The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Edgar Zilsel
The Genesis of the Concept of
Physical Law *
Content |
|
6. 16th Century
Theological and Juridical Writers
8. Rising of the Natural
Sciences
10. The Universal Laws of
Nature HHC: titling added |
The Philosophical
Review, 51 (3 May 1942, 245-279. |
INVESTIGATION of physical laws is
among the most important tasks of modern natural science. The naturalist observes recurrent
associations of certain events or qualities. He is convinced that these regularities,
observed in the past, will hold in the future as well, and he calls them “laws
of nature”, especially if he has succeeded in expressing them by mathematical
formulas. Knowledge of physical
laws is of the greatest importance both to the theorist and to the engineer.
Whoever knows a law of nature is
able to predict and, consequently, to control events: without investigation of
laws there is no modern technology. As Western civilization of the modern era
is based materially on its technology, so it is distinguished spiritually from
the cultures of all other periods and nations by making the investigation of
natural laws the basic task of science. To primitive and oriental civilizations
the concept of physical law is quite unknown. We shall see that it was virtually
unknown to antiquity and the middle ages, and that it did not arise before the
middle of the seventeenth century.
It is strange that, in spite of its
importance, the genesis of the concept of natural law has not yet been
thoroughly investigated. Yet this
is but a symptom of the rather unsatisfactory state of research in the field of
the history of ideas in general. We
must not confuse, however, the juridical term “natural law” with the same term
in the sense in which it is used by our naturalists. As is generally known, the juridical
concept (ius naturale, lex naturalis) design-
* This essay is part of a study undertaken with the help
of grants from the Committee in Aid of Displaced Foreign Scholars, the Social
Science Research Council, and the Rockefeller Foundation.
nates moral commands that are based
not on statute law but on reason, divine commandment, and moral instinct, and
are common to all nations. It
asserts how reasonable beings shall behave, whereas natural laws, as they
are studied by modern naturalists, state and describe as a mere matter of fact
how physical processes do take place. Numerous historical inquiries on the
former concept have clarified its development.
1 On the other hand, the historical remarks on the concept
of physical law are as rare as they are poor. In this field the most valuable
preliminary work has been done, up to now, by the authors of a few dictionaries.
2 We shall use the material collected by them and try to
increase it in essential points. Since the historical problem we are
dealing with is intricate and the literature that must be taken into account is
very extensive, we do not make a claim to completeness. The juridical concept of natural law will
not be discussed in this article. Yet we cannot disregard it completely,
since it cannot be neatly separated from the naturalist’s concept in its
embryonic stage.
The concept of physical law, as it
is used in modern natural science, does not contain any ideas of command and
obedience. Yet it obviously
originates in a juridical metaphor. In a well governed state there will be
laws which are for the most part observed by the citizens. Lawbreaking will occur comparatively
seldom, and will be punished when detected. The more powerful the government and the
cleverer the police is, the rarer it will be. Let us suppose now the government to be
omnipotent and the police to be omniscient. In this ideal case the behavior of the
citizens would completely conform to the demands of the
lawgiver
1. Cf. the article
“Natural Law” in the Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences (New York,
1933), xi, 284ff. (Georges Gurvitch).
2. The remarks in Ernst Cassirer,
Das Erkenntnisproblein (2nd ed., Berlin, 1911), I, 367ff. and especially
in Franz Borkenau, Der Übergang vom feudalen zum bürgerlichen Weltbild
(Paris 1934), 15-97 are not quite reliable. The article “law” in Murray’s New
English Dictionary gives most valuable material. Some material is to be found in Littré’s
French, in Liddell-Scott’s Greek, and in Harper’s Latin Dictionary. The Thesaurus Linguae Latinae has
not yet proceeded to the article “lex”. The Vocabulario della Crusca and
Du Cange, Glossarium Mediae et Infimae Latinitatis, do not contain
material referring to our problem. Hans Kelsen in his article “Die
Entstehung des Kausalgesetzes aus dem Vergeltungsprinzip”, Journal of Unified
Science (‘Erkenntnis,), 1940, 69 ff., and his book Vergeltung und
Kausalitat (which will appear in Holland) derives the ideas of causality and
physical law from the juridical idea of retribution. Kelsen’s valuable paper could not be used
in this article.
246
and laws would be always observed.
