The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Edgar Zilsel
The Methods of Humanism *
Content |
|
1. The Professions of the Italian Humanists 1300-1600 2. Erudition, Fame and Mastery of Style – The Professional Ideals of the Humanists 3. Usefulness of Knowledge and Pride in Knowledge. The Psychological and Sociological Roots of Scholarship
5. The Humanists as Dispensers of Fame 7. The Humanists and the Scientific Literature |
[1943?] in Social Origins of Modern Science Edgar Zilsel, Diederick Raven, Wolfgang Krohn, R. S. Cohen
Kluwer Academic Publishers, ISBN: 0792364570
10/01/2000, 22-64 |
The first representatives of worldly learning in
the modern era were the Italian humanists. Humanism
is older than modern science. Though
they conform in some respects - both humanism and science deal with worldly
subject matters and proceed rationally - the two intellectual attitudes differ
hardly less from one another than science and scholasticism.
Just because of this contrast an
analysis of humanism can shed light on the characteristics of the scientific
spirit. As the methods of the
scholastics are understood best through the study of their professional tasks,
so the sociological analysis of humanism must start with the occupations and
professional aims of its representatives.
1. The
Professions of the Italian Humanists 1300-1600
The ancestors of the humanists are found among
the public officials and secretaries of the late medieval Italian cities.
In thirteenth century Italy merchants
and artisans, conscious of their worldly interests and their wealth, had
arisen. Numerous noblemen had moved
from their castles to the cities and in some cities, as in Florence, had even
turned to trading like burghers. Feudalism
which had settled all public affairs within the framework of the traditional
relations between the feudal lords, their vassals, and bondsmen, was
disintegrating. The advance of money
economy had considerably increased the tasks of public administration and
required public officials with rational training and juridical knowledge.
Also the intellectual world of the
feudal period, being substantially rural, could no longer satisfy the rising
townsmen. On the other hand, some
ancient traditions still survived in the doctrines of the church and
* [This essay has not been previously made
public. We know that a first version
of this essay was written before the summer of 1941 for in his ‘Report on the
present state of the study of Dr. Edgar Zilsel on the Sociological Roots of
Science’ of June 22, 1941, Zilsel mentions a MS on humanism and writes
“The Chapter on humanism and its conformities with and differences from
science is nearly ready for the press” (HP/Z).
In his first application to the American Philosophical Society
(APS) of October 28, 1941, Zilsel again mentions what we take to be the same
MS. This time he writes: “The section
of the relation ship of the scientific to the humanistic methods (about forty
typewritten pages) is nearly ready for the press”.
For reasons that are unclear to us
Zilsel did not publish this MS. In his
second application to the APS of February 28, 1943, he writes: “The section on
the methods of humanism (71 typewritten pages)... [is] ready for the press”.
We take this to be a reference to the
MS published here. Like he did in his
essay ‘Problems of Empiricism’ Zilsel makes use of what could be called
‘supporting evidence paragraphs’. In
the original MS these paragraphs are indicated to put into small print.
Following his practice in his
‘Problems of Empiricism’ we have put these paragraphs in the main text and
have not turned them into footnotes. Eds.]
22
the learning of the theologians.
Particularly in Italy where numerous
monuments testified to the grandeur of classical antiquity the memory of the
past was not dead. The Italian
burghers looked up with envy to the achievements of ancient Rome when their
own world appeared small and poor. It
is strange that a youthful society, faced with the task of building up an
intellectual culture of its own, looked back to the past.
Yet this “renaissance” - process, one
of the most impressive testimonies to the power of tradition in history, is
susceptible to sociological explanation. Ancient
civilization was but incompletely known to the Middle Ages.
The fundamental differences between
the nascent capitalistic society and the Roman republic of the Roman empire,
therefore, could not be noticed. It
was manifest, however, that classical civilization had been higher than the
contemporary and, being a worldly civilization of city dwellers, it fitted the
cultural desires of the trading noblemen and burghers better than the half
military, half rural culture of the knights and the religious ideals of the
monks. In the Flemish, French and
German cities this congeniality was not able to produce the humanistic
enthusiasm for antiquity; it was sufficient only later to make its adoption
possible after it had developed in Italy. In
the Italian cities, on the other hand, where the burghers considered
themselves the direct descendants of the ancient Romans, the sociological
congeniality was supplemented by patriotic pride in a past that was felt to be
their own. Rienzi, the son of a
tavern-keeper, thus could carry on his burgher insurrection against the Roman
nobility with ancient slogans and by imitating political institutions of the
Roman republic.
Rienzi was a political revolutionary and had no
literary aspirations. Before he had
himself proclaimed “tribune of the Roman people” in 1347 he had been a notary
of the Roman municipality and later of the Papal See at Avignon.
Other public notaries, enthusiasts or
classical antiquity, combined burgher patriotism with literary activity.
Half a century before Rienzi, Lovato
des Lovati, a contemporary of Dante, called himself “judge and poet of Padua”.
His disciple, Albertino Mussato,
proudly signed his letters as “poet and historiographer of Padua”.
He wrote a Latin tragedy composed in
the style of Seneca with a patriotic-political purpose and several Latin works
on contemporary history and moral philosophy.
By profession Mussato too was a city official: he was a notary public,
a member of the public council of Padua, and headed diplomatic legations of
his native city to the Pope and the Emperor (1302 and 1311).
From their legal education these
political city clerks knew more of ancient Rome than the artisans and
merchants. Hence they could express
the contrast between the new burgher culture and the world of feudalism by
ideals formed after ancient patterns and become, thus, the true initiators of
the “revival of learning”.
Usually Petrarch (1304-1374) is considered as
the first humanist. Though a friend
and admirer of Rienzi, he was more a literary man than a politician or
office-holder. He too, however, was
the son of a Florence notary, had studied law at Montpellier and Bologna, and
was often employed as a political ambassador by the Pope and the Archbishop of
Milan. Several times the position of
an apostolic secretary, that is of a permanent official of the curia,
23
was offered to him.
He made his living as a protege of
wealthy noble families (the protection of the Colonna family, however, was
lost by him, when he advocated the cause of Reinzi) and from numerous
ecclesiastical sinecures. Powerful
patrons - prelates, princes, and cities - competed for his services after he
had become famous. Petrarch’s friend
Boccaccio (1313-1375) was like Petrarch primarily a literary man, but also in
his life public offices play a certain part. He
was the son of a merchant and, before he turned to literature, a merchant
himself. As a young assistant to a
merchant he made contact with the scholar officials at the court of Naples.
After he had distinguished himself by
his literary activity and classical scholarship he was frequently employed as
ambassador by his native city, Florence. He
lived on his modest wealth and from an annual stipend, allowed to him by the
city of Florence for his public lectures on Dante.
The lives of both Petrarch and
Boccaccio show the close connection between office and scholarship in the
period of early humanism. In the
fourteenth century literary activity, if it did originate in governmental
activity, was at least rewarded by political offices.
Up to the sixteenth century numerous Italian
humanists were chancellors, secretaries, and officials of princes, cities, and
the curia. The humanist office-holders
chiefly had to conduct the foreign affairs of their employers.
Their offices, however, tended to
become sinecures. More and more
humanists developed into court historians, court orators, and court poets or
free literati dependent on princes, noblemen, and bankers as patrons.
Others were engaged as tutors of the
sons and, sometimes, the daughters of princes, or founded schools for children
of noblemen. Or they travelled from
city to city giving lecture-courses on classical authors to older students,
the lectures being paid by the municipalities.
Several humanists held academic chairs.
At the universities, however, the
spirit of scholasticism still predominated. The
medieval and Renaissance universities were not devoted to research but to
teaching: they were but institutes for the theoretical training of clerics,
notaries and attorneys, and physicians; the seven liberal arts - grammar,
rhetoric, dialectic, arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and music - were at most
universities not completely represented and everywhere regarded as merely
preparatory subjects preceding the true, that is professional, training.
The humanists in the Faculties of Arts
- for them the first three of the liberal arts came into consideration - were,
consequently, less esteemed and paid considerably less than the theologians,
jurists, and medical doctors. Usually
the humanistic teachers of “eloquence” were engaged for one year only and were
more like travelling lecturers than permanent professors.
Most of the fifteenth century
humanists, however, took the occupations as professors, lecturers, and
political secretaries alternately, and even the court poets and free literati
were, at least occasionally, employed as political ambassadors by their
patrons. Such court positions,
connected with occasional official missions but without office and university
routine, were best liked by the humanists.
24
A few humanists became bishops and cardinals and
one - Enea Silvio Piccolomini - even pope, the secretarial activity was the
start of their ecclesiastical careers. Before
the invention of printing the copying of ancient manuscripts offered the
possibility of a livelihood to many humanistic scholars.
(In the university cities there had
been professional copyists even in the scholastic period).
After the establishment of the first
printing press in Italy in 1465 many humanists worked with printers as
assistants, editors, and proofreaders. The
great printer of classical texts, Aldo Manuzio (1450-1514) employed over
thirty classical scholars and was himself humanistically educated.
He had been a tutor to the nephews of
the count della Mirandola before he became a printer.
Besides there were a few exceptional
cases. Niccolo Niccoli (d. 1437), the scholarly collector of manuscripts,
whose home was the center of the humanist circle in Florence, was the son of a
trading nobleman and originally a merchant himself, he later lived without
occupation on his modest wealth. Marsilio
Ficino (1433-1499), the son of the physician to Cosimo Medici, was from his
boyhood educated to become the head of the “Platonic Academy”, lived as such
in the house of Lorenzo Medici, and was ordained as priest in his old age.
At the end of the fifteenth century
the above-mentioned Giovanni Pico della Mirandola and his nephew Francesco
were rich counts. Vespasiano da
Bisticci was a humanist bookseller in the fifteenth, and so was the
archaeologist Jacopo Mazochi in the sixteenth centuiy; the former still had
despised the printing press. Ciriaco
de’ Pizicolli (d. 1450), the collector of Roman inscriptions, was a
travelling merchant. A few humanists
were monks. In the sixteenth century
the humanistic travelling lecturers, free literati, and political secretaries
gradually disappeared. Since such
positions were no longer available, in the later half of the century the
humanist university professors regarded teaching as their permanent
profession: the type of erudite and pedantic philology professor that
flourished in 17th century France and Holland began to develop.
Our survey refers to the Italian
humanists only until the end of the sixteenth century; the humanists outside
Italy will be discussed later.
The following list of occupations from Petrarch
to 1600 is based chiefly on Georg Voigt: Die Wiederbelebung des classischen
Alteriums, 3rd ed. Berlin 1893; J.A. Symonds: The Renaissance in
Italy, vol. 2: The Revival of Learning. The Modern Library, New
York; J.E. Sandys: A History of Classical Scholarship, vol. 2,
Cambridge 1904; and the Enciclopedia Italiana.
Political secretaries and officials:
Giovanni di Conversino (1347-1406, secretary
of Petrarch, chancellor of Ragusa and Carrara, professor at Florence, vagabond
humanist), Zanobi da Strada (cf. below p. 11), Coluccio Salutati (1331-1406,
assistant to an apostolic secretary, chancellor of Florence), Aurispa
(1369-1459, prebends, temporarily apostolic secretary), Loschi (1365-1441,
prebends, chancellor of Ferrera, apostolic secretary and protonotary),
Lionardo Bruni (1369-1443, apostolic secretary, chancellor of Florence), Carlo
Marsuppino (1398-1453, professor of eloquence, chancellor of Florence, title
of an apostolic secretary), Gianozzo Manetti (1396-1459, Florentine nobleman,
wealthy merchant, and ambassador; at the court of Naples; apostolic
secretary), Flavio Biondo (1388-1463, apostolic secretary), Lorenzo Valla
(1407-1457,
25
professor of eloquence, secretary of King
Alfonso of Naples, apostolic scriptor), Pier Candido Decembrio (1399-1477),
apostolic secretary; at the Milan court), Poggio Bracciolini (1380-1459,
copyist, apostolic secretary, chancellor of Florence), Bartolomeo Facio
(1401-1457, teacher, later chancellor in Genoa, secretary and historiographer
to the King of Naples), Benedetto Accolti (1415-1466, professor of civil law
at Siena, chancellor of Florence), Platina (1421-1481, tutor, secretary to
Cardinal Gonzaga, abbreviator apostolicus).
Lecturers and university professors:
Manuel Chrysoloras (d. 1415, Greek
ambassador to Venice, 1396 Greek chair at the University of Florence),
Argyropulos (after 1456 lecturing on Greek and philosophy at Florence and
Rome), Georgios Trapezuntios (after 1420 Greek lectures at various
universities), Theodorus Gaza (1400-1448, Greek chairs at Ferrara and Rome),
Poliziano (1454-1494, professor of eloquence, tutor to the son of Lorenzo
Medici), Pomponio Leto (chair of eloquence Rome), Pomponazzi (1462-1524,
professor of philosophy), Alciato (1492-1550, professor of civil law at
various universities), Leonicus Thomaeus (after 1497 professor of philosophy
at Padua), Mario Nizolio (1498-1576, professor of philosophy at Parma and
Sabionetta), Robortelli (1516-1567, professor of eloquence at various
universities), Sigonio (1524-1584, professor of eloquence at various
universities).
Educators:
Gasparino da Barzizza (d. 1431, professor of
eloquence at Padua, court orator to Filippo Maria Visconti, the tyrant of
Milan; principal of a school at Milan), Guarino (1370-1460, professor of
eloquence at various universities, tutor to the son of the Duke of Ferrera and
principal of a school), Vittorino da Feltre (1378-1446, professor of eloquence
at Padua, principal of a school for the sons of the Marquess of Gonzaga and
other children).
Free literati:
Beccadelli-Panormita (1394-1471, lecturing in
Bologna and Pavia; receiving presents; at the court of the King of Naples,
tutor to the crown prince and often ambassador), Porcellio (born 1406,
historiographer to the condottiere Malatesta and the King of Naples, vagabond
humanist); Filelfo (1398-1481, professor of eloquence at the University of
Padua, lecturing in Venice, secretary at the Constantinople imperial court and
in a Byzantine legation to the sultan and the kings of Hungary and Poland,
lecturing in Venice, professor of eloquence in Bologna and Florence, receiving
presents, professor of eloquence in Rome, died impoverished in Florence),
Pontano (1426-1503, at the court of Naples: secretary, ambassador, tutor).
Prelates:
Bessarion (1403-1472, Greek archbishop of Niccea,
converted to catholicism at the council of Florence, cardinal), Enea Silvio
Piccolomini (1405-1464, secretary in the Vienna imperial chancery, bishop,
cardinal, pope), Marco Musuro (d. 1517, professor of eloquence at Padua,
assistant to the printer Manuzio, bishop of Malvasia), Paolo Giovio
(1483-1552, physician in Milan, apostolic secretary, bishop of Nocera), Bembo
(1470-1547, at the courts of Ferrara and Urbino, apostolic secretary,
cardinal), Sadoleto (1477-1547, apostolic secretary, bishop, cardinal),
Aleander (1480-1542, professor of eloquence in Paris, librarian of the
Vatican, apostolic nuntius to Germany, archbishop, cardinal).
Monks:Luigi
Marsili (1330-1394, Augustinian), Ambrogio Traversari (after 1431 General of
the Camaldolentic order).
26
2. Erudition, Fame and
Mastery of Style –
The Professional Ideals of the Humanists
The professional group of the humanists arose
from the diplomatic and administrative needs of the early capitalistic cities
and principalities. Florence, whose
municipal offices in the thirteenth century had been known as the best place
for public notaries to acquire higher training, became in the fifteenth
century the center of humanism.
