conflicting theories about the legitimacy of
private property deemed theft by Marxists or essential for civilized life by
the mainstream; and,
· conflicting views about
technology deemed the natural inheritance of all workers by Marxists or as any
change in knowledge that shifts the production function of a nation or firm as in
the Standard Model of economics. A.21 Having split the
world into two warring camps threatening nuclear annihilation for nearly half a
century, the philosophy of technology exists in engineering and humanist
traditions within Market and Marxist branches.
It awaits a new Robert Boyle to make the metaphysical compromise
necessary, to mend the schism, to heal the Fisher King as in the Grail Legend
(E. Jung & M-L von Franz 1970) After nearly a
century of military-industrial-ideological competition, technology today poses
questions affecting the future of all humanity. From climate change, human population
growth, species extinction to the genomics revolution, human manipulation of
space, time, matter and mind - technology - has reached global proportions. Humanity
reigns supreme but lacks a convincing design for governance of the planet. This will require a careful weaving of ‘can
do’ and ‘should do’ into the fabric of a tent big enough and strong enough to
accommodate the cultural and national diversity of human wants, needs and
desires. Calling Robert Boyle!
Chapter 6:
Form & Fixation An Aside on
the Metaphysics of Technology
[A] HHC: It
should be noted that the Oxford Dictionary reports first usage
of ‘technology’ in 1615 meaning:
“a discourse or treatise on an art or arts; the scientific study of the
practical or industrial arts.” (OED, technology, 1 a)
[B] [C] Of Bentham, Marshall wrote: “Another way in which he influenced the young economists around him was through his passionate desire for security. He was indeed an ardent reformer. He was an enemy of all artificial distinctions between different classes of men; he declared with emphasis that any one man's happiness was as important as any other's, and that the aim of all action should be to increase the sum total of happiness, he admitted that other things being equal, this sum total would be greater the more equally wealth was distributed. Nevertheless so full was his mind of the terror of the French Revolution, and so great were the evils which he attributed to the smallest attack on security that, daring analyst as he was, he felt himself and fostered in his disciples an almost superstitious reverence for the existing institutions of private property.” (Marshall 1920: 628, ft 2).
|