With such an ideal state nature was
compared in the seventeenth century. The observable recurrent associations of
physical events, in which the philosophers and scientists of the period began to
be interested, were interpreted as divine commands and were called natural
laws. Thus the concept of
natural law originated in theological ideas. Later these non-empirical components fell
gradually into oblivion. Our
historical investigation, therefore, will have to trace the idea of God as a
lawgiver to nature and the influence of this idea on the rising natural
sciences. Since one is, generally
speaking, inclined to consider contemporary ideas as a matter of course and to
ascribe them uncritically to thinkers of the past, we shall bring into
prominence the differences from modern thinking before the seventeenth century.
Finally we shall try to explain
sociologically why the concept of physical law was lacking then and why it
developed in the period of Descartes, Hooke, Boyle, and
Newton.
2. The roots of our concept go back
to antiquity. They consist in a few
passages of the Bible and the Corpus Juris. A few other ancient ideas are of less
importance.
The divine lawgiver is the central
idea of Judaism. Since God in
addition is the creator of the world, it is easy to understand that the idea
arose of his not only having given the moral and ritual laws to his people, but
also having prescribed certain prohibitions to the physical world. In a description of God’s power and
omniscience Job 28, 26 says that God made a law for the rain (and
a way for lightning and thunder). The Hebrew text uses the word chok.
This is derived from the verb
chokak, meaning to engrave, and is the same term which is used for moral
and ritual laws in the Old Testament. The Septuagint translates very freely “he
numbered the rain (HHC- Greek not reproduced)”, the Vulgate literally
gives ponebat legem. The
same word chok, which however in this context means rather boundary, is
used in Job 26, 10, which says that the Lord made a boundary
(Septuagint: [HHC- Greek not reproduced], Vulgate: terminum)
to the water, until light and darkness come to an end. Likewise Job 38, 10 says the Lord
set a boundary (chok, [HHC- Greek not reproduced],
terminos), bars, and doors to the ocean. The following verse II, without using the
term “law”, pronounces the wording of a divine command or, better, prohibition:
the Lord says to the sea:
“Hitherto shalt thou come but no
further; and here shall thy proud waves be stayed”. The Hebrew text uses the future to
express the command, as is usual in Hebrew and is done also in the Ten
Commandments. The Septuagint and
the Vulgate too translate literally by the future.
There are a few more analogous
passages in the Old Testament Psalm 104, 9 says the Lord has set a
boundary (gevol, terminum) to the waters that they may not pass over;
that they turn not again (Hebrew: future) to cover the earth. Proverbs 8, 9 even twice uses the
word law (chok), for which in the translations, however, two different
terms are used. It says the Lord
gave his decree (chok, terminum) to the sea that the waters should not
pass his commandment (chok, legem). And Jeremiah ,5, 22
says the Lord has placed the sand for the bound of the sea by a perpetual
decree (chok, [HHC- Greek not reproduced],
praeceptum), that it cannot pass it; and though the waves thereof
toss themselves, yet can they not prevail; though they roar, yet can they not
(Hebrew: future) pass over it. 3
We have met with the most ancient
stage of the concept of physical law in ten verses of the Old Testament. The influence of the Bible on occidental
thinking is immense. These verses
were quoted through centuries again and again, and have decidedly contributed to
the formation of concepts in rising natural science. Viewing the text of the Vulgate (which
before the rise of Protestantism was the really effective factor), we twice find
the term law (lex) (Job 28, 26 and Prov. 8, 29)
and once (Job 38, II) the wording of a divine
prohibition. In this passage and especially in Jeremiah 5, 22
the idea is distinctly implied that the sea, to which the divine command
is addressed, wishes to offer resistance but, being too weak, is forced to bow
before the supreme power of the Lord. This might be a survival of primeval
animism and demonology. As subject
to divine commands rain, lightning and thunder, winds, and earth and,
especially, the sea are given: the laboratory, which is the very birthplace of
the scientific concept of natural law,
3. The following Job-verses
are somewhat less important: 28, 25. The Lord made the weight
for the winds and the measure for the waters; 38, 5. He gave the measures to earth and
stretched a line upon it; 38, 8. He shut up the sea with doors -
I am greatly indebted to Dr. Boas Kohn, librarian of the Jewish
Theological Seminary of America, for his information on the Hebrew
text.
248
still is far remote. The empirical background of the biblical
idea, presumably, is the observation that there are certain permanent traits in
nature: the waves of the sea advance and recede, when tossed up by a gale, but,
eventually, the dividing line between sea and land remains unchanged; wind and
weather produce considerable destruction, but, after all, life goes on as usual.