From 1375 to 1466 Florence had seven chancellors: five of them - Salutati,
Lionardo Bruni, Carlo Marsuppini, Poggio, and Benedetto Accolti - were famous
humanists. The fact, however, that
everywhere in Italy the humanistic offices turned into sinecures and the
office-holders into literati shows that the original needs were supplemented
by others of a less vital character. With
growing wealth analogous processes frequently occur in social evolution.
In the case of the humanists it was
the desire for prestige that came into play - prestige, incidentally, being in
politics hardly less useful than efficiency of office work.
The political secretary and ambassador
was required to increase the prestige of his employer and this secondary
function gradually became primary. Since
the office-holder was working with his pen, his tongue, and his brain, the
prestige he could give was based on his style, his eloquence, and his
learning. Naturally, classical
antiquity presented the literary models and the sources and contents of the
erudition. Hence mastery of style,
learning and prestige became the professional ideals of the humanists.
The embryonic stage of these ideals is
disclosed in a passage in Giovanni Villani’s chronicle on a thirteenth century
public official. It reads: Brunetto
Latini, the chancellor of Florence, “was the first to teach the Florentines
the rudiments and to make them skilled in well speaking and the
knowledge of how to govern our republic according to the art of politics”.
Both Latini and Villani still belong
more to the Middle Ages than the modern era. Latini
was born half a century before Dante; his Latin still is entirely medieval and
his cyclopedias epitomize the learning of scholasticism.
Villani, the contemporary of Petrarch,
is a merchant and, consequently, hardly touched by the spirit of humanism.
Yet he praises the late medieval city
clerk as the pioneer of worldly learning and eloquence: two of the three
ideals which we are analyzing appear as early as in this voice from the very
dawn of the modern era. The public
officials turned into humanists a century later, when they put the tasks of
public administration, still emphasized in Villani, in the background behind
their function as givers of prestige. The
humanists, who in the Renaissance crowded the office of the Papal See and the
Italian princes and cities, wanted to have as little as possible to do with
office routine. Most of them, of
course not the Florentine chancellors, were employed primarily for display as
official orators, ambassadors, and authors of polished diplomatic notes.
Besides there were other clerks,
trained in civil or canon law, who did the real office work.
The humanists, however, despised the
jurists because of their lack of eloquence and, at the same time, envied them
their higher salaries and greater influence. When
27
the problems of public administration multiplied
under the pressure of growing capitalism the public officials for mere display
disappeared and were again replaced by jurists in the late sixteenth century.
The sociological reasons why the officials chose
classical authors as literary models have been indicated above pp. 19ff.
We repeat the dates of the officials
and authors mentioned: Brunetto Latini 1220-1294, Lovati 1236-1309, Dante
1265-1321, Mussato 1261-1329, Giovanni Villani’s chronicle about 1345, Rienzi
1313-1354, Petrarch 1304-1374. On the
reputation of the Florentine notaries, the chancellors of Florence 1375-1466,
and Villani’sjudgement on Latini cf. Georg Voigt: opere cit. (l891)
1392.
When in 1329, Petrarch who often was temporarily
employed as official ambassador once aspired to a permanent position as
apostolic secretary he had to undergo an examination in the papal business
style. Since his Ciceronian style was
found too pompous he failed (cf. Ibid. II, 4).
Petrarch’s failure seems to indicate
that the humanistic ideals have originated rather elsewhere than in the office
and invaded it only later. Actually,
office routine always and everywhere is very conservative.
The new, specific humanistic style
was, therefore, first used by men as Petrarch and Boccaccio who were not
ordinary and permanent officials. Yet,
not only did all of them have close contacts with offices, but also
appreciation of literary skill and worldly learning first arose among
office-holders in modem civilization. In
1358, six years after Petrarch’s failure, a certain Zanobi da Strada, was as
the first true humanist permanently employed in the Papal chancery.
Zanobi had been a Latin teacher in
Florence and a political secretary of the King of Naples before he became
apostolic protonotary. Petrarch’s
admirer, Coluccio Salutati, entered the municipal office of Florence after a
legal training in 1373.
The skills of the humanistic secretaries were
required also for the humanists who had developed into free literati.
In all periods in which authors or
artists are not yet dependent on a large public but on individual patrons, the
protege has the sociological function of increasing the prestige of his
protector. The writer humanist was
maintained by a prince, a pope, a city tyrant, or banker.
The more impressive his writings were
and the more famous he became the more fame redounded to his patron.
Viewed sociologically, the
writer-humanists were primarily “dispensers of fame”: in the dedications of
their works they took care adequately to fulfill this task.
The humanistic professors, lecturers,
and schoolmen, finally, are but a necessary consequence of this development;
when a special group of professional dispensers of fame has monopolized the
intellectual leadership of the age and attracts gifted young people, teachers
who prepare for this profession must develop, and the upper classes must feel
the desire to make also their children familiar with the new spirit, too.
Altogether mastery of style,
erudition, and fame are the specific professional ideals of humanism in all
its varieties and, manifestly, the secretarial office is the soil from which
they have sprung.
Among the humanists there were followers of all
kinds of philosophies. Although there
were Platonists and Aristotelians, idealists and Epicurean materialists,
orthodox Catholics, a few admirers of the Cabbalah, and many irreligious
freethinkers, pornographers and highly moral family men: they all
28
shared the three ideals of fame, perfection of
style, and classical erudition. And
they agreed only in these ideals - and, of course, in the veneration of
classical antiquity. The three
professional ideals of humanism, therefore, must be discussed in greater
detail. Though mastery of style is the
basic element in the triad, we shall start with the analysis of erudition,
since this is comparatively nearest to the aims of science.
The differences between phenomena that
are nearest to one another usually are most instructive.
Knowledge is esteemed by man for two different
reasons. First, in numerous
cases, knowledge is useful biologically. He
who knows where food can be found is superior, biologically, to the man who is
ignorant of this fact. Since one
must know the causes to be able to produce desired effects this biological
usefulness applies to knowledge chiefly of causes and physical laws, that is
of recurrent associations of phenomena. Viewed
more accurately, even the given illustration implies a regular connection
between quite a number of facts. He
who knows the habitat of an edible plant knows that at a place with certain
properties always or frequently certain objects are found which, if eaten,
appease hunger. It is not a single
fact but a recurrent association of several phenomena that is known and proves
useful to him. This kind of knowledge
plays a decisive part in all economic acts, in technology and all crafts and,
obviously, is the biological basis and economic root of science.
A man who, faced with the task of
lifting a load, studies the law of the lever may be taken as the archetype of
the scientist. As has been proclaimed
by Francis Bacon, knowledge is power: it enables man to control nature.
Since control of processes is based on
the ability to predict them and since all actions point to the future,
scientific knowledge tends to refer to the future.
At any rate it aims at general
statements. Universal implications are
its adequate logical expressions: always, if certain conditions, A, are
realized, certain phenomena, B, occur
Man is a social animal.
It is a matter of course, therefore,
that the man who possesses useful knowledge enjoys social esteem, just as the
strong are more highly esteemed than the weak, the skilful more highly than
the awkward. It is remarkable,
however, that knowledge also of disconnected facts which are of no use at all
can be the object of social esteem and considerable pride.
The origin of this pride implies a
problem. It is not the well known
sublimation of values that we have here in mind.
Rather often activities, originally
esteemed only because of their usefulness, later become values per Se.
In this way, on a higher cultural
level, scientific investigation of causes is esteemed for its own sake.
This sublimation is not only
understandable, psychologically, but also quite indispensable.
Many abstract theories, developed
without regard to any use,
29
only later have met with practical application;
satisfaction even of the practical needs of society, therefore, can not be
safeguarded unless science, i.e. knowledge of causes and laws, is esteemed as
a value per Se. All this is well known
and does not need further discussion. On
the other hand, it implies a problem: how it happens that so many people are
proud of knowing isolated facts unknown to others.
Why are these polyhistors conceited?
Whoever has observed quarrelling
scholars and the ardor with which they endeavor to clear themselves of the
suspicion of some very unimportant ignorance will not doubt that pride in
knowledge can be a strangely strong motive of human behavior.
This motive is not restricted to the ranks of
scholars. Otherwise it could not be
explained why crossword puzzles, “quizzes”, and similar opportunities to
display one’s knowledge of entirely useless details have met with such
popularity. Certainly a social motive
plays a part in this appeal. When one
succeeds in such tests one is considered “educated” and the lower ranks of
society are characterized by lack of education: nobody wishes to be counted
among them. But behind this additional
motive the original problem reappears. Why
is it that in all civilized nations accumulation of knowledge, not referring
to any practical needs, is a component of higher education and gives certain
social privileges? Knowledge of
isolated facts is obviously a luxury. Certainly
any fact can, occasionally, become a stepping stone to later knowledge of
causes; no detail is so unimportant that this possibility can ever be excluded
in advance. The possibility, however,
is too indirect to explain why erudition is considered a value.
What is, for example, the use of knowing the
names of rare and remote objects? Do
primeval ideas come into play here? Primitive
societies believe in word magic and are convinced that things can be
influenced by pronouncing their names. Before
technology had separated from magic, knowledge of names could, therefore, be
considered just as useful as knowledge of causes.
The medicine man had to know even the
most secret names: he had to undergo a specific training, his occupation was
probably the first profession, and he and his colleagues formed the first
privileged group in human society. The
analogy between a modern “quiz” contestant who is proud of his knowing the
names of the nine Muses, a Renaissance humanist, and a medicine man believing
in word magic may appear artificial. Yet
pride in knowledge is, sociologically, a primitive, psychologically, an
infantile trait. It most probably
originates in the fact that children are both weak and ignorant and look up to
their father, who not only protects but also teaches them.
To him they ascribe both surpassing
strength and surpassing knowledge. All
children want to be like the father: they want to be grown up and, certainly,
showing knowledge is as good a proof of one’s being grown up as proving one’s
strength. This motive becomes
particularly manifest in children who are proud of knowing the facts about
birth and procreation. There is no
evidence that all pride in knowledge derives from the infantile pride in
sexual knowledge. The infantile
desire, however, to be grown up like the father offers the best if not the
only explanation of the remarkable
30
phenomenon that even quite useless knowledge is
esteemed by men. All men have been
children and once have looked up to their fathers.
In many cases the relation of man to his ideals
and authorities mirrors the relation of the child to the grown up and,
particularly, the father. Gods are
always imagined superior to man both in power and knowledge.
In the monotheistic religions,
together with omnipotence, omniscience is attributed to the deity.
The same attributes appear among the
professional ideals of some of the most ancient professions.
The medicine man, the priest, and
after the invention of writing, the scribe (as in ancient Egypt) all laid
claim to superior knowledge. Since in
primitive civilisations every knowledge is still believed to be useable for
magic, usefulness of and pride in knowledge can not yet be separated in the
case of the medicine man. The wisdom
of the priest, too, may have, originally, been used for magical purposes.
The case is different with the scribe.
The secular scribes in ancient Egypt
had nothing to do with magic and proved useful in public administration and in
administration of the big estates. Both
the priests and the scribes, however, were privileged groups.
They were in the position,
consequently, to disregard practical utility and based their claims to social
esteem more on the superiority than the usefulness of their knowledge:
especially the Egyptian scribes were exceedingly proud of knowing more than
the ignorant common people, as the precepts of the scribe Duauf to his son
Pepi disclose. Together with the
medicine man, the priest and the secular scribe are the most ancient scholars.
In prescientific civilizations
practically useful knowledge appears almost exclusively in the form of
technological skill in the lower ranks of society, namely among the despised
artisans. It is a remarkable
phenomenon but it hardly can be doubted that social esteem of the mere volume
of knowledge is older than esteem of its utility: scholarship is older than
science.
Egyptian scribes, proud of their knowledge cf.
A. Erman: Agypten und agyptisches Leben im Altertum, ed. H. Ranke,
Tuebingen 1923, pp. 374f., pp. 443, 448; looking down upon artists and
artisans, Ibid, pp. 504, 533.
Scholars are proud of knowing as many facts as
possible. In prescientific theoretical
literature there is, therefore, a tendency to the accumulation of unconnected
details. Thus the compilations and
cyclopedias are composed that are so characteristic of the medieval
scholastics and all priestly scholars when they turn to secular subject
matters. Scientific connection of
facts by general implications is still unknown in periods of mere scholarship.
Even today this prescientific form of
theoretical activity prevails in works ordering their contents alphabetically.
The Nouveau Petit Larousse Illustre,
for example, the most popular French dictionary, gives definitions of all
words. Under the heading “mer” it
explains that the sea is “a vast accumulation of salt water covering the
greater part of the globe”. Under the
heading “mere” it says that a mother is “a woman who has given birth to one or
several children”. Although such
dictionary articles are familiar to us, it is worthwhile to question their
31
ends. Manifestly
the definitions given are practically useless, since every Frenchmen knows the
meanings of both headings and non-Frenchmen who do not know them understand
the French definitions even less. Where
then do they originate? The
addictedness to exact definitions would indicate a survival of the scholastic
spirit. The sentence, however, given
to illustrate the second definition, clearly points to humanism as the
historical source of the method used: “Agrippinna”, the dictionary says, “was
the mother of Nero”. In prescientific
civilizations fledgling scholars learned in this way what a mother is.
Even after the rise of science,
however, the spirit of scholasticism and humanism survives in many fields,
especially in education.
A French dictionary has been selected as example
since the humanistic spirit is especially strong in French education.
- Our remarks were not intended to
advocate practical utility as the only aim of education.
As mentioned above, not even in the
merely intellectual training of a scientist would this goal be sufficient.
In addition, education aims at
development of emotional patterns always at least as much as the training of
technicians and theorists. Particularly
the advocates of humanistic education have always stressed emotional and
esthetic values: classical culture is connected, by indissoluble links, with
western religion, literature and art. We
have, however, not to discuss goals of education but to describe sociological
facts and to compare the intellectual procedures of science and scholarship.
A remarkable relation to time must be
disregarded. Science originates in the
needs of action and action points to the future.
The scientist, being primarily
interested in recurrent associations of events, endeavors to predict what will
happen if certain conditions are realized: he tries to extrapolate the
regularities observed in the past to the past.
The scholar, on the other hand, is primarily interested in the past.
Factual knowledge is based on
experience and tradition, that is on recollection of’ past events.
When the scholar is proud of knowing
disconnected facts and of knowing as many of them as possible, he inevitably
must turn to the great receptacle of facts: the past.
History, archeology, philology,
therefore, are the very fields of scholarship.
Hence a noteworthy difference between science and scholarship results.
Scientific zeal is frequently linked
to progressive ideas. The more the
scientist stresses action and the more he regards science, as Francis Bacon
did, as a means of controlling and changing events the more science develops
into a tool of progress. Sometimes
science was, and more frequently it was considered, even a tool of revolution.
Erudition and scholarship, on the
other hand, are eminently conservative. This
becomes manifest as early as in the most ancient representatives of the
scholarly professions: the medicine man, the priest-scholar, the Egyptian and
Babylonian scribe, all were custodians of tradition.
Just as pride of knowledge,
apparently, is older than esteem of its usefulness, so, in the social
development of knowledge, the conservative tendency precedes the progressive
one. Both phenomena originate in the
division of society into subgroups. Learning
and preservation of tradition are specific ideals of certain, numerically
small, professional groups. To the
whole of society action, utility of knowledge, and
32
progress are more important.