These observations refer to certain
empirical regularities and would not be so different from the statements made in
modern physical laws, if only the regularities were specified. A statement of the circumstances with
which, in spite of storms, the situation of the seashore is regularly
associated, would make predictions possible and would be a geophysical law.
Of course, the authors of the Old
Testament were not interested in statements like that. They were inspired by the emotional idea
that nature, being ruled by the Lord, must behave as it does, and they
restricted themselves to the vaguest indications as to how nature
behaves. The same idea of “must”
participated in the formation of the modern concept of physical law, but it was
supplemented by the exact description of the empirical facts. In the further development the idea of
necessity gradually receded to the background and eventually vanished, the
observable recurrent associations of events remaining as the only content of
physical laws. 4
3. To classical antiquity also the
idea is not quite foreign that physical processes are superintended and enforced
by God or gods as by judges. It is
implied as early as in the oldest philosophical fragment in the Greek language
that is literally left to us. In
the first half of the sixth century B.C. Anaximander says
5 that all
4. It is remarkable that in the great
document of ancient Egyptian monotheism, in Akhenaton’s major Hymn to Aton,
the sun-god Aton is praised as the creator of the universe but not as
lawgiver: neither moral nor physical laws are mentioned (cf. James H.
Breasted: The Dawn of Conscience, New York 1933, 281
ff. This is possibly connected
with the fact that, apparently, some social conditions obstructed the
development of legislation in Egypt, in contrast to Babylonia which produced the
code of Hammurabi. Actually the
Babylonian creation-story in the Gilgamesh epic conceives the sun-god Marduk as
the lawgiver to the stars. Tablet 7
raises the rhetorical question: “who prescribes the laws for (the star-gods)
Anu, Enlil, and Ea, who fixes their bounds?” and explains that Marduk
“maintains the stars in their path” by giving “commands” and “decrees” (cf.
Morris Jastrow: The Civilization of Babylonia and Assyria
(Philadelphia 1915), 441 last line
ff.).
6.
Diels, Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 5th ed., Berlin 1934, 12 B
I.
249
things arise from the indefinite,
the primary substance, and return to it “according to necessity. For they pay fine and penalty to each
other for their iniquity according to time’s order.” The inevitability of a certain physical
process is expressed here in juridical terms. Yet gods as lawgivers or judges are not
mentioned. They appear half a
century later in Heraclitus. “The
Sun”, Heraclitus says, “will not transgress his measures; otherwise the Erynyes,
the bailiffs of Dike (the goddess of justice), will find him.”
6 In Anaximander the physical regularity which is
interpreted by him half mythologically, half juridically, is still based on
metaphysical construction; nobody had ever observed that all things spring from
and return to the indefinite. In
Heraclitus, on the other hand, the physical statement is based on actual
observation, the regular course of the sun being an empirical fact. The regularity itself, however, is
presumed as obvious and not described.
With progressing rationalism the
scanty indications of a juridical interpretation of the course of nature
vanished again in the following period.
In the period of the sophists the terms “law” and “nature”, [HHC-
Greek not reproduced] and [HHC- Greek not reproduced], became even
opposites, “law” designating everything that is, as a mere convention,
artificially introduced by men. Democritus therefore did not know
anything of “natural laws”, though he attempted to explain all physical
phenomena by causes. A century
later Aristotle for the same reason never used the law-metaphor.
7 Plato uses the term “laws of
nature” only once to characterize the behavior of the healthy in contrast to the
sick human body. 8 As a characterization of the healthy and normal state
the phrase occurs also in the second century A.D.
6. Ibid., 22 B 94.
Fragment B 334 says: “all human laws are derived from the one divine law.
This… is stronger than everything.”
In a somewhat dubious scholium to a
medical poem of Nicander Heraclitus is said to have called fire and the sea
slaves to the winds “according to divine law” ([HHC- Greek not
reproduced] ibid., 22 A 14a).
7. Cf. Bonitz,
Index Aristotelicus. In Physics
II, 193a15, Aristotle points out that, if a wooden bed is dug in and
sends up a shoot, the shoot is wood but not a bed. He contrasts the perishable and
artificial shape of the bed with its permanent and natural material by calling
the former a mere “arrangement according to law” ([HHC- Greek not
reproduced]). This is the strict
opposite to the terminology of modern science, in which laws always refer to the
permanent traits of the physical processes.
8 Tim. 83e: when a man is
sick, the blood picks up the components of the food “contrary to the laws of
nature” ([HHC- Greek not reproduced]). Cf. Ast, Lexicon
Platonicuin.
in Lucianus.
9 The law-metaphor plays a certain part in the Stoics
only. The Stoics were determinists
and believed in fate and divine providence. Living in a period of rising monarchies
they viewed the universe as a great empire, ruled by the divine Logos. Consequently the idea of a natural law
was not unknown to them. For the
most part it referred to moral prescriptions based on reason. This Stoic idea is the source of the
juridical concept of natural law, which influenced jurisprudence and political
philosophy through two thousand years. A few times, however, although the two
meanings were never neatly separated, the idea was applied by the stoics to
physical processes too. Zeno, the
founder of the school, speaks of. natural laws in this ambiguous way. His disciple Cleanthes mentions the “law
according to which the prince of nature steers the universe” three times in his
well known hymn to Zeus. A few
verses later the first passage speaks of the obedience of the firmament and the
stars; the two other passages refer to moral law. His follower Chrysippus once compares the
universe at length to a state and calls reason ([HHC- Greek not
reproduced]) a law ([HHC- Greek not reproduced]) to
nature. 10 In Cicero On Laws, however, the
concept of natural law is not applied to physical objects.
The Stoics were not much interested
in physical phenomena and never gave instances of natural law in its physical
meaning. Such instances appear
about the beginning of the Christian era in Ovid. Ovid complains once of the betrayal of a
friend; his faithlessness is so monstrous, that the rivers will flow uphill, the
sun will go backwards, water will produce fire and fire water, in short, “all
things will proceed reversing nature’s laws (naturae praepostera legibus
ibunt). 11
Possibly the idea that the ordinary course of nature
must be ascribed to laws is influenced by the Stoics. On the other hand the term “law” in Ovid
designates hardly more than the opposite to disorder: in several passages
unarranged hair is
9. Amores 22: “the
legislature of nature” ([HHC- Greek not reproduced]) is observed among
animals,, as pederasty is unknown to them.
10. Zeno: Arnim, Stoicorum Veterum
Fragmenta, I fg. 162; Cleanthes: ibid., I fg. 537 p. 121 1.
35, p. 122 1. 20, p. 123 1. 5; Chrysippus: ibid., II fg. 528, cf.
fg. 919.
11. “Tristia I, 8 verse 5.
In Met. 15, 71 (Rim) Ovid
says of Pythagoras that he knew all secrets of nature, the origins of snow,
lightning, and earthquakes - and the “law according to which the stars
move”.
251
called “hair without law (sine
lege)” by him. 12 A rather isolated passage in the Stoic Seneca, however,
seems nearer to the modern usage of language. Seneca is not surprised that comets,
being a very rare phenomenon, are “not yet subjected to certain laws (nondum
teneri legibus certis)”; posterity will be surprised, he says, that we
ignored such obvious things. 13
Possibly the Stoic idea of the divine law which is
identical with the divine reason is here involved.
At any rate the law-metaphor was not
quite unknown to the ancients. This
is illustrated by the term astronomy. The Greek word nomos means
law, and the science of the stars could not have been called astronomy if the
idea had not existed that the order and regularity of the stellar movements were
analogous to human law. The names
astronomy and astrology originally were synonymous.
14 As early as the fifth century B.C. the term “astronomy”
was familiar to Aristophanes. 15
Some authors, such as Aristotle, Archimedes, Polybius,
and Hipparch, use the term “astrology” only. Others, such as Pappus and Seneca, prefer
“astronomy”. With the increasing
influx of oriental superstition magical aspects eventually prevailed in the term
“astrology”. In the fifth century
A.D. the Latin encyclopedias for monks explain “astronomy”, literally
translating the Greek term, as the science dealing with the “law of the stars
(lex astrorum)” 16
In the astrological literature of late antiquity
sometimes laws of nature are mentioned in an entirely magical sense. Thus the
astrologer Vettius Valens (about 150 A.D.), discussing astrological
predetermination, speaks of the “legislation” of nature, fate, and the stars.
17
12. Met. I, 477; Ars. amat.
III, 133. (On Ovid cf. Deferrari-Barry-McGuire, A
Concordance of Ovid, Washington 1939, s.v.
lex.)
13. Natural. quaest. VII, 25,
3-5.
14. On the names “astronomy” and
“astrology” cf. Pauly-Wissowa, Realencyclopädie d. class.
Altertuniswissensch., Stuttgart 1896, s.v. Astronomie (Hultsch).
In addition cf. Thesaurus
Linguae Latinae s.v. astrologia, astronomia, astronomicus,
astronomus.
15. Nubes 194,
201.