The historical development, however,
is determined rather by interaction of social subgroups than by the interests
of an abstract whole of society.
In the case of Renaissance humanism the
retrospective tendency of the scholars met halfway with certain progressive
desires of the rising middle classes. The
burghers tended to detachment from the feudal past; they were, however,
ignorant and still unable to settle their problems intellectually by their own
means. The scholars, on the other
hand, looked back to antiquity. Yet
the retrospective learning of the scholars had something to offer to the
burghers. The link between the two
apparently opposite tendencies was formed, as we have pointed out before, by
the urban and worldly character of both the classical and the early
capitalistic civilization. Thus the
birth of the new city culture, intellectually, took the shape of a
“Renaissance” and a “revival”. The
revival of learning appears “reactionary” when we view only the words of the
humanists; it points to the future in so far as it expresses cultural desires
of the new middle classes - to which, after all, the humanists themselves
belonged. However, the technical needs
of manufacture and trade eventually proved stronger than the professional
ideals of a few scholar-officials and literati: humanism declined and
scholarship was superseded by science in the seventeenth century.
After having discussed the characteristic
features of scholarship in general it is easy to demonstrate them in
Renaissance humanism in particular. Since
we are interested in the sociological origins we shall restrict ourselves
primarily to the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries.
In the humanist, pride in knowledge is
expressed by a deep contempt for the non-scholars.
Petrarch would rather be not
understood than extolled by the multitude; as he explains, it is a disgrace to
the learned to be praised by the mob. Coluccio
Salutati, the chancellor of Florence (1331-1406), points out that knowledge
and eloquence distinguish man from beast and man from man; in this respect,
however, the distance between man and man is even greater than between man and
beast. The terms Salutati uses
-wisdom, eloquence, intelligence - are obviously meant to characterize the
humanist and manifestly, in his opinion, the scholar is further above the
non-humanist than man above the beast.
Petrarch, epist. famil. XIV, 2 (ed.
Fracassetti, vol. I, p. 279); cf. Ibid. I, 7 (vol. I, p. 63).
Salutati, Epistolario, ed. F. Novati in Instituto Storico hal.,
Fonti 15-18, I, 77, 79, II, p. 204.
The contrast between the theoretical aims of
humanism and of science stands out most distinctly in the tendency of the
early humanists towards accumulating scraps of knowledge without theoretical
connection. Thus Petrarch wrote “On
33
things to be remembered” and “On famous men”.
Boccaccio on “The genealogies of the
pagan gods”, on “The vicissitudes of famous men”, on “Famous women”, on
“Mountains, woods and rivers”. In the
merely enumerative method these compilations agree with the numerous “summae”
of the scholastics, and, especially, with the late medieval cyclopedias for
laymen, such as the Trésor of Brunetto Latini.
The only difference is that the humanist compilations drew the facts
from a considerably greater number of classical authors and replaced the
medieval Latin with Ciceronian style. In
the fifteenth century these half medieval compilations develop, on the one
hand, into essays such as Poggio’s On the vicissitudes of Fortune and
On the calamities of princes, on the other, to learned archaeological
encyclopedias such as Biondo’s Roma Instaurata, Roma Triumphans, and
Italia Illustrata that were the forerunners of the modern handbooks of
classical archeology. Even as late as
in 1506 Rafael Volaterranus wrote a encyclopedia, Commentarii Urbani,
which tried to comprehend the whole of humanistic knowledge in three volumes,
entitled geography, anthropology and philology.
Volaterranus’ work differs from a
modem encyclopedia by the absence of scientific criticism and alphabetic
order, from the medieval cyclopedias for laymen by the fact that it abounds
with veneration of classical antiquity. Also,
collections of biographies and lists of celebrities are very numerous in
Renaissance literature. Among them are
several collections of famous women and such a strange work as Manetti’s six
books On famous long-lived persons (c. 1450) in which the lifes of
“all” celebrities who reached the age of sixty years, from Adam to the
humanist Niccoli, are described. A
tendency to collection of curiosities is rather manifest in humanist
literature from Petrarch up to the beginning of the sixteenth century.
The encyclopedia of Volaterranus was widely
read. The Catalogue of Printed
Books of the British Museum gives seven Latin editions and one Italian
translation between 1506 and 1603. On
collections of biographies cf. Edgar Zilsel: Die Entstehung des
Geniebegriffes, Tuebingen 1926, pp. 159-175.
Collections of curiosities: Domenico
di Bandino d’Arezzo: Fons memorabilium universi (c. 1370); Gulilelmus
Pastrengo (a friend of Petrarch): De originibus rerum (printed Venice
1547; deals with inventors, founders of cities, ancient offices and names
etc.); Polydorus Vergilius: De rerum inventoribus, Venice 1499 (deals
with comparatively few technological inventors, but reports on the genesis of
writing, marriage, prostitution, various sects, etc.
For the greater part it gives fabulous
stories and myths collected without any criticism.
It appeared from 1499 to 1680 in at
least 20 Latin editions and 12 translations); Sabellicus: De rerum et
artium inventoribus (a poem printed in 1560); Alexander Sardus: De
rerum inventoribus (intends to fill the gaps in the work of Polydorus
Vergilius); Pierio Valeriano (d. 1558): De infelicitate literatorum
(printed 1620; a collection of biographies of “unhappy” literati).
Reference works, encyclopedias, and tables are
required also in modern science. They
are not regarded, however, as the true achievements of science but contain
only the material from which the scientific structures are built.
A
34
considerable part of the humanist literature, on
the other hand, resembles such collections of material, rather inadequately
arranged, while scientific elaborations are absent.
The deficiencies of humanism are best
illustrated by a comparison with a contemporary pioneer of the really
scientific spirit. In 1554 Niccolo
Tartaglia mentions the rule for the solution of equations of the third degree,
discovered by him. He tells how he,
fortunately, found the method after a rival in a mathematical competition had
set him several problems leading to cubic equations.
If he had not discovered the rule he
would have been blamed “by the ignorant crowd but certainly not by intelligent
people”. For, as he adds, “one
particular secret does not make a man a scientist, because science deals with
general rather than with particular subjects; the number of the particular
subjects is infinite and it is not possible, consequently, to know every one
of them”. This is the voice of a
representative of the true modern era. As
self evident as Tartaglia’s remark sounds to us, one will meet with a similar
remark in none of all the humanists. Much
too proud of their erudition to regard the slightest scrap of knowledge as
unimportant, they knew as little of the difference between fruitful and
sterile insights as the medieval scholastics.
This is a decisive difference between humanism and science.
Humanism, and all prescientific
scholarship, esteems the mere volume of learning; scientists appreciate
knowledge only if it results in further knowledge.
In the case of Tartaglia the question
is of a general mathematical rule but in the same desire to make knowledge
work and bear fruit Galileo’s general physical laws also have their origin.
Tartaglia, by the way, was also one of
the forerunners of Galileo in the investigation of mechanical laws.
He was, of course, not a humanist but
wrote in the Venetian vernacular and belonged rather with the artisans.
This remarkable man was a self
educated mathematics teacher who sold mathematical advice to gunners and
architects, ten pennies one question, and had to litigate with his customers
when they gave him a worn out cloak for his lectures on Euclid instead of the
payment agreed upon.
Tartaglia on the scientific insignificance of
particular subjects Quesiti et inventioni diversi IX, 25 (Venice 1554,
fol. 106 v.); “ten pennies (scudi) a question” Ibid. III, 10 (fol. 42
r.); the worn out cloak Travagliata inventione, Venice 1551, appendix
terzo ragionamento (sig. F ij v.).
The merely accumulative and enumerative method
of humanism manifests itself also in other traits.
Even those works that are not just
compilations are always interwoven with unnecessary references to classical
authors. Manifestly, the Renaissance
scholars used every occasion to display their classical reading.
By citation reputation as a scholar
was acquired. In a contemporary report
on the first lecture at the University of Florence of Carlo Marsuppini the
later chancellor is expressly praised in that “there was no Greek nor Roman
author from whom he did not quote”. By
this, the biographer adds, “he gave a great proof of his memory”.
The emphasis upon memory is significant.
The official speeches which the
political secretaries were required to deliver on the occasion
35
of princely weddings, coronations, and
diplomatic missions had to be made from memory.
Otherwise they would not have befitted
the festive occasions and would not have gained credit for the employers of
the speakers. A good memory,
therefore, belonged to the professional requirements of a humanist.
From the fourteenth century, when
Petrarch dedicated a chapter of his book On the Remedies for the
Vicissitudes of Fortune to the praise of memory; good memory was mentioned
time and again when the eminent gifts of a famous author were enumerated.
To scientists too a good memory is
useful; yet it would never be counted among the characteristics of a good
scientist in a scientific age. As
early as in the fifteenth century Leonardo da Vinci, who was not a humanist
but on artist-engineer, that is a superior craftsman, had the scientific
attitude towards memory: “who ever appeals to authority, he says, applies not
his intellect but his memory”. Galileo
and Descartes also scoffed at the humanistic esteem for memory and, in
contrast to it, stressed causal reasoning and mathematical demonstration.
The report on Marsuppini in Vespasiano da
Bisticci: Vite; Petrarch’s chapter on memory in De remediis
utriusque fortunae I, 8; Leonardo on the contrast intellect-memory.
Analogous passages in Galileo and
Descartes cf. below p. 42; qualities of eminent authors were frequently
enumerated. Instances: Boccaccio,
Eulogy of Petrarch (printed in Petrarch, De remediis, Rotterdam
1649, at the beginning): Petrarch was distinguished by his “innate gifts (ingenium)
and his memory”; Boccaccio, Opere volg, Firenze 1833, XV, 49:
Dante was distinguished by his “capacity, memory, intellect, innate
gifts (ingegno), and invention”; Alberti, Opusc. mor., ed. Bartoli,
Venice 1568, p. 160: authors of eminent “memory, mind, and innate gifts
(ingegno)” are very rare; Erasmus, Ciceronianus (1528) in Opera,
Basel 1540, 1, 829: eminent authors are distinguished by “invention,
arrangement of ideas, imagination, emotion, charm, memory, learning,
spirit and genius”; Trissino, Poetics (1563), in Opera, Verona
1729, II, 120: Dante was distinguished by his “memory, his innate gifts
(ingenium), his marvellous nature, and his learning”.
To people who appreciate memory so highly, the
past means more than the future. The
merchants, artisans, and navigators of the Renaissance must have been
conscious of the newness of their achievements and their age; otherwise they
could not have accomplished the complete transformation of feudal technology
and economy. From artists - who
belonged with the artisans -we have a few remarks expressing such sense of
youth. The literati, on the other
hand, felt aged and tired even at the very beginnings of humanism.
As early as in the 14th century
Petrarch complains of the lack of eminent men and contrasts “the misery of his
century” with the grandeur of classical antiquity.
His friend, Salutati, points out that
the authors of the period do not produce anything new; we are, he says,
“botchers only, patching together garments from pieces of classical cloth”.
Similar expressions of resignation
recur frequently in humanist writings. We
are but diminutive men (homunculi) exclaims Lionardo Bruni (c. 1400) and the
same term in Greek translation (anthropiskoi) is repeated in Bessarion (1462).
Only the ancients, particularly the
ancient authors, are in the
36
opinion of the humanists real men.
This senile attitude of the literati
is among the strangest phenomena in the rise of the new society.
How it derives from the professional
ideals of the scholars has been explained before.
Probably it is a somewhat artificial
product and may be compared to a flourish by which the scribe attests his
professional dignity.
Feeling of decay in Petrarch, Epist, famil.,
ed. Fracassetti VI, 4, vol. I, 336 ff., cf. ibid. I, 1); Salutati’s
remark quoted in Karl Vossler: Poetische Theorien der Fruehrenaissance,
p. 54; Bruni’s remark ibid. 82; Bessario’s remark in a Greek letter to
Apostolios (Migne, Pairologia, Patres Graeci, CLXI, 688 ff.).
The sense of inferiority to antiquity is the
emotional background of both the literary and the philosophical method of
humanism. In their ideas of literary
style the humanists virtually never got beyond the ideal of imitation.
They occasionally disagreed on the
question as to whether the perfect writer has to imitate one author - Cicero -
or better imitates several classical models alternately.
The idea, however, that writers could
have their own personal style, though a familiar notion to a plebeian author
such as Pietro Aretino, who wrote in the vernacular, occurred extremely seldom
to learned humanists. And in their
philosophical quarrels they always uncritically refer to their ancient
authorities and attack the authorities of their opponents.
Even if once a scholar tries to
conciliate, as Bessarion did in the quarrel between the Platonists and
Aristotelians of his period, he pleads for eclecticism and without
discrimination proclaims all philosophers of antiquity as authorities that, by
a modern, must be followed, not attacked. Just
in this context the modern thinkers were called “diminutive men” by Bessarion,
as mentioned above. The notion of
autonomous investigation of truth, manifestly, was foreign to humanism.
Laurentius Valla only (about 1450)
occasionally advocated philosophical originality, Johannes and his nephew
Franciscus Pico originality of literary style (about 1500).
Imitation of Cicero advocated in Paolo Cortese’s
letter to Poliziano (the letter before the last in Politianus, Opera,
Basel 1553); likewise Bembo in his letter to Joh. Franc. Pico (Bembo,
Opera: Basel without date III, 17 ff.); eclectic imitation of several
authors advocated in Joh. Franc. Pico’s letter to Bembo (in Pico, Opera
II, 123 f., contained also in Bembo, bc. cit. III, 3 ff.); likewise
Erasmus of Rotterdam, Ciceronianus (Opera, Basle 1540, 1, 820 ff.).
Personal style advocated in Pietro
Aretino, Lettere I, 123; cf. I, 82 and 114; III, 176.
Though a literary celebrity, Aretino
was proud of his lack of education; he always scoffs at humanistic erudition.
- Laurentius Valla advocating
philosophical originality: philosophers always had the freedom of saying what
they think not only against heads of other schools but also their own school
head; this applies the more to philosophers who have joined no school at all
(in Dialectica, preface). Valla’s
sense of originality, however, must not be overestimated, though he has a
certain tendency to criticize established authorities.
In the quoted work he is opposing
Quintilianus, who at this time was not generally recognized, against the
authority of Cicero, pointing out that Quintilian can be surpassed only by a
god (op. cit. chap. 40, 1509 edition, fol. 29 v.).
On both Pico’s cf. below p. 44 f.
37
The ideal of imitation, though interesting to
historiographers of literary style, need not be discussed here.
The humanist belief in authority, on
the other hand, directly concerns our problems.
It hardly differs from the
prescientific attitude of the medieval scholastics.
These believed in the authority of the
Scripture, the church fathers, and Aristotle, the Renaissance scholars in the
authority of the secular writers of classical antiquity: this is the only
difference. The humanist belief in
authorities is entirely unscientific. It
is in accord rather with the traditionalism and collective mindedness of the
Middle Ages than the individualistic spirit of early capitalism.
The merchants, many artisans and
artists of the Renaissance were already used to relying on their inventive
spirit and their individual abilities. In
these ranks appreciation of novelty and, among a few artists of the fifteenth
and sixteenth centuries, even ideals of originality had developed.
It is remarkable how little this
individualistic spirit influenced the scholars of the early modern era.