16. Cassiodorus inst. 2, 7;
Isidorus diff. 2, 152.
17. Anthologiae (Kroll) 5,
cap. 9 p. 219 1.26ff. fate ([HHC- Greek not reproduced]) has given a
law ([HHC- Greek not reproduced]) to every being, surrounding
it with an unbreakable wall; (The term [HHC- Greek not reproduced] seems
to indicate influence of the Stoics) ; 7 cap. 3 p. 272
l.9ff.: nature ([HHC- Greek not reproduced];) gave
a law ([HHC- Greek not reproduced]) and encompassed man with
the wall of necessity; 9 cap. 7 p. 343 1.33ff.: the stars order the universe by
their influence without ever transgressing the boundaries of legislature
([HHC- Greek not reproduced]).
252
4. On the whole one must take good
care not to overestimate the similarity of the classical concept of nature and
modern natural science. Deterministic ideas were known to the
ancients. They were indicated as
early as in Heraclitus’ doctrine of the fiery Logos who rules the universe and
expresses himself in the cyclic change of matter. They were explained in detail in the
Stoic doctrine of fate. Nevertheless two points must not be
overlooked. First, ancient
determinists spoke much more frequently of the logos than of the
nomos, more frequently of the reason than of the law of the
universe. Secondly, the classical
determinist doctrine had a tinge of myth and emotion rather than of science and
experience. Heraclitus and the
Stoics felt the development of the whole universe as necessary and enforced, but
were not interested in single physical laws. How far remote from natural science the
determinism of the Stoics was is revealed by their giving vaticination as a
verification of their doctrine of fate. 18 The superstitious Stoics were determinists. On the other hand the ancient
representatives of the scientific interpretation of nature, such as Democritus
and Lucretius, who consistently advocated causal explanations of nature, did not
use the law-metaphor. It is
significant that, whereas modern translations of Lucretius speak of physical
laws again and again, this term was unknown to Lucretius himself.
19 Lucretius, following Epicurus, stressed three basic
principles of nature. In his poem
they play a part analogous to physical laws in modern science: nothing can be
produced from nothing, nothing can be annihilated, and the amount of motion in
nature is constant. 20
But since all quantitative details are
lacking, his “laws of conservation” (as one is tempted to call them) are
extremely vague. Moreover,
Lucretius does not call them laws, but speaks of principles. In Epicurean philosophy there are
and can be no “laws” of nature, since the gods do not take care of the
world.
18. Cf. Arnim, loc. cit.
vol. 2 cap. 6 § 4 pp. 270-272.
19 The very complete Index
Lucretianus, Gotoburgi 1911, by Johannes Paulson, gives only three passages
in which the term “law” is used in a non-juridical sense. III, 692 (Munro) states that the human
soul is not immortal but is subject to the “law of death (leti lege)”; V,
58 states that all things must perish and nothing can break “the laws of time
(aevi leges)”; and V, 720 denies the existence of chimeras,
stating that members of the body can combine only if they are adapted to each
other; all animals are bound “by these laws” (teneri legibus
hisce).
20. I, 149ff.; I,216ff.; II,
71 (Munro).
There hardly is room for physical
laws in ancient science either. Aristotle makes a few general statements
approximately corresponding to laws of motion - sublunar bodies tend to their
natural place, celestial bodies move in circles - but they are vague, incorrect,
and formulated teleologically. And,
of course, they were not called “laws” by Aristotle.
20a Peculiarly enough only three physical laws were
correctly known to the ancients: the law of the lever, the optical law of
reflexion, and the law of buoyancy. All three of them are discussed in
Archimedes, who, however, never used the term “natural law”. Although Archimedes, by far the most
eminent physicist of antiquity, certainly verified all three laws by experiments
(the law of buoyancy was even discovered by him experimentally), he does not
explain them empirically. He rather
follows the deductive method of Euclid, starts from postulates, and deduces and
proves his physical statements, as if they were mathematical theorems.
21
Even from
a mere external point of view his method is Euclidean, in so far as all theorems
are numbered as the theorems in Euclid. In a mathematical treatise, however,
there is obviously no room for the law-metaphor: Archimedes speaks as little of
the “law” of buoyancy as Euclid speaks of the “law” of Pythagoras.
22 The deductive method in Archimedes probably originated
in the same remarkable sociological phenomenon which also caused the poor state
of physics in antiquity. Ancient
civilization was based on slave labor and, in general, their patrons and
representatives did not have occupations, but lived on their rents. In ancient opinion, therefore, logical
deduction and mathematics were worthy of free-born men, whereas experimentation,
as requiring manual work, was considered to be a slavish occupation. Archimedes himself gave expression to
this contempt for manual labor and technology.
23 On the whole the development of
20a. The Mechanica, ascribed
to Aristotle, is probably spurious. It knows the principle of the lever
without using the term “law.” Cf. above footnote
7.
21. Buoyancy: de corp. fluit.
I theorems 3-7; lever: de plan. aequ. theor. 6f. The, law of reflexion is used half a
century before Archimedes in Euclid’s Optics, theor. 19 (Euclid,
Opera, ed. Heiberg-Menge vol. 7 p. 31); it was known to Archimedes (cf.
scholium 7 to Euclid’s Catoptrics, ibid. p. 348; Archimedes’
Catoptrics is lost) and is given as theorem in the (spurious)
Catoptrics of Euclid.
22. Even today physicists still speak
rather of the principle than of the law of
Archimedes.
23. Cf. Plutarch, Vitae,
Marcellus 34 and 17.
254
physics was seriously impaired in
antiquity by the contempt for manual work, technology, and experimentation.
And where physics comes to a
standstill in a rather embryonic stage the concept of physical law cannot
develop.
Another literary document of
antiquity has contributed a few ideas to the modern concept of physical law.
This is the Corpus Juris. In the introductory sections, both of
the Pandects and of the Institutes, the Stoic idea of natural law (jus
naturale) is explained. In
contrast to statute law natural law is based on mere reason, does not change,
and is common to all nations. For
the most part moral obligations - veneration of God, obedience to parents - are
given as examples. 24 On the other hand it is stated that “nature has taught
all animals the natural law”. From
it the intercourse of male and female, begetting and education of the offspring,
derive. Obviously in this
explanation two different ideas are mixed. On the one hand a statement is made on
matters of fact. The empirical fact
that mammals propagate by sexual intercourse and take care of their offspring
could be called a biological law in the modern meaning of the word. On the other hand these facts are
interpreted as results of a sort of legal permission or command, nature or God
being the lawgiver. 25 This confusion facilitated the application of the
law-metaphor to physical facts even centuries later. In the history of ideas the Corpus
Juris was almost as influential as the Bible.
5. The Christian Middle Ages
did not make any contribution to the development of our concept. We need not enlarge, therefore, on
medieval authors. Of course the
Bible passages on God as the lawgiver of the universe were often quoted and
paraphrased by the church fathers and Scholastics. The ideas also of the Stoics and the
Corpus Juris on natural law (jus naturale) were exerting some
influence. A passage in the
Christian orator Arnobius (about 300 A.D.) is of some interest, since it
gives a few instances of the physical regularities which were
explained by the theologians through divine laws. In order to prove that the Christian
religion is not anything monstrous Arnobius
28 asks his audience
whether
24. Dig. I, I, 3; Inst.
I, 2.
25. Inst. I, 2, II:
naturalia iura… divinã providentiã constituta.
26. Adv. Gentiles I,
2,
“the laws initially established”
have been overthrown since the time the new faith has spread. All instances are given in the form of
rhetorical questions. He explains
that the elements have not changed their qualities. The structure of the machine of the
universe (presumably he has in mind the astronomical system) has not dissolved.
The rotation of the firmament, the
rising and setting of the stars, have not changed. The sun has not grown cold. The change of the moon, the turn of the
seasons and of long and short days, have neither stopped nor been disturbed.
It still rains, seeds still
germinate, trees still produce and lose their leaves, etc. On the whole he takes his instances from
the same field as the Bible and Ovid do; and, of course, there is no question of
laboratory physics. A certain
predilection for astronomical and cyclic processes is significant. About 400 A.D. St. Augustine
27 developed
the concept of God’s eternal law by which the universe is ruled. Augustine’s eternal law stems from the
biblical idea of the divine lawgiver, but is an entirely teleological concept.
It is identical with the
impenetrable providence of God and has nothing to do with the physical laws of
the modern scientists.
An extensive discussion in Thomas
Aquinas throws light on the Scholastic concept of law and may be analysed here,
as far as our subject is concerned. Thomas combines seeming logical exactness
with considerable empirical vagueness. A law, according to his definition,
28 is “a rule
and measure of acts”. Yet we shall
see that in one case physical processes and phenomena are also covered by this
concept. Thomas distinguishes
positive from natural law (jus naturale).29
The former needs promulgation by the lawgiver (and
consequently has no bearing on our subject); the latter does not, since “it is
promulgated by the very fact that God instilled it into man’s mind, so as to be
known by him naturally”. 30
Later,
natural law is defined as “the participation of the eternal law in reasonable
creatures”. 31
With the “eternal law” (lex aeterna)
we have transcended the province of human actions. It is “the
27. E.g. de lib. arb. I, 6; de
civ. dei XIX, 12.