Obviously it was not humanism that has
produced modern thinking. Viewed
sociologically humanism was the ideology of a caste of literati-officials
that, in their time, monopolized the intellectual leadership of the age but
since then has become extinct. Viewed
historically humanism was a by-path rather than the main road of the advance
of the scientific spirit, and the modern spirit in general.
Certainly the humanists have helped to
replace ecclesiastical with secular thinking.
They have, moreover, rediscovered classical philosophy, literature,
and art and, thus, transmitted the intellectual achievements and aesthetic
ideals of antiquity to the subsequent centuries.
In intellectual developments, however,
methods are more important than material contents.
The spirit of science, which sets off
the modern era from all other periods, originated in social groups which, as
artisans and navigators, were not touched by or were opposed to humanism.
From these ranks came Francis Bacon’s
enthusiasm for progress and the seventeenth century insurrection against
belief in authorities. In Galileo,
Descartes, and Bacon this revolt was directed against scholasticism and
humanism alike. Science arose in open
opposition to humanism.
A considerable portion of the spirit of
prescientific scholarship, however, survives in the age of science.
Primarily our present philology and
historiography, directly descend from Renaissance humanism.
Both are more interested in single
facts than in general laws, more in the past than in prediction, and they are
not always free from certain implications of the pride in erudition.
On the other hand our historians and
philologists have not adopted the uncritical belief in authority and the
passion for imitation from their Renaissance ancestors.
In the modem world of natural science
and machines even the “humanistic studies” could not remain unaffected by
essential elements of the scientific spirit.
38
5. The Humanists as
Dispensers of Fame
We have at length discussed the humanist ideal
of erudition. The ideal of fame,
having less relations to the scientific spirit, may be treated more briefly.
The desire for fame is very strong in
man. It is particularly powerful in
the upper classes and can, hence, even become the economic basis of special
professions. In many civilizations
with a warlike nobility professional bards make their living by spreading the
fame of members of the upper ranks. In
the tribes of the North American Indians the warriors themselves sang of their
deeds. In Greece of the Homeric period
and among the ancient Norsemen the primeval tribal equality existed no longer;
there a nobility had developed and professional rhapsodists and scalds had
taken over the task of singing the deeds of the heroes.
The prestige of the upper class in
early capitalistic Europe was based more on wealth, political power, and
display of luxury than on warlike deeds. Especially
in Italy, however, the desire for fame reached a degree unknown in any another
culture except classical antiquity. Probably
it was the division in numerous small states, rivalling with one another, that
in Italy produced the unusual intensity of the desire for fame.
Apparently the same sociological cause
produced the same effect in ancient Greece. Also
a certain fading of religious faith in the early modern era contributed to the
increase of the passion for fame, for the glory ideal cannot fully develop as
long as the spiritual interest is directed towards non-worldly objects.
At any rate the municipal governments, princes,
and popes, city tyrants, bankers and noblemen of Renaissance Italy competed
with each other for fame. To this end
they used a special professional group, the humanists.
It has been mentioned how the
political secretaries not only had to conduct foreign affairs but also to
increase the prestige of their employers, by their literary activity.
This function was discharged in two
ways. Primarily the humanists were
required to insert rather immoderate glorifications of their protectors in
their writings or, at least, in their dedications.
This was the direct method, used to
excess by the literati. On the other
hand the prestige of a prince or prelate was increased more indirectly by the
mere fact that he was able to maintain outstanding writers or scholars.
In this respect painters, sculptors,
and architects could render the same services as literati.
Famous authors or artists at the court
of a prince discharged the same sociological function as his palace, his
suite, and his luxurious garments and jewels.
Almost in all civilisations princes and noblemen increase their
prestige by display of costly luxuries that sometimes are very important for
the development of civilization. Viewed
sociologically, the writers and artists of the Renaissance belong with these
luxury goods of the upper class. In
addition most of the dynasties and all city tyrants in Renaissance Italy could
not rely on the prestige of ancestors. Usurpers
need dispensers of fame much more than old dynasties with inherited prestige
and the same is true for popes who come to power by election.
Hence in many cases the Renaissance
patrons even hunted after celebrities with offers of donations and positions,
endeavoring to win them over if they were in the service of a competitor.
39
To the writer the profession of a dispenser of
prestige offered the financial basis for his literacy activity.
This is a phenomenon common to all
periods in which a large and educated public has not yet developed and in
which, consequently, authors, and artists are dependent on individual patrons.
In the Renaissance, particularly,
there existed a kind of symbiosis between the humanist and his patron.
The author was supported by his patron
and, in return, made him famous. Sometimes
the authors were fully conscious of this reciprocity.
The more rationally the “give and
take” was handled by the dispenser of glory and the more frequently he changed
his patrons the more his activity degenerated into adulation and blackmail.
The low of this development of an in
itself morally neutral sociological relationship is represented by the
humanist Filelfo in the fifteenth century and the vernacular writer Pietro
Aretino in the sixteenth. Both were
extremely gifted authors who procured themselves patrons according to mere
rational business principles without any moral inhibitions.
In a period in which authors do not
live on donations from individual patrons but on the sale to an anonymous
public of their books, writers like Filelfo and Aretino would probably have
made use of publicity agents. In the
Renaissance they used shameless extortion. It
is significant that those humanists who, by their occupation, were more remote
from the fame business lived up to the moral standards of the contemporary
middle class. The bookseller
Vespasiano da Bisticci, the educators Vittorino da Feltre and Guarino, the
printer Aldo Manuzio were exemplary business, family, and professional men.
In the world of the free literati and
their upper-class protectors, on the other hand, glory displaced virtually all
other ideals. The greed of fame,
probably, was increased also by the specific reciprocity of the patron -
protege relationship. It was certainly
more honorable to be protected by a famous than by an unknown patron and more
glorious to be praised by a celebrity than by an unknown scribbler.
Both sides, therefore, were interested
in the increase of fame.
Ever since humanism had come into existence the
ideas of the humanists were dominated by glory.
As early as in the fourteenth century,
Petrarch dedicated quite a series of chapters to the problems of fame in his
book Remedies for the Vicissitudes of Fortune.
There we find chapters “on glory”
and “on the hope of fame”, “on fame hoped from buildings” and “on fame hoped
from intercourse”, “on infamy”, “on contempt”, and “on posthumous fame”.
The book, however, is a dialogue and
of the protagonists only one praises fame, whereas the other, advocating the
vanity of all worldly goods, always opposes eternal bliss to desire for fame.
Manifestly, in Petrarch the medieval
ideal of Christian humility still combats the humanistic ideal of fame.
Over the same conflict Petrarch
drudges his life away in his dialogue On Contempt of the World.
There St. Augustine advocates
Christian humility whereas Petrarch, who himself appears as the other speaker
of the dialogue, reproaches himself with his vanity.
The dialogue ends with the promise of
the humanist to collect all his strength against the allurements of fame: “may
God assist me”. Still, thirty years
later, the same conflict of the two ideals - characteristic of a period of
transition - appears in the letters of the chancellor Salutati.
When, on the other hand, later
humanists -
40
Erasmus, Lorenzo Valla, Francesco Pico -
occasionally object to fame, the Christian arguments are, for the most part,
replaced by Stoic ones. Such humanists
attacks against greed for fame, however, must not be taken too seriously.
Just as the analogous attacks in ancient Stoics and Sceptics, they only
confirm the strength of the adversary.
Before business people preachers declaim against the treasures that are
eaten by rust and moths; before an audience of literati, and protectors of
literati, other literati declaim against fame.
Petrarch De remediis utriusque fortunae
(together with De contemptu mundi) Rotterdam 1649. De rem, I,
117, 122; II, 25. De cont. III, 808 ff., 812, 820, 823.
Epistolario di Coluccio
Salutati in Instiiuto Storico lialiano, Fonti no. 15-18: for fame:
I, 10, 89, 105, 110, 198; II, 182, 204; III, 86; against fame: III, 349, 425,
471.
The idea that dispensing of fame is the chief
function of the literati emerges very early. It
is implied in an odd theory of Boccaccio on the sociological descent of the
poets. In ancient times,
Boccaccio explains, the kings had used priests to achieve veneration of
themselves and their ancestors; from these priests, in his opinion, the
writers descend. The economic
background of the idea clearly stands out in the Latin letters of Filelfo.
In 1433 Filelfo, one of the most
influential and unscrupulous of the humanists, begins a letter to Cosimo
Medici by mentioning the gracious reception given to him by the addressee and
stresses that, in return, he has in his writings commended Cosimo’s name to
immortality. This is but the
introduction to an attempt to set his protector against two humanists rivals.
The main part of the letter explains
that Niccoli and Carlo Marsuppini are worse than pestilence and accuses them
of having called another competitor, the old Chrysoloras, a lousy beard.
Curiously enough the writer protests a
few lines later that he has not learned to flatter and to adulate.
In another letter to a certain Simoneta of 1451, Filelfo first assures
the addressee of his love. After
mentioning that others prove grateful for benefits by gold and gems he
continues: “I, however, make gods out of men and give them the immortality
which is implied in the eternity of glory. Certainly
you can see what you may expect from me”. The
real project of the letter is a petition for a donation.
Filelfo’s Latin letters were published
and later printed. It is
significant that in his Greek correspondence, which was not intended to be
published, the “dispenser of fame” ideology occurs only once, in a letter to
the Sultan. There Filelfo asks for the
release of a few female relations who had been captured by the Turks.
Beginning with the affirmation that he
has already heard of the glorious deeds of the sultan, he introduces himself
as follows: “I am among those who make mortals immortal by the glory that the
word dispenses”. The request follows.
In Filelfo the give and take in the
glory business is quite manifest.
Family tree of the poets: Boccaccio, Opera
volga, Florence 1832, XV, 53 f. (Vita di Dante); Filelfo’s Latin
letters: Epistobarumfamiliarum libri 37, Venice 1502, fol. 12 r,
and fol. 54 V.; letter to the sultan: Emile Legrand: Cent-dix lettres
Grecques de Filelfe, Paris 1892, p. 63. Further
evidence of the “dispenser of glory” ideology: G. Voigt, op. cit. I,
334 (Poggio), 446 (Petrarch, Beccadelli-Panormita), 527 (Filelfo).
41
Sometimes strange ideas result from the
“dispenser of fame” ideology. In the
middle of the 15th century Benedotto Accolti, the chancellor of Florence,
states the dark ages had actually achieved as much as classical antiquity;
only the historical writers had been deprived of their remunerations and had,
for this reason, hushed up all eminent achievements.
Or Porcellio, court humanist to the
King of Naples, about the same time considers the dispensers of glory more
important that the glorified persons; he begins his exposition of the deeds of
the condottiere Piccinino with the praise of the writers “by whose documents
the praiseworthy men live in eternal memory of mankind and, miraculously,
become immortals from mortals”. About
half a century later an Italian court humanist to the emperor Maximilian I,
Sbrullius, who had been portrayed by Dürer and, in return, had dedicated a
poem to the painter, affirms with a strange reversal that Dürer will become
immortal by the poem and he himself by the picture.
Accoltus: De praestantia virorum sui aevi.
Parma 1697, p. 60 (the same opinion expressed in Poggio: Dc varietaic
fortunae, cf. Voigt, op. cit. II, 492); Porcellio in Muratori:
Rerum btabicarum scriptorcs, Milan 1761, XXV, 2A; Sbrullius in J. von
Schlosser: Materialien zur Quellenkunde der Kunstgeschichte III
(Wiener Akademie Berichte, philo.-hist. Klasse vol. 180 (1916), 72)
On Sbrullius or Sbrollius cf. C.G. Jöcher: Allgemeines Gelehrtenlexicon,
Leipzig (1751).
The passion for fame of the Renaissance literati
results in a remarkable phenomenon that essentially distinguishes humanism
from modern science. Since the time of
Francis Bacon scientists usually give control of nature, progress and
furthering of human civilization as aims of their activity.
If they ever mention fame as a motive
they speak, at the highest, of the prestige of their scientific school, their
university, or their fatherland, but even this is done only in somewhat
backward countries. No modern
scientist would admit that he does his research in order to become famous.
Just this is plainly stated by the
Renaissance humanists. In doing so,
they only follow, however, classical models. To
classical literature not only the “dispenser of fame” ideology is familiar but
also the desire for fame is very often given by ancient authors as the
decisive incentive of cultural activities. Thus
Cicero declares in his Tusculaneans that “it is honor that nourishes
the arts and men are impelled to the studies by fame”.
This idea was with enthusiasm adopted
by the Renaissance. As early as in
1386 Coluccio Salutati quoted the saying of Cicero and expressed his
agreement. Salutati, however, rejected
the same saying as heathenish seventeen years later since, as mentioned
before, he still wavered between the humanist ideals and Christian humility.
In the following centuries fame is
very often used even as an argument in theoretical controversies.
Over and over again it is pointed out
that the behavior, the literary style, or the doctrines of some adversary are
not likely to make him famous: obviously this argument is considered to be a
valid refutation. The fame ideology is
a typical product of humanism. Originally
it was foreign to the artists who in the fourteenth century still adhered to
the guild ideals of the artisans and thereby, in some respect, were nearer to
the
42
modern spirit than the literati.
When in the early Renaissance the
artist rejected love of gain as incentive he demanded love of his art from the
painter without even mentioning fame. In
the middle of the fifteenth century, however, the fame ideology spread from
the literati to the architects, painters, and sculptors who began to be
ashamed of their descent from artisans. The
sixteenth century artists gave desire for fame as a motive of their activity
just as the humanistic dispensers of glory.
Fame as motive in classical antiquity: Cicero,
Tusc. I, 2, 4 and pro Arch. 6 and 11.
Similar passages: Plato, conviv.
208 C ff., Horace, ep. II, 3, 324.
On the “dispenser of fame” ideology in classical antiquity cf.
Alexander’s complaint of having no equal herald of his deeds as Achilles had
in Homer; furthermore Theognis 237 ff., Pindar, Nem. 4, 6 ff.; 7, 13;
Pyth. 1, 90ff.; 3, 114ff.; 01., 9,27; Cicero, ad. fam. V,
12, l3;pro. Arch. 6, 9 and 12; Horace, carm. IV, 8 and 9; ep.
II, 1, 229 ff.; Vergil, Aen. IX, 440 f.; Pliny, nat. hist.
pref. 25 (on Apion); Seneca ep. 21, 3 ff.; Claudianus, de cons.
Stilich. 3 pref.
Renaissance: fame as motive: Salutati,
Epistolario loc. cit. I, 70 and III. 86 (Cicero quotations).
Bessario (In calumniatorem Platonis,
Venice 1516, I, 1) starts his attack on George of Trapezunt with the
remark that he had expected George’s work to have been written “in order to
gain posthumous fame”. Franciscus
Pico, letter to Bembo (1512) in Opera II, 123 f.: literary imitation
must be avoided since it is detrimental to fame.
- Likewise Erasmus, Ciceronianus
(1528) in Opera, Basle 1540, I, 840 ff.
- Cardano, De vita propria
(1542) in Opera, Lugduni 1663, I fol. 7 r: “immortalization of name”
praised as “glorious invention”. Desire
for fame given as motive for the composition of his book by the French
humanist Bachet (1621), full quotation below, p. 48. Michelangelo Biondo,
Treatise on Painting (1549) in Quellenschriften für Kunst-Geschichte,
Vienna 1888, vol. 5, 32: all artists should strive for fame.
The treatise begins with the wish for
“immortal fame to all excellent artists of Europe” (Biondo is a medical doctor
and not strictly a humanist; his treatise is written in the vernacular).