28. Summa Theol. II, I qu. 90,
art. I resp.
29. Ibid. qu. 71, art. 6,
resp. 4.
30. Ibid. qu. 90, art. 4, obj.
i resp. The agreement with the
ancient concept of natural law is obvious.
31. Qu. 91, art. 2, obj. 2
resp. Here the term lex naturalis, not jus naturale, is
used.
256
type (ratio) of divine wisdom
as directing all acts and motions”.
32 Thomas explains that God governs the acts
and motions of all creatures and is to the world as the artist is to his work.
Since in every artist the type of
the order (ratio ordinis) which is produced by him pre-exists, the type
(ratio) of the divine wisdom bears the character (rationem) of
law. So the idea is distinctly
expressed that the whole of nature (not only human actions) is subject to law.
Two points, however, must be
brought into prominence. First, the
whole idea that the type of the order of the world pre-exists in God is
obviously Platonic. And, secondly,
the order Thomas has in mind is a teleological, not a causal one: to the words
“divine wisdom”, quoted above, he makes the significant addition “moving
everything to its due end (ad debitum finem)”.
33
The
distance from the modern concept of physical law is
considerable.
Somewhat later 34
objections are discussed, stating
that irrational beings cannot be subject to the eternal law, since it cannot be
promulgated to them and since they do not participate in reason. The objections are refuted and it is
expressly stated that “all movements and actions of the whole of nature are
subject to the eternal law”. What
promulgation is to man “the impression of an inward active principle” (i.e. an
Aristotelian entelechy) is to natural things. As the only instance, however, the sea is
given, which, according to Prov. 8, 29, received a law from God.
As to natural law Thomas shares the
ambiguity with the Corpus Juris. On the one hand he gives moral
precepts as instances (evil has to be avoided); on the other he quotes the
Pandects and explains that sexual intercourse and education of the
offspring among animals are based on natural law. Man has some natural laws in common even
with inanimate things: not only man, but, as Thomas maintains, every substance
strives to preserve its being. 35
22. Qu. 93, art. I resp (cf. qu. 91,
art. I).
23. The teleological character of the
order of the world is stressed and identified with divine providence I qu.
22, art. I. Ibid. art. 2 obj. I and 3 it is explained that
Democritus and the Epicureans denied providence (and with it, as we may add,
order and eternal law) by ascribing the course of nature to “necessity of
matter”.
24. Op. cit. qu. 93, art. 5,
obj. I and 2.
25. Ibid., qu. 94, art. 2 - It
is not quite clear whether in Thomas physical regularities belong to natural or
to eternal law. In the article just
quoted [a few of them are counted with natural
law. In qu. 93, art. 5, on the
other hand, they are counted with eternal law. Natural law is restricted to reasonable
beings in qu. 91, art. 2, obj. 2.]
HHC: [bracketed] displayed
on p.258 of original.
257
On the whole Thomas combines the
biblical idea of God as the lawgiver of the universe and the ancient concept of
natural law with Platonic and Aristotelian ideas. His concept of eternal law, therefore, is
entirely teleological and identical with the idea of divine providence. Moreover, our discussion is apt to give a
distorted view of his interest in physical regularities. The passages of the Summa Theologica
in which they are mentioned have been singled out from a very extensive
exposition. In the edition of Pope
Leo XIII (Rome, 1892) they fill just two pages, whereas his whole
discussion of law extends over two hundred and seven pages. Actually the Summa Theologica is
interested in all theological problems connected with the concept of law and
deals with physical phenomena only in so far as they are mentioned in the Bible
and the Corpus Juris.
6. 16th Century Theological and
Juridical Writers
6. In discussing authors of the
modern era we have to show, first, that the concept of physical law was not
known before the seventeenth century. Since numerous authors must be
considered, we shall treat them in groups without strictly observing the
temporal sequence. We may begin
with a few theologians and jurists.