Guild ideals in artists: Cennini, Treatise on
Painting (c. 1390), chap. 2 (in Quellenschriften für Kunstgeschichte,
vol. 1, new ed. Vienna 1888 p. 4). Glory
ideals in artists: Leone Battista Alberti, Treatise on Painting (1435)
in Quellenschriften für Kunstgeschichte. Vienna 1877, vol. 11, pref.
and pp. 49 and 99. Leonardo,
Treatise on Painting (c. 1500): I am addressing myself rather than to
painters greedy for money, to artists “who want to gain fame and honour
through their art” (ed. Ludwig, Quellenschr., vol. 15-17, Vienna 1882,
I § 81, cf. I § 65; Leonardo is otherwise very little influenced by
humanism). Vasari, Biographies of
Artists, in Opera, ed. Milanesi, Florence 1887, I, 91: eminent
artists produce perfect works “inflamed by desire for fame”; ibid I,
11: Michelangelo created his works “in order to leave posthumous fame like the
ancients”; cf. ibid. VIII, 163. Francesco
d’Ollanda (a friend of Michelangelo), Da pintura antiga (in
Quellenschr. N.F., vol. 9, Vienna 1899) p. 27: immortal name is the only
valuable aim in human life.
It can hardly be assumed that the writers, and
artists, of the Renaissance were essentially vainer than their modern
colleagues. Many modern scholars too
may be motivated in their research by the desire for prestige.
The fact that Renaissance authors
openly admit personal fame to be their aim whereas modern scholars, as far as
such questions are discussed at all, put fame in the background behind
impersonal ideals makes the real difference between the two periods.
Of
43
course, many humanists, more or less sincerely,
professed religious ideals. Impersonal
intellectual ideals, however, were far less developed in the period of the
Renaissance than of modern science. This,
apparently, is correlated to the absence of any co-operative organization of
intellectual activities before the seventeenth century.
Scholars, by their very nature, seem
to tend towards personal rivalries. In
the Middle Ages the strength of group tradition and the common membership of
the church were counterweights to such individualistic impulses.
Yet even at the late medieval
universities, where institutions corresponding to modern laboratories and
research institutes were unknown, the practice of disputation produced a
considerable quarrelsomeness among the schoolmen.
In the Renaissance rivalry among the
scholars greatly increased. The
disintegration of feudalism and the rise of economic competition had,
sociologically and economically, prepared the soil for literary individualism.
The professional conditions of the
literati produced it. In their belief
in authorities the humanists still were medieval; in their quarrelsomeness
hyperindividualistic. Literary
polemics became as frequent and vehement as never before and personal quarrels
and intrigues were regarded as an unavoidable part of the life of a literary
man. In this general struggle of all
against all, every kind of humanist took part: political officials as Lionardi
Bruni, Carlo Marsuppini, and Poggio, free literati as Filelfo, university
professors as Robortelli and Sigonio are among the most quarrelsome of the
scholars. Only those humanists who
were more remote from the “fame business” - the booksellers, printers, and
educators - abstained from the general passion for polemics.
The idea that scholars have to promote knowledge
by mutual co-operation was as yet unknown to all of these individualistic
advocates of the fame ideal. Even at
the end of the sixteenth century Henri Estienne (the younger), because of
scholarly rivalry, did not allow his son-in-law Isaac Casaubonus to use his
library for philological studies. Both
Estienne and Casaubonus were Geneva Huguenots and very remote from the amoral
literati of the Filelfo and Panormita period, both were outstanding classical
scholars, but their scientific ideals were entirely individualistic.
It is not mere coincidence that
Francis Bacon, who first proclaimed the objective ideals of progress of
science and control of nature, at the same time rejected personal fame and
advocated foundation of research institutes based on co-operation of
scientists. Not before the middle of
the seventeenth century were Bacon’s ideas realized, the Royal Society was
founded and the first scientific periodicals were published.
At any rate the hypertrophy of fame in
the Renaissance is but the reverse of the absence of any co-operative
scientific institutions. Only the
scientific age views science as a great building, rising stone by stone
through co-operation of scientists, each of whom uses the results of his
fellow workers and predecessors. The
complete lack of this idea in the Renaissance is among the most characteristic
differences between science and humanism. It
must not be overlooked, however, that even in the scientific age, and even
after the rise of learned periodicals and research institutes both for the
sciences and the humanistic studies, a certain liking for learned polemics
44
might occur more frequently among philologists
than among natural scientists. This,
certainly, is a survival of the humanistic spirit.
On Henri Estienne vs. Casaubonus cf. Sandys,
loc. cit. II, 205. Francis Bacon
against personal ambition as scientific motive Novum Organum I, 129
(Fowler, p. 337); for research institutes, co-operation, and division of labor
in scientific research Nova Atlantis.
Mastery of style is the third of the
professional ideals of the humanists. We
discuss it last not because it plays a smaller part than the ideals of
erudition and of fame but because it is remotest from the scopes of science.
It has grown out from the tasks of the
political office and refers both to the written and the spoken word since the
political secretaries had frequently to act as official orators.
Because of this connection with speech-making, mastery of style was
usually called “eloquence” in the Renaissance.
As far as humanism was represented at the European universities the
chairs of eloquence were its seats. How
far valuation of eloquence went may be shown by a few remarks of an early
humanist. Eloquence, Coluccio Salutati
says: “is the greatest of all humanistic studies, the most beautiful of all
sciences”. In a letter on the death of
his master and friend Petrarch Salutati expresses his conviction that in
heaven the deceased “with his eloquent breast” will succeed in persuading God
early to reunite Petrarch’s admirers with their master.
He, Salutati, is looking forward to
meeting his friend again and will regale himself in the other world of the
“nectarean suavity of Petrarch’s eloquence”. The
quotation at once gives a good instance of the rhetorical exaggerations that
by the humanists were considered eloquent style.
The emphasis upon style lasted up to the end of the Renaissance.
At the beginning of the sixteenth century Bembo, papal secretary and
later cardinal of the Roman church, cautioned authors against reading the
epistles of St. Paul; St. Paul’s Greek would have spoiled the style of the
readers. Not before the decline of the
literati and the rise of the professors in the later half of the sixteenth
century did classical erudition become more important in humanism than
imitation of classical eloquence. Even
the most learned and pedantic professors, however, attached great value to the
linguistic purity of their Latin expositions.
Salutati on eloquence loc. cit. I, 179 21
f., I, 230 1. 9 f., II. 295; on Petrarch in heaven, ibid. I, 199. Bembo
on St. Paul cf. J.A. Symonds op. cit. 511.
Science is interested in factual and logical
content, mastery of style is a formal and aesthetic ideal.
A great portion of the humanist aims,
therefore, has nothing to do with scientific knowledge.
Even from the merely stylistic point
of view, however, the prose writings of the Renaissance humanists differ
considerably from modern scientific works. Before
the rise of the professors at the end of the Renaissance these writing are
virtually always pathetic, often satirical, and abound with declamations and
rhetoric repetitions even when theoretical
45
arguments are brought forth.
It is not here our task to give value
judgements but to investigate humanism causally and to compare it with
science. Theoretical knowledge
certainly does not exhaust the totality of human activities; in the scientific
age, too, there are in addition to science fine arts and letters.
From the aesthetic and the educational
point of view the emphasis upon style and the refinement of literary language,
due to humanism, are of considerable historical importance.
In classical antiquity rhetoric had
played a great part in higher education. The
sense of the aesthetic values of language was widely spread and also
considered a prerequisite also of historiography and every philosophical and
scholarly activity. Among the monks of
the Middle Ages this sense had been lost: they were too much interested in the
other world and subtle theological arguments to care much for language.
Literary style and language were
rediscovered as objects of interest by the political secretaries of the early
Renaissance and this discovery has left its mark on the civilization and the
education of the Western world.
It is another question whether the specific
style favored by the humanistic still appeals to the modern mind.
The language of modern science is
exact, factual, and concise. Since
also the non-scientific literature has not been left untouched by this new
style the literary taste of our age may take offense at the overheated
declamations and the verbosity of the humanists.
The merely factual writings on
technological topics of Renaissance artisans (their contents will be analyzed
later) and the witty letters of the completely uneducated Pietro Aretino make
a much more “modern” impression on readers of our time than the works of the
humanists. They are nearer to the
modern sense of style just because their authors were not touched by humanism.
Of all sixteenth century Italian prose
writers with humanistic education, only Macchiavelli is virtually free of the
Renaissance rhetoric that appears so unmodern to us.
Macchiavelli, however, wrote in the
vernacular just as the artisans.
The specific style of the humanists has more to
do with the absence of the scientific spirit than historians of thought who
disregard the literary form of the publications possibly assume.
Actually the great advocates of
experimentation at the beginning of the seventeenth century scoffed in their
writings not only at the sterile subtleties of the scholastics but also at the
rhetoric of the humanists. Such
antihumanistic attacks occur frequently in the works of William Gilbert,
Galileo and Francis Bacon. It is
remarkable, however, that Gilbert and Bacon themselves are still strongly
influenced in their style by humanistic verbosity; Galileo only writes an
unsophisticated, though witty, Italian which stems from the plain language of
the plain people. Descartes too
is entirely free of humanistic “eloquence”. Even
from the stylistic point of view modern science arose in manifest opposition
to humanism.
Attacks against humanism: William Gilbert, De
Magnete, London 1600, preface to the reader: the contemporary writers are
“destroyers of the good arts, literary idiots, grammarians, sophists”
etc. He, Gilbert, will not “refer to
the ancients and Greek auxiliaries, since neither Greek arguments nor
Greek words are able better to prove or to illustrate the
46
truth... And
we have not used the paint of eloquence or the adornment of words in
this work but have restricted ourselves to discussing difficult things in such
a style and by such words that are necessary to understand them”.
- Galileo, Diabogo sopra i due
massimi sistemi del mondo, Edizione nazionale VII, p. 87, line 20 ff. : if
the argument were on “human studies where there is neither truth nor
falsity... skill of speaking” would be instrumental, but “in the natural
sciences oratory is inefficient”; ibid 135 I, 1 ff.: by mere combining
and interpreting everything could be proved from Virgil and Ovid and even
better from the alphabet; ibid. 139 I. 4 f.: opponents who refer to
authorities in their argumentation would better call themselves “historians or
doctors of memory” than philosophers; subject of the argument is “the world of
the senses not the world of paper”; ibid. 293 I, 7: “rhetorical
flowers” do not fit in with scientific arguments; they belong to “orators and
poets”. - Francis Bacon,
Advancement of Learning I, 4, 2: the humanists prefer words to the matter
and believe in authorities; -
Descartes, Récherche de la vérité, Oeuvres, ed. Cousin XI, 341: Latin
and Greek are of no more importance than the Swiss and Breton dialects;
rational argumentation, not memorized knowledge is the point that matters.
In an argument Pico della Mirandola, the
younger, says that things are more important than words.
Pico’s remark is a noteworthy
exception in humanist literature for, in general, the interest of the
humanists is primarily directed towards language.
They were engrossed in “eloquence” and
the classical purity of the used phrases, in products of classical literature
and Latin and Greek grammar. Objects
of nature and theoretical problems interested them, in general, in so far as
they had been treated before in classical literature.
A humanist once pointed out that
Caesar had made himself immortal through his description of the conquest of
Gaule - not by the conquest itself. Another
humanist dispenser of glory, in a work on famous men, mentions the invention
of printing among the great achievements of the age.
He does not give, however,
technological details of the invention or appreciate its import on the spread
of material knowledge, but sees its merit in “the destruction of linguistic
barbarism”. The odd report on printing
ends with the praise of a humanist colleague, well deserved, for his pure
Latinity - the name of Gutenberg is not mentioned.
The numerous “philosophical” writings
of the humanists are primarily exercises in eloquence.
They are more literary collections of
Platonic, Pythagorean, Aristotelian, and Stoic quotations than original
efforts to solve philosophical problems. Only
the neo-Platonic philosophy of Ficinus seems sincerely interested in material
questions, his interest, however, originating rather in his Christian faith
than in a zeal for scientific explanation of the world.
Not until the decline of humanism at
the end of the sixteenth century did a more original natural philosophy arise
- Telesio, Giordano Bruno - and this was, in Bruno, combined with vehement
attacks against humanistic overestimation of language and linguistic pedantism.
The analogous attacks of the first
modern physicists and scientific philosophers have just been mentioned.
In their combats with rising humanism
the scholastics too had brought forth the same arguments against their
victorious rivals. They too reproached
the humanists with disregard of the material problems and with the preference
given to words. In this respect, after
the humanistic interlude, science has returned to the standpoint of
47
scholasticism - though the scientist and the
scholastic might considerably disagree on the question as to which problems
belong to the “material” ones and by which methods they have to be
investigated.
On Pico cf. the end of this note.
- Caesar and the conquest of Gaule in
Muratori, Rer. hal. Script. XX, 448, 453.
- Printing and Latinity in Egnatius (Cipelli)
De exemplis illustrium virorum, Paris 1554, fol. 299 f. Polydorus
Vergilius too in his well known De rerum invcntoribus, Venice 1499,
only points out that printing has diminished the price of books and made
preservation of classical authors possible (book 2, chap. 7).
- Bruno against humanism, della
causa, dial. 3 (at the beginning), dial. 4 (beginning).
- Scholastic opposition to humanist
overestimation of words: the Cologne professor of theology Hochstraten (1521)
in his reply to Hutton’s Letters of Obscure Men and a scholastic
magister in a protest against the new humanistic curriculum at the University
of Leipzig (1519), cf. Friedrich Paulsen: Gcschichte des gelehrten
Unterrichtes, 3rd ed. Leipzig 1919, 1, 52 n. and 109; the Vienna professor
of theology Saeldner against followers of Enea Silvio Piccolomini (about 1450)
cf. G. Voigt, loc. cit. II, 292.
“Things more important than words”, Johannes
Franciscus Pico in his second letter to Bembo on the imitation of Cicero
(Works of both Pico’s, Basle 1601, II. 145).
Pico himself, however, ends his first
letter on the same subject with a long apology for the lack of stylistic
polish. Yet few parallels to Pico’s
attack on overestimation of words might be found in humanistic literature.
Altogether the younger Pico
(1470-1533) and his uncle Giovanni Pico (1463-1494), who is so often quoted as
a representative of the Renaissance spirit, are rather exceptions among the
humanists. The elder Pico, proclaiming
love of truth as the only motive of a true philosopher, disregards fame (loc.
cit. I, 212, de hominis dignitate); he argues against overestimation of
classical antiquity, underestimation of the own period, and demands study of
the scholastics, Arabs, and Chaldeans (ibid. I, 79, apologia).
The younger Pico argues against
fame as aim: philosophy and science must be studied only for the sake of God
and truth (ibid. II, 24 de studio phibosophiae); he attacks
imitation (II, 123 ff. letter to Bembo) and underestimation of the own period
(ibid. II, 125 f.). The special
position of the elder Pico possibly is partly explained by his training in
scholastic philosophy at the Paris university; except for the few humanistic
monks, he is, probably, the only humanist who had such a training.
In addition both Pici, being wealthy
counts, were farther remote from the usual fame business of the literati.
7. The Humanists and the Scientific Literature of Classical Antiquity
In the humanist literature, the almost complete
silence on the contemporary technological inventions and geographical
discoveries is striking. The period of
the Renaissance was a period of technological revolution and an unprecedented
expansion of the geographical horizon. Of
these great historical events in which the artisans, manufacturers, and
merchants were naturally highly interested virtually nothing is to be noticed
in the writings of the Italian humanists. This
silence is closely linked with the separation of liberal and mechanical arts
or, what is the same, the disdain of manual labor.
Technological inventors and navigators
were “mechanics”. Humanists, on the
other hand, were proud of being representatives of the “liberal arts” and,
particularly, representatives of
48
their more distinguished division.
This superior division (the “trivium”
of grammar, dialectic, and rhetoric) comprehended those arts in which
relationship to speech is especially manifest.
To the inferior “quadrivium” (arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and
music) the Italian humanists paid virtually no attention.
The treatment of the discoverers and inventors
in contemporary literature will be discussed later more extensively.
Certainly several humanists worked also on
ancient mathematics and natural science. They
edited Euclid, Archimedes, Apollonius, and Diophantus, translated them into
Latin and, by these editions and translations, considerably influenced the
rising modern physics and mathematics. Yet
it would be erroneous to ascribe understanding of mechanical and mathematical
problems to the editors. All of these
editions and translations are the work of philologists who edited the ancient
scientists because they were ancients rather than because they were
scientists. The texts and translations
are not only full of material mistakes but the prefaces reveal the merely
literary attitude of the editors and, sometimes, a remarkable lack of
mathematical understanding. The first
Greek edition of Archimedes (Basle 1544), the work of a certain Thomas
Gechauff, a German humanist, is the most superficial.
Archimedes was by far the most eminent mathematician of antiquity and
virtually the only ancient physicist to investigate quantitative laws by means
of experimentation and mathematics.
Compared to Aristotelian and medieval “physics” his work represents an
entirely new approach to the problems. Actually
it contributed a great deal to the development of modern scientific mechanics
after it had come into the right hands.
Of all this the humanist editor is not aware.
His preface is manifestly intended to
hide his mathematical ignorance behind the usual laudatory phrases of the
professional dispensers of fame; as scientific achievements of Archimedes he
gives statements that were known both to every ancient and every sixteenth
century schoolboy; and the value of mathematics is proved by means of a
classical quotation from Quintilianus stating that mathematical knowledge is
necessary for the orator. The
application to technology of mathematics, with which the contemporary
architects and engineers were intensely occupied, obviously is considered as
too inferior by the humanist. The
verbiage of Gechauff’s prefaces is in a remarkable contrast to the first Latin
edition of Archimedes that had appeared one year earlier (1543). Its
editor was Tartaglia, one of the forerunners of Galileo, who really understood
the great ancient scientist and, in practice and treatises, applied
Archimedean methods and results to technological problems.
Tartaglia, however, was, as mentioned
above, not a humanist but a self-educated mathematics teacher and mathematical
adviser to gunners, architects, and merchants.
Of course, Tartaglia, who admitted that he knew little of the ancient
languages, had not himself translated the Greek text but edited a thirteenth
century Latin translation. All of his
own words are written in the vernacular.
49
The preface to the first Greek edition of
Diophantus (Paris 1621) - the editor was Bachet, a French humanist - is
sounder than Gechauff’s preface to Archimedes.
Bachet compares his tract with a previous Latin translation and is
concerned with textual correctness and the biography of Diophantus.
In a lengthy and “eloquent”
explanation, however, he gives as incentive of his publication emulation with
another scholar and his desire to become famous.
He is an adherent of the humanistic
glory ideology and a conscientious philologist but not a mathematician.
The preface to the first Greek edition
of Euclid (Basle 1533) is typical of humanism.
It too, however, does not contain any evidence of real mathematical
knowledge.
The prefaces to the first editions of ancient
scientists are reprinted in Beriah Botfield Prefaces to the First Editions
of the Greek and Roman Classics, London 1861.
The following quotations refer to this
work. The editor of the first Greek
Archimedes edition, Thomas Gechauff, called Venatorius, was a Nuremberg
preacher who wrote several theological works and translated also Aristophanes.
His Archimedes edition also contains
the Latin Archimedes translation of Jacob of Cremona.
It has three prefaces.
In the first the scientific importance
of Archimedes is proved as follows (loc. cit. 416 f.): Gechauff points out
that the circle has no beginning and no end: “who of the ancients, I ask, has
more clearly written on this fact than Archimedes?”
The cube stays stable however it
falls: “who, I adjure you, has more eruditely, more accurately, more
diligently explained these facts than our Archimedes?”
There follows an enumeration of ten
contemporary eminent “mathematicians”; all of them are classical scholars,
only three - Regiomontanus, Schöner and Rheticus - actually were
mathematicians. Several classical
anecdotes on Archimedes conclude the first preface.
The second preface (420-425) begins
with long references to ancient philosophers on mathematics and quotations
from Homer and Vulcanus. The value of
mathematics is proved (423 f.) by means of Quintilianus’ statement that the
orator requires mathematical knowledge. As
an example Gechauff at length discusses the size of an ancient acre that must
be known to the orator and gives no fewer than five diagrams to illustrate the
concept of the area of a rectangle.
The editor of the first Greek Diophantus, Claude
Gaspard Bachet, sieur de Meziriac, was a humanist and lawyer, author of Latin,
French, and Italian poems and a French translation of Ovid.
His Greek Diophantus contains also the
editor’s Latin translation of the text. The
first preface is addressed to a lawyer. Just
as Themistocles competed with Miltiades “in honourable emulation for fame”,
Bachet begins, I am thinking day and night of how I might become as famous as
you are. You have surpassed all
jurists and even Papiniamus. To which
field am I to turn? After having
examined all other disciplines, I decided to choose mathematics “since it
wonderfully delights the minds and since in mathematics the subtlety of the
intellect specially comes to light. This
Diophantus will give evidence of my achievements and show whether I have
deserved fame beyond the ordinary mathematician”.
The preface to the reader (658-665) is
less personal. It gives learned
biographical notes on Diophantus, mentions an earlier Diophantus translation
of Xilander (1575), “that is much worse than ours”, and states that in the
following edition the text has been purified for the first time and that
additions of the editor have been enclosed in brackets.
A French translation of the first
books of Diophantus (from Xilander’s Latin translation) had been published
thirty-six years earlier by Simon Stevin (L’arithmetique, Leyden 1585)
who was not a humanist but, originally, a bookkeeper and cashier of the
municipalities of Bruge and Antwerp, later a military engineer and
Quartermaster general of Holland, and who really understood mathematics.
50
- The editor of the first Greek Euclid (Basel
1533) was Simon Grynaeus, a Basle professor of Greek, a friend of Thomas More,
and editor of works of Aristotle, Plato, Plutarch, and Ptolemy.
The preface loc. cit., 381 ff.
- The German humanists Peuerbach and
Regiomontanus, however, in contrast to their colleagues, were eminent
mathematicians.
The editions of Euclid and Archimedes exerted
their influence rather in circles linked to the mechanical arts and opposed to
humanism than among the colleagues of their humanist editors.
And only a small minority of the
humanists were engaged in work on classical scientific literature.
Scientists were edited scarcely before the sixteenth century, that is
about two centuries later than the ancient orators, poets, and philosophers.
Interest in ancient science did not
belong to the original aims of humanism. Apparently
the humanists began to occupy themselves with classical scientists only when
other circles became interested in mathematics and natural science.
In his History of Classical
Scholarship, Sir John Erwin Sandys gives two lists of first prints of
Latin and Greek authors. The Latin
list contains seventy-one first editions from 1464 to 1596, starting with the
Mainz print of Cicero’s de officiis of 1464.
Among them there are only three books
- Pliny the Elder (1469), Lucretius (1473), and Vitruvius (1486) - that can be
called works on topics of the natural sciences or technology.
The list of Greek first editions
begins with Aesop’s fables of 1478 and contains one hundred and eight prints.
Seven works - ancient astronomers,
Galen, Hippocrates, Ptolemy, Euclid, Archimedes, Diophantus - deal with
astronomical, medical, geographical, mathematical, and mechanical subjects.
The first Greek Euclid was printed in
1533 - sixty-nine years after Cicero - the first Greek Archimedes in 1544, the
first Greek Diophantus not until 1621. Neither
Euclid nor Archimedes appeared in Italy but in Basel, Diophantus in Paris.
Certainly, these printed first
editions do not exhaust the ancient scientific literature that was at the
disposal of Renaissance readers. There
were handwritten copies before the invention of printing and there were Latin,
and later vernacular, translations of Greek authors.
And, certainly, it was not the fault
of the humanists that the great majority of preserved ancient writers were
orators, philosophers, poets, and historiographers.
But just this fact discloses the part
played by science in the humanist “revival of learning”.
Somewhat less than 6.5% of the first
prints of ancient authors dealt with scientific problems.
It is historically understandable that
Galileo, scoffing at the humanistic way of thinking, would remark that his was
the world of the senses not the world of paper.
The two lists of first prints in Sandys op.
cit., vol. 2, Cambridge 1908, 102 ff. Galileo
on the world of papers, cf. above p. 42.
The rise of interest in zoology and botany too
is somewhat linked with humanism. The
first print of Pliny’s Natural History, Rome 1469, was edited by the
humanist Theodorus Gaza, a Greek refugee who also translated the biological
works of Aristotle into Latin. Among
the earliest zoologists of the modern era is Aldovrandi (c. 1522-c.l605) who
published thirteen folio volumes on natural history.
Aldovrandi was a professor of
philosophy at Bologna, an Aristotelian who had turned to zoology upon
stimulation of the
51
Montpellier physician Rondelet.
Humanist influence is distinctly
noticeable in his work. Of his two
books on the eagle the first treats its subject philologically and
archaeologically and only the second describes the biological facts.
The other eminent zoologists of the
sixteenth century - Rondelet (1577-1666), Salviani (1514-1572), Gesner
(1516-1565), and Belon (1517-1564) - were medical doctors with few relations
to humanism (cf. E.W. Gudger: The five great naturalists of the sixteenth
century, Isis 22, 1934, 21 ff.). Between
1469, the year of Gaza’s first edition, and 1600 thirty reprints of Pliny’s
Natural History were published, but before 1469, there was no humanistic
literature dealing with biology. Obviously
also the biological interest of the late Renaissance originated outside
humanism.
It cannot be overlooked that preoccupation with
language and related problems is characteristic primarily of the Italian
humanists. In Germany, England, and
France a not negligible fraction of the humanists took part in the religious
struggle of the period, advocating the cause of the Reformation.
Other non-philological questions too engaged the non-Italian humanists.
A humanist like the English Chancellor
Thomas More considerably differs, in his problems, his style, his life, and
his death, from his Italian literary and office colleagues.
The humanist alchemist to Queen
Elisabeth, John Dee, wrote a preface in the vernacular to an English Euclid
translation (1570) and showed interest in, and a limited understanding of, the
mechanical arts, cartography, and navigation.
His fellow countrymen and contemporaries, the mathematicians Recorde,
Leonard and Thomas Digges, furthered commercial arithmetic, surveying, and
gunnery in spite of their humanistic education.
The two most eminent astronomers
before Copernicus, Peurbach and Regiomontanus, lectured in the middle of the
fifteenth century at German universities alternately on astronomy and Latin
poets. And after all, Copernicus
himself had received a humanistic education at the University of Cracow.
Obviously, outside Italy, eloquence
and language had absorbed less of the interest of the humanistic scholars, a
fact that should require a sociological explanation.
8.
Rational Methods in Humanism
The professional ideals of eloquence, fame, and
erudition basically distinguish humanism from science and its aims.
Yet humanistic scholarship is not less
rational than science and in some way the Renaissance scholars were even more
intellectualistic than modern scientists. This
intellectualism appears in their idea of poetry.
Though the ancient idea of poetical
“enthusiasm” - the idea of divine frenzy - was, at least as a metaphor, very
familiar to the Renaissance, poetry was considered a learned and often a
learnable activity. Even when the
innate gifts of the eminent poet or writer were stressed, Minerva, the goddess
of wisdom, was considered a fitting allegory for the donors of these gifts.
Only the uneducated and anti-humanist
Pietro Aretino has an anti-intellectualistic conception of poetry that is much
more modern than everything written on this subject by humanists.
The Renaissance conception of painting
is not less intellectualistic.
52
When the painters were rising from handicraft
they attached great value to their lack of relationship to the mechanical
arts. After the second half of the
fifteenth century they therefore emphasized that painting, since it requires
geometrical knowledge, is a science. This
argumentation is humanistic as is disclosed by the frequent reference to
Pamphilus, a Greek painter who about 400 B.C. had used the same argument for
the same social reasons. Great
painters, moreover, are frequently called “great intellects” in the numerous
Renaissance treatises on painting.
Minerva as allegory for innate poetical talent
in Erasmus, Ciceronianus (Works, Basel 1540, I, 830 f.) and in
Trissino, Poetics (Works, Verona 1729, II, 116).
On the idea that painting is a science
and the reference to Pamphilus cf. Edgar Zilsel: Die Entstehung des
Geniebegriffes, Tuebingen 1926, p. 147. Great
painters as great “intellects”: Alberti, On painting (about 1440) in
Quellenschichte für Kunstgeschichte XI, 47; Giovanni Santi (The Father
of Rafael, about 1480) in Federigo de Montefeltroe, ed. Holtzinger,
Stuttgart 1893, XXII, 16 vers 90a; Michelangelo Buonarotti, Rime c Leticre,
Firenze 1903 p. 432; cf. Zilsel loc. cii., p. 266.
The intellectualism of the Renaissance is nearer
to the Middle Ages than to the spirit of our century.
In prescientific periods the majority
of the population is strictly bound to tradition whereas the small “learned”
minority which is able to read and write overestimates reason.
The medieval theologians were
extremely intellectualistic and there is a continuity of the same attitude in
Renaissance humanism. Even in the
scientific era the importance of the irrational elements of the human mind was
discovered, by Rousseau and the German Romanticists, not before the end of the
eighteenth century. In the evolution
of human civilization reason is younger than irrational tribal instincts,
irrational custom, irrational tradition. But
this is true only if humanity is viewed as a whole.
The majority of mankind is mute and
does not leave written documents. As
soon as literary men appear they are so proud of their exceptional position as
scholars that they stress the characteristics by which their profession stands
out from the rest of the population. For
this reason everywhere written literature starts with intellectualism and only
very late do the men who produce and leave written documents discover the
irrational elements by which the behavior of mankind, and of themselves, is
still dominated. The intellectualism
of Renaissance literature, therefore, is not a scientific but a primitive
trait and one must be very careful not to mistake the rational procedure of
the humanists for a scientific one.
In humanism the systematic method that is
characteristic of science was but slightly developed.
This is true even of the
quintessential field of humanist activity, philology.
Up to the middle of the fifteenth
century imitation of classical “eloquence” was the chief aim of the humanists.
The classical scholars felt
enthusiastic for ancient manuscripts, collected them, and emended the text if
passages were not understandable. They
replaced the mistakes of the medieval copyists, however, rather arbitrarily
with phrases conforming with their opinion on classical “eloquence”.
A sense of historical exactness was
foreign to them.
53
Though as early as in the fourteenth century
Salutati had detected the spuriousness of the pseudo-Ciceronian On
Differences, Lorenzo Valla’s proof of the spuriousness of the donation of
Constantine is the methodically most eminent achievement of the fifteenth
century and, probably, all Renaissance philology.
This document, on which the pope based
his claims to worldly domination was shown by Valla to be a medieval
falsification. His treatise was
written in 1440 but, for political reasons, could be printed only
seventy-seven years later by Ulrich von Hutten.
Valla’s analysis of the document uses
both linguistic and historical considerations and is as rational as that of a
modern philologist. He worked by order
of the King of Naples, a political adversary of the curia with an aversion to
the church - Valla was an Epicurean and, probably, a free thinker - which
might have sharpened his criticism. It
is significant both of the scholars and the church in the period of humanism,
that Valla a few years later made his peace with the pope and became an
apostolic writer. Valla also knew that
the correspondence between St. Paul and the philosopher Seneca was a medieval
falsification.
Valla’s treatise on the Donation of Constantine
reprinted and translated by C.B. Coleman, New Haven, 1922.
On his philological achievement cf.
George Voigt, op. cit. I, 69 and II, 475 f., 496 f.; J.E. Sandys op.
cit. II, 66 f., and Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorf Gcschichte der
Philologie (in Einleitung in die Alieriumswissenschafi, ed. A.
Gercke and E. Norden, 3rd. ed. Leipzig-Berlin 1927) I, 11 f.
In the fifteenth century there was some more
exact philological analysis. Poliziano
who in his Miscellanies (1489) wrote on the chronology of Cicero’s
letters and the use of the tenses in Greek inscriptions was, in the judgement
of U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorf, “a real philologist though not a textual
critic”. Many of the humanists who
lectured on or edited Latin and Greek authors were eminent classical scholars.
It certainly was not easy to read the
manuscripts, to correct the mistakes of the copyists, to understand and to
interpret the often very difficult texts without the help of the numerous
reference works that are at the disposal of modern scholars.
All these activities presupposed a
considerable amount not only of learning but also of rational thinking.
After the invention of printing
philological exactness also increased. The
humanists who in the late fifteenth and early sixteenth century edited
classical authors in the printing offices in Venice, Paris and especially in
Basel, and did a great deal of textual criticism and textual emendation.
They proceeded with much greater care
than the early humanists and habitually compared various manuscripts of the
same text. Yet, all of this rational
philological work was lacking in systematic method.
To some extent this is true even for
the eminent classical scholars among the sixteenth century professors,
Robortelli and Sigonio in Italy, both Scaligers, Henricus Stephanus and
Casaubonus in France, Lipsius in Holland. True,
imitation of classical eloquence was no more their chief aim.
But they did not systematically use
the results of their colleagues; they had no method for determining and
comparing the age and reliability of the codices; and even the
54
sixteenth century scholars more frequently
edited, emended, and interpreted single texts than investigated general
questions.
It is remarkable how rarely the humanists gave
an account of their methods. There are
a few humanistic expositions of logical problems, composed by Laurentius Valla
and the German Rudolphus Agricola in the 15th century, by the Italian Nizolius
and the Frenchman Petrus Ramus in the sixteenth.
All of these humanistic logicians attack the Aristotelian logic of the
scholastics, reproach it for artificiality, and want to replace Aristotle with
Quintilianus. All of them conceive
logic as a branch of rhetoric, an approach that is typically humanist -and
unscientific. The methods of humanist
philology, however, were not discussed in these treatises.
Methodological writings were rarely
composed by the classical scholars. Even
for elementary instruction in Latin grammar the medieval memorial verses of
Alexander of Villadei were used up to the end of the fifteenth century.
The first modern Latin grammar was
composed by the learned bishop Perotti, one century after Petrarch, in 1468,
the first successful modern Latin prosody by the same author in 1453.
The elegantiae of Lorenzo Valla
(c. 1440) deals more with “eloquence” than with proper grammar and is an
extremely learned juxtaposition of details without any systematical
arrangement. The humanists
occupied themselves with the correct spelling of Latin words as early as in
the fourteenth century. The first
learned Latin dictionary was published by Robert Estienne in 1532, two
centuries after Petrarch, its Greek counterpart by Henri Estienne in 1572.
The first treatise on the method of
textual emendation was written in 1557 by Robortelli (On the Art and Method
of Emending Ancient Books), seven years later a treatise On the Methods
of Emending Greek Authors by the Dutch professor, Willem Canter followed.
The codices were always used without
exact methods of determining their age. The
first treatise on paleography in which such methods were given was composed by
Mabillon in 1681, almost one century after the period which is the subject of
our analysis. Not until 1697 did
Bentley publish his treatise on the spuriousness of the Epistles of Phalaris -
the first contribution to historic-philological criticism that equals and
surpasses the achievement of Lorenzo Valla of 1440.
Investigation of the “genealogical
tree” of the codices was first demanded by protestant theologians in the
middle of the eighteenth century and the exact method of textual criticism was
accomplished by Lachmann in the middle of the nineteenth century.
Thus one of the outstanding classical
scholars of our time, Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorf, could say that it was
“the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries that elevated humanism to the level
of a science”. Of course, this
development was a gradual one and, certainly, the professor-humanist in the
sixteenth century proceeded more critically and thoroughly than the political
secretaries and literati in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries.
Humanistic treatises on “logic”: Valla:
Dialecticae disputationes contra Aristotelicos, printed posthumously 1499;
Agricola: De inventione dialectica, 1480; Ramus:Dialecticae
partitiones, Paris 1543; Nizolius: De veris principiis et vera ratione
phibosophandi contra pseudophilosophos, 1553.
On the development of the
humanistic
55
methods cf. Voigt, op. cit. II, 373
(Latin grammar), 376 ff. (Latin grammar, Perotti), 378 (Valla’s
elegantiae), 379 ff. (prosody and Greek Grammar), 381 ff. (textual
emendation); Sandys op. cit. II, 202 f. (Scaliger the elder), 141
(Robortelli), 216 (Canter); Wilamowitz-Moellendorf op. cit., 22 f.
(Scaliger the elder), 28 f. (humanism rising to the level of science only
after the Renaissance); Giorgio Pasquali: Storia della critica del tesio,
Firenze 1934, p. 3 (Lachmann), 9 (protestant theologians), 90 and 93 (l6th
century humanists guessing on the age of codices).
On the whole the sixteenth century humanists
investigated their problems by relying only on their intelligence and without
giving an account of their methods. One
might object to this characteristization that it fits the nascent natural
sciences as well. Yet this objection
is erroneous. The first
representatives of modern natural science were so well conscious of the
novelty of their aims that they proceeded much more methodically than the
sixteenth century, let alone the early humanists.
Galilei very often discussed his new
scientific method in interspersed remarks, most extensively in his God-Weigher
(1632); Francis Bacon opened his combat for the new scientific approach to
nature with a most extensive exposition of the method of induction (1620); and
Descartes’ first publication, his Discourse on the Method for well
directing one’s Reason and investigating Truth in the Sciences, is, as the
title indicates, a program not only of the new philosophy but also, in spite
of the disregard of experience, of the new scientific procedure.
In humanism analogous methodological
expositions are absent, since it had started from stylistic ideals and had
turned to theoretical aims only gradually. If
one disregards this difference one may say that more critical and more exact
methods arose in humanism in about the same century (1590-1690) as in the
natural sciences. Humanism, however,
was two and a half centuries older than science.
This synchronism is remarkable.
Since direct influence between the two
competitors can hardly be assumed, both phenomena may be considered as two
effects of one common cause: the increase of individual thinking and
rationality in sixteenth century society. Of
both critical philology and natural science there are certain beginnings in
classical antiquity. Both are absent
in the oriental cultures, though in China philological activities of
literati-officials, comparable to the early humanists, were richly developed.
The emergence of critical and
systematical methods in philology is also a characteristic peculiarity of
modern Western civilisation as the rise of science, the development of machine
technology, and modern capitalism. In
the Renaissance, however, only the first beginnings of the exact philological
methods appeared.
What distinguished the humanist from the
scholastic method? The humanists
themselves were well conscious of the difference.
The early humanists derided the
“barbarous” Latin of the scholastics and their ignorance of classical authors.
The attacks on the scholastics in
Ulrich von Hutten’s Letters of Obscure Men (1515) were pointed in the
same direction. Still about 1600
Casaubonus, after having attended a disputation at the Sorbonne, is said to
have remarked: I have never heard so much Latin spoken without understanding
it. A similar Casaubonus anecdote,
however, already points to a difference that passes
56
beyond linguistic and stylistic ideals.
To a friend, explaining that in this
auditorium of the Sorbonne scholars have been disputing for four hundred
years, the philologist is said to have replied: what have they decided?
This reply of a humanist could as well
have been made by a scientist. The
method of disputation at the late medieval and early modern universities is
scholastic. Casaubonus’ answer shows
that humanism rejects this method and, at the end of the fifteenth century,
had developed a concept of exactness that differs from the exactness aimed at
by the scholastics in logical distinctions and syllogisms.
Certainly, Casaubonus did not miss
experimentation and mathematics in the scholastic disputations.
What else he did miss is,
unfortunately, not pointed out.
Casaubonus’ aversion to the method of
disputation is typically humanist. When,
at the beginning of the sixteenth century, humanism conquered many German
universities, the obligatory disputations were replaced in the curriculum by
“declamations”, i.e. exercises in public speaking.
Cf. Friedrich Paulsen: Geschichte
des gelehrten Unterrichts auf den deutschen Schulen, 3rd. ed., Leipzig
1919, I, 120 f.
We, heirs of a scientific evolution of three
hundred years, are in a better position than Casaubonus to see the
methodological problems. There is not
only one kind of rationality. Compared
to the methods of knowledge and action in every day life in a precapitalistic
society bound to tradition, the methods of scholasticism, humanism and science
are equally rational. These three
varieties of rational procedure, however, are substantially different.
In the eyes of the scholastics logical
distinctions, syllogisms, and criticism of the opponent, based on the
doctrines of some authority, represented the peak of rationality.
The humanists proceeded rationally
even when their chief endeavor still pointed to imitation of the style of the
classical authors; this endeavor, though not a theoretical one, was an
entirely intellectual and learned affair. Later
the humanists gradually developed the rational methods of historical criticism
and textual emendation, methods which, unfortunately, up to now have been much
less analyzed than those of physics and mathematics.
Neither the scholastics nor the
humanists, however, used the methods of science.
As far as humanism is concerned, this
fact is partly a consequence of the difference of subject matters: experiments
can not be performed in the study of literary products of the past.
It can not be explained by the
peculiarity of the objects of their studies, however, that the humanists
virtually never investigated causes. This
is a difference of mental attitude that basically distinguishes humanism from
science. The humanist, proud of his
erudition, gathers single facts, the scientist wants to explain and to
predict. And even methodologists of
our time might disagree on the question as to whether the humanists did not
use quantitative methods and never investigated general laws, because their
field of research does not admit these methods, or because their interests lie
in a different direction. Even today
these methods are almost exclusively reserved to the natural sciences; they
are used in the social sciences more rarely and extremely seldom in the
investigation of literary and historical objects.
In our opinion this fact has less to
do with
57
intrinsic differences between natural objects
and human activities than with the descent from Renaissance humanism of our
humanistic studies. Investigation of
causes and general laws, quantitative methods (and experimentation) do not
fit, sociologically and intellectually, into scholasticism and humanism.
These methods, the very
characteristics of science, do not go back to the “liberal arts” of the Middle
Ages and the Renaissance; they rather ascended to the scholars and professors
from the ranks of the artisans. But
this did not happen before the end of the sixteenth century and will be
discussed in the following sections.
9. Sociology of Extra-Italian
Humanism
A few words are necessary on the sociology of
the extra-Italian humanists. The
Italian origin of European humanism has hardly ever been doubted.
Numerous German, French, English, and
Spanish humanists had studied in or visited Italy.
The Councils of Constance (1414-1418)
and Basle (1431-1449), at which prelates and princes with their secretaries
met from all parts of Europe, contributed much to the spread of humanism.
Just as in Italy, in Germany, France,
and England political secretaries were the first representatives of the
humanistic spirit. Even before the
Council of Constance, in the time of Petrarch, there were humanists in the
imperial offices of Charles IV at Prague. Jean de Montreuil, the first French
humanist, was secretary to the curia at Avignon, to the Dauphin, and later
chancellor to Charles VI (1380-1422) of France.
A few decades later Adam de Molyneux,
the first English humanist, was secretary of state to Henry VI of England.
Still in the sixteenth century there
were such humanistic officials outside Italy: the chancellor Thomas More
(1480-1535) in England and the secretary to Louis XII, Guillaume Budé
(1467-1540) in France are the most famous examples.
In extra-Italian humanism, however, political
secretaries played a smaller part because the Papal See and the great number
of Italian princes, city republics, and city tyrants were lacking in France
and England. In Germany there were a
considerable number of princes, free city republics, and prelates subject to
the Emperor alone and, consequently, a considerable number of humanist office
holders and city clerks. Yet even in
Germany as early as in the first half of the sixteenth century virtually all
the more eminent humanists were professors. This
predominance of the teaching profession can be accounted for by the specific
development of higher instruction in Central Europe.
In Germany between 1456 and 1544 no
fewer than ten universities were founded. These,
as new institutes, were less open to medieval traditions than the old Italian
universities and some of them owed their foundation even to the direct
intention of the reigning princes to promote humanism.
After the appearance of Luther, in
addition, many protestant princes and cities founded secondary schools, all of
them with humanistic curricula. Most
of the old Latin schools had given up the medieval curriculum even before
Luther. In Germany, for all these
reasons, classical scholars with theoretical interests had considerably more
opportunities to teach
58
as university professors or as rectors and
masters of secondary schools than in Italy.
In western Europe too most of the fifteenth and
sixteenth century humanists were professors. Many
of them taught eloquence at the universities of Paris, Montpellier, and
Bourges, Oxford and Cambridge, Louvain and Leyden.
Since outside Italy the universities,
usually, offered resistance to the intrusion of humanism, at two of them
special colleges for the studies of ancient languages were established, the
collegium trilingue at Louvain in Belgium (1518) and the college de France at
Paris (1531). Everywhere the
humanists were members of the faculties of arts which, however, were
considered merely preparatory for the other faculties and afforded less pay to
their professors. Only at Paris were
there also humanist professors of law, the great role played by the newly
introduced Roman Law in France accounting for the considerable number of
jurist-philologists. In England after
1512 several new “public schools” came into existence where also many
humanists were headmasters and masters. In
Switzerland the University of Basel (founded in 1459) was a center of
humanism. In the late sixteenth
century the French professors, in the early seventeenth the Dutch were the
leading classical scholars in Europe.
Paris jurist-philologists: cf. The Cambridge
Modern History, vol. I, New York 1903, p. 577; English Public School,
ibid. 1, p. 582.
The early appearance and the great number of
professors must not be interpreted as evidence of the origin of extra-Italian
humanism from academic instruction. It
was, on the contrary, rather want of skilled political secretaries that
produced the new educational establishments.
In Prussia, before the foundation of the university of Konigsberg, the
elector of Brandenburg applied to Melanchthon, then the leading classical
scholar in Germany, for an expert Latinist. The
elector, as he expressly wrote, needed good Latinists, then lacking in
Prussia, for his diplomatic correspondence with Poland.
To satisfy this want the university
was established (1544) and Melachthon’s son-in-law, professor Sabinus, became
its first rector. A few years
earlier the same Sabinus had introduced the humanistic reform at the
University of Frankfurt-on-the-Oder with a speech on the importance for the
statesman of a polished Latin style. The
foundation of the University of Konigsberg is not an isolated case.
Outside Italy the humanistic reform of
the universities was everywhere carried through under pressure from the
princes against the resistance of the Scholastic minded professors.
The collegium trilingue in Louvain was
established by the bequest of the royal counselor Busleiden; the college de
France by King Frances I, upon the instigation of his political secretary
Budé: in both cases humanist statesmen were the real founders.
The charters of several German
Renaissance universities disclose the influence of Enea Silvio Piccolimini,
then an official in the imperial chancery. As
far as humanism spread to eastern Europe the royal chanceries at Prague, Ofen,
and Cracow were its first seats. Everywhere
in Germany the princes, reigning prelates, municipalities, and, primarily, the
emperor were the
59
real protectors of humanism.
Their motives, probably, were
identical to those which had led to the establishment of the University of
Konigsberg. In the last analysis,
probably, most of the numerous new universities and secondary schools in all
parts of Europe were founded to promote education of skilled political
officials: “skilled”, in the Renaissance, meaning “able to write polished
Latin”.
Greek and Hebrew were not used in the diplomatic
correspondence and yet were almost always included in the new humanistic
curricula. Educational aims, however,
and the development of public instruction must not be interpreted too
narrowly. Ideas are not separated by
impenetrable walls. The ruling ranks
of the Renaissance sought after spiritual values, apt to embellish their lives
and to increase their prestige. The
monastic ideals of the Middle Ages contradicted their love of luxuries and the
university professors were pedantic scholastics.
In this period of transition the
humanistic officials were the only intellectuals able to present the required
values. Since the officials considered
eloquence and philology to be the very keys to the new world of humanism, the
princes promoted the studies of the ancient languages even beyond the direct
diplomatic requirements.
Some features of extra-Italian humanism,
however, exceed the ideology of the literati-officials as it had developed on
the other side of the Alps. The
studies of Hebrew and Greek belong to them. That
is the language of the Old Testament, this of the New.
Very few Italian humanists were
interested in Hebrew and the enthusiasm for Greek did, in Italy, not at all
refer to the New Testament. Manifestly,
in central and western Europe, the philological interest in language and words
was much more frequently combined with a religious interest in the word of God
than in the country of the Papal See. After
Luther and Calvin this combination resulted in the well known alliance between
humanism and Protestantism. Both
partners hardly had more in common than certain individualistic tendencies and
hostility to catholic scholasticism. A
few Renaissance universities, however, were founded at least as much to
further protestant theology as to promote humanistic eloquence.
All these relations need not be
analyzed here. The Lutheran and
Calvinistic varieties of humanism have nothing to do with our problems, since
their relationship to the science of philology is independent of the question
as to whether the philologist deals with Tacitus or the text of the Bible.
Sixteenth century protestant theology
is certainly not nearer to science than the contemporary secular philology.
At the German universities Lutheran
theology rather soon returned to methods not very different from those of the
scholastics. Even disputations, which
had first been eliminated from the artistic faculties by the humanists, were
reintroduced a few decades later. Historical
criticism in the manner of Laurentius Valla was first applied to the Bible by
the heretic Jew Spinoza in the late seventeenth century and by Jean Astruc,
the catholic physician, in the early eighteenth century.
Protestant theology did not contribute, substantially, to the
development of the philological methods until the eighteenth century.
60
On the development of the German universities in
the period of humanism cf. Friedrich Paulsen: Geschichte des gelehrten
Unterrichts auf den deutschen Schulen, 3rd. ed., Leipzig 1919, vol. I,
book 1, chap. 4 and book 2, chap. 1-4; on the German secondary schools,
ibid 1, 5 and II, 4-7. A
comprehensive exposition and sociological analysis of the intrusion in the
non-German universities of humanism would be desirable.
A few data in Stephen d’Irsy:
Histoire des Universités, vol. I, Paris 1933, chapter 10 and 11.
On the foundation of the University of
Konigsberg cf. Paulsen op. cit. I, 241.
Foundation of the collegium trilingue ibid. 129; Aeneas Sylvius
and German university charters ibid. 138; the German princes, prelates,
and municipalities and the humanistic university reforms ibid. 172 and
112 (Wittenberg), 121 (Rostock, Greifswald), 123 (Mainz), 128 (Cologne), 131
(Vienna), 135 ff. (Heidelberg), 139 (Basel, 142 (Tuebingen), 153 f.
(Nuernberg); foundation of protestant universities for theological reasons, p.
252 f. (Jena and Helmstedt) (1558 and 1576). Elimination
of the disputations ibid., 120 f., their reintroduction, 271 ff.
In spite of their great number the professors
were not the only humanists in western and central Europe.
There were in Germany numerous
court-humanists to prelates and princes and wandering poets making their
living as dispensers of fame by selling laudatory lines to more or less
munificent municipalities. Culturally,
however, fifteenth century Germany had not yet caught up with the native
country of the Renaissance. Compared
to their Italian colleagues the German literati-humanists, therefore, were
rather poor fellows, both financially and intellectually.
Ulrich von Hutten (1488-1523), the
merciless antagonist of the medieval spirit, is the most brilliant of them.
In his adventurous life - he was
successively a student, soldier, courtier with the archbishop of Mainz, poet
laureate, and a persecuted fugitive - he resembles more the wandering scholars
of the late Middle Ages than the successful Italian literati such as Filelfo
and Panormita. The first German
humanist professors too really belonged with the wandering poets.
“Professors” Peter Luder (14 15-1476)
and Conrad Celtes (1459-1508) moved from university to university, giving
lectures on poetry, sought to sell their eulogies to cities and prelates,
occasionally worked as political secretaries, and lead a rather loose life,
more similar to the Italian literati than to pedantic university men.
Only after 1520, in the period of
Melanchthon, when humanism had gained a firm footing at the faculties of arts,
did the German humanist professors adopt the mode of life of their more
respectable colleagues. In France Jean
Dolet (1509-1546) differed considerably from the professors.
He was successively secretary of the
French embassy in Venice, poet, orator, printer, and eventually was executed
as a heretic. Furthermore there were,
as in Italy, humanist printers in Basle (Amerbach, Froben, Cratander), in
Paris (Robertus Stephanus), in Antwerp and Leyden (Plantin, Elzevir); many
other humanists were employed by these printers. There were quite a number of
humanist catholic canons and protestant pastors in Germany, humanist
physicians to prelates, and humanists living with aristocratic patrons in
France.
One humanist, the most famous of all of them,
Erasmus of Rotterdam (1467-1536), resembles sociologically, even the modern
literary celebrities. Erasmus
originally had been a priest. He
entered the service of the bishop of Cambrai and
61
went with him to Paris where he lived as a Latin
teacher. As a tutor to an English
nobleman he came to England, then gave lectures at Oxford and Cambridge and
became a professor of divinity at Cambridge. Later
he went to Basel and lived in the house of the humanist printer Froben.
Froben not only paid him a salary for
his activity as a literary adviser and proof reader but, as a novelty, also
royalties for his books. Though
Erasmus also received pensions from patrons, he is the first author in history
to live, to a substantial degree, from the sale of his publications to an
anonymous public. Of his Adagia
(translations included) thirty thousand copies are said to have been sold in
Europe during the author’s lifetime. Only
three hundred years later when, with the rise of the middle classes, a large
educated public had come into existence, did professional writers, living on
the return of their publications, become a common phenomenon.
In his period Erasmus is an
exceptional case, accounted for by his unusual fame.
He does, therefore, not essentially
differ in his intellectual attitude from the other humanists as, in general,
ideas are influenced by sociological changes only if considerable groups of
individuals are affected. Not until
the nineteenth century did the rise of professional writers leave noticeable
marks on modern ideology, as, for example, on the modern ideas on genius,
posterity, and misunderstood persons.
On Erasmus as a professional writer, cf. John
Clyd Oswald: A History of Printing, New York 1928, p. 135 ff., and G.H.
Putnam: Books and their Makers During the Middle Ages, New York
1897, II, 214 ff.
On the whole the sociological bases of
extra-Italian and Italian humanism do not substantially differ.
Beyond the Alps too the humanistic
style and the humanistic spirit arose first in the political offices.
Everywhere the political secretaries
underwent the same social development as in Italy.
Everywhere they turned into literati,
dependent on patrons, living as dispensers of fame on the one hand, as
professors on the other. Everywhere,
therefore, eloquence, erudition, and fame were the professional aims of
humanism proper. Outside Italy the
humanists took a considerably greater part in the religious struggles of the
period although, sociologically, the alliance between humanism and
protestantism was a rather extrinsic affair, however seriously it may have
been taken by many humanists. Apart
from this more religious attitude the greater percentage of professors is,
sociologically, the greatest difference between European and Italian humanism.
The ideals of eloquence and fame,
therefore, had fewer and less brilliant advocates beyond the Alps.
Literary dispensers of fame were
virtually absent especially in England. One
more sociological phenomenon that seems to be peculiar to England would
require further analysis. In the later
half of the sixteenth century, apparently, more English scholars with academic
training published works in the vernacular on problems of mathematics and the
mechanical arts than in any other European country.
England, furthermore, is the only
country in Europe in which the first printed book - Caxton’s The Dictes or
Sayings of the Philosophers - appeared in the vernacular.
It dealt, of course, with
62
classical philosophers and was the translation
of a French book. These two facts are
possibly connected. English scholars,
apparently, looked down on the mechanical arts less than their continental
colleagues; and a public with theoretical interests though without university
affiliation was in England possibly more numerous than abroad.
If both facts are correct their
historico-sociological explanation would be of importance for the problem of
the genesis of modern science.
The following list of occupations of
extra-Italian humanists before 1600 is based, primariily, on Sir John Edwin
Sandys op. cit., The Cambridge Modern History, vol. 1, chap. 16,
the Allgemeine Deutsche Biographic, the Grande Encyclopedic, the
Biographic Nationale de Belgique, and the Oxford Dictionary of
National Biography. The list
contains 72 persons; 45 of them (62,5%) are professors, nine (12.5%) political
office holders. The corresponding list
of Italian humanists (above pp. 6 ff.; 43 persons) contains 15 (34.9%)
professors and educators and 15 (34.9%) political secretaries.
Although both lists are not at all
complete, they are composed according to analogous principles and may be
compared. The comparison shows
the much greater percentage of professors among the extra-Italian humanists.
Both lists contain only better known
authors and, in the period of early humanism, also humanists noteworthy for
sociological reasons. Authors remote
from classical scholarship proper have not been listed, even if they play a
leading part in the Renaissance literature of their countries.
Of the seven leading French
Renaissance poets (“La Pleiade”) one (Dorat) was a professor, one (Belleau)
secretary to a marquis, and five (Ronsard, Du Bellay, Jodelle, Baif, Pontus de
Thyard) were noblemen.
secretaries and political officials:
France:
Jean de Montreuil (1361-1418,
chancellor to Charles V, friend of Lionardi Bruni, historiographer); Jean
Lemaire (1473-1525, royal financial clerk, secretary to the count of Ligny,
historiographer and poet); Guillaume Budé (1467-1540, secretary to Louis XII,
maître de requêtes, diplomatic missions; pioneer in the studies of Roman Law
and Roman coinage); Jacques de Thou (1553-1617, councillor of state).
Germany: Johann of Neumarkt (d. 1380, notary, bishop and chancellor to
Charles IV, friend of Petrarch); Willibald Pirckheimer (1440-1530, counselor
and ambassador of Nuremberg, historiographer, translator); Sebastian Brant
(1457-1521, professor of law, Basle; city clerk Strassburg); Johannes
Cuspinianus (1473-1529, poet and statesman). England: Adam de
Molyneux (d. 1450, keeper of the privy seal to Henri VI), Thomas More
(1480-1535). Holland: Busleiden (d. 1518, royal counselor).
Professors, master of secondary schools:
France:
Nicolas de Clemanges (1360-1440, professor of
eloquence, Paris); Faber Stapulensis (1455-1537, professor, Paris); Alciati
(1492-1550, professor of Roman law at Avignon, Bourges and Italian
universities); Grouchy (1520-1572, professor of philosophy at Bordeaux and
Paris); Pierre Ramus (15 15-1572, professor of philosophy and eloquence,
Paris); Cujas (1522-1590, prof. of law at Toulouse, Geneva and German
universities), Hotman (1524-1590, professor of law); Doneau
(l527-159l,jurist); Brisson (1531-1591, jurist); Godefroy (1549-1621, jurist);
Casaubonus (1559-1614, professor at Geneva and Montpellier, lectuer du roi and
librarian at Paris); Passerat (1534-1602, professor of eloquence, Paris);
Turnebus, Dorat, Lambin (sixteenth century, royal readers). Germany:
Peuerbach (1423-1461), magister, lectures as the first at the University
of Vienna on Latin poets, visits Italy, astronomer-humanist); Regiomontanus
63
(1436-1476, visits Italy, magister Vienna,
librarian to Mathias Corvinus, Budapest; lecturer Nuremberg, bishop,
astronomer-humanist); Peter Luder (1431-1474, wandering poet and professor;
M.D. Padua, political secretary to Sigismund of Austria); Hegius (1433-1498,
master at secondary schools); Rudolphus Agricola (1440-1485, studies in Italy;
town clerk Groningen, prof. Heidelberg, often diplomatic missions); Wimpeling
(1450-1528, professor); Reuchlin (1455-1522; visits Italy, counselor to the
count of Wurtemberg, judge of the Swabian Confederation, professor); Conrad
Celtes (1459-1506, poet laureate, wandering professor); Von den Busch
(1468-1534); Heinrich Bebel (14711528) and Helius Hessen (1488-1540):
Wandering poets and professors; Melanchthon (1497-1565, prof.); Simon Grynaeus
(1493-1541, head master, professor); Joachim Camerarius (1500-1570, prof.);
Johannes Sturm (1507-1589, prof.); H. Wolf (1516-1580, secretary to J.J.
Fugger, headmaster); Neander and Basilius Faber (16th cent., headmasters);
Crusius, Frischlin, and Xilander (16th century, professors); Justus Lipsius
(1547-1606, secretary to Cardinal Granvella, prof. at Jena, Leyden, and
Louvain). England and Scotland: William Lily (1468-1522,
highmaster of St. Paul’s); Richard Croke (1522, public orator, Cambridge);
John Cheke (1540 regius professor, Cambridge); George Buchanan (1506-1582,
professor, public official); Roger Ascham (1515-1568, Cambridge); Thomas
Wilson (1525-1584); Andrew Melville (1545-1622); John Owen (1560-1622,
master).
Physicians:
Julius Caesar Scaliger (1484-1558, in Italy
soldier, physician to French bishop); Rabelais (1490-1553, proofreader,
physician); Linacre (1460-1524, Greek studies in Italy, M.D. Padua, physician
to Henry VIII of England, later priest); Hartmann Schedel (1440-15 14, M.D.
Padua, physician).
Theologians, monks, clergymen:
Jean Heynlin and Guillaume Fichet (professors of
theology at the Sorbonne, introduce first printing press in Paris in 1470,
first printed book: the letters of Gasparino Barzizza); Amyot (15 13-1593,
professor Bourges; bishop of Auxerre); William Selling and William Hadley
(benedictines, 1460-170 Greek studies in Italy); William Grocyn (1446-1519,
professor of theology, Oxford prebends); Colet (1466-15 19 dean of St. Paul,
London, prebends); Latimer (1485-1555, bishop of Worcester); Rudolf von Langen
(1438-1519, canon MUnster); Conrad Muth (1417-1526, canon Gotha); Thomas
Gechauff(1510-1551, German pastor).
Living with patrons:
Joseph Justus Scaliger (1540-1609, living with
French nobleman).
64