The widely read handbook of
jurisprudence Doctor and Student by Christopher Saint Germain, published
in Latin in 1532 and in English in 1530 and 1531, briefly repeats
the opinions of Thomas and the Corpus Juris on eternal law, to which the
universe is subject, and on natural law. Of the latter two meanings are
distinguished, one referring to reasonable creatures only, the other to all
creatures. 36 The first meaning is merely juridical, the second covers
also biological and physical phenomena. Seventy years later, Richard Hooker
advocates the same ideas more extensively in the first chapters of his well
known treatise The Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity, published in 1592 or
1594. 37
Of course
he knows and discusses God’s eternal law which is identical with divine
providence. As to natural law he
separates the natural law of reasonable
36. 15th edition~ London 1571, chap.
I p. 3 and chap. 5 p. 5f. On the
first editions cf. S.E. Thorne, “St. Germain’s Doctor and Student”, The
Library, IVth series, vol. X (1930) pp. 421-426.
37. Book I, chap. 3. Works
(ed. Keble, 7th ed., Oxford ,888) I 200ff.
258
beings and the natural law which is
kept “unwittingly by the heavens and elements”.
38 He adds that the latter “hath in it
more than men as yet attained to know or perhaps ever shall attain”. The very laws of nature, which one
century later became the most important subject of scientific investigation, are
considered unrecognizable. Hooker
quotes the Bible on God as the lawgiver of rain and sea and gives an enumeration
of natural laws reminiscent of Ovid and Arnobius.
39 The elements do not change their
qualities; the celestial spheres, sun and moon, move regularly; the turn of the
seasons, wind and rain, enable the earth to bear fruit. If this order were disturbed, “what would
become of man whom these things do all serve”? Obviously Hooker’s concept of natural law
is still entirely anthropocentric and teleological.
Nothing essential about our problem
is contained in Jean Bodin, the most eminent political philosopher of the period.
40 On the other hand an important advance to logical
clarification of the law-concept was made in Suarez. In his Tractatus de Legibus
(1612) the Spanish Neo-Scholastic consistently clings to the
distinction between “morals” and “nature”
41 and restricts the term “law”, in its
proper meaning, to the former. Suarez opposes the definition of law in
Thomas Aquinas because it disregards this distinction.
42 “Things lacking reason”, he says,
43 “properly,
are capable neither of law nor of obedience. In this the efficacy of divine power and
natural necessity… are called law by a metaphor.” The wording of the Scripture (he quotes
the well known passages) is said to be in accordance with this explanation.
In the section on eternal laws
44 the
Bible passages are interpreted in the same way and the statement that irrational
and even inanimate beings can be subject to the eternal law is called “a mere
mode of expression”. 45 The Corpus Juris too, when speaking of natural
laws among animals
38. Chap. 3 p.
206.
39. Ibid. p.
207.
40. De la République (1577)
does not give a general analysis of the law-concept. Universae Naturae Theatrum
(Francofurti 1597) restricts itself in the preface (fol. 3) to a few
generalities on the unchangeable course of the celestial spheres. Methodus ad facilem historiarum
cognitionem (1566) mentions “some eternal law of nature” according to which
everything undergoes a cyclic change: vices follow virtue, ignorance science,
darkness light (VII, 36). The
astronomical pattern is manifest.
41 Moralia et naturalia II,
2 §12.
42. I, I §1
43. I, I
§2
44. II, 2 §§, 10, 12,
13.
45. II, 2 §12: quaestionem esse de
modo loquendi.
259
(which, actually, are led “by
natural instinct”), makes use of a “metaphor”.
46 “The real natural law inheres in the human minds only.”
47 Certainly, Suarez knows as little of natural laws in the
modern meaning of the word as Thomas did, but his concept of law is considerably
more modern. The intellectual
change from Thomas to Suarez will be explained in our last
paragraph.
7. Beyond the ranks of theological
and juridical writers about 1600 natural law is scarcely mentioned. In 1570 John Dee, the alchemist to Queen
Elizabeth, mentions that nature “abhorreth empty space so much, that, contrary
to ordinary law, the Elements will move or stand”.47a
Montaigne in his Essais
(1582) uses the term natural law only once and in its juridical sense.
48 Shakespeare once makes Falstaff speak jokingly of
natural law in its juridical meaning. In Cymbeline (1609), on the other
hand, he calls it “nature’s law” that the human embryo remains nine months in
its mother’s womb. 49
Shakespeare thus adds one more instance of a
prescientific natural law to the instances in the Bible, Ovid, Arnobius, and
Hooker.
The term is used more frequently in
Francis Bacon. In his
Advancement of Learning (1605) Bacon discusses the pyramid of the
sciences and gives knowledge of “the Summary law of nature” as its “vertical
point”. 50 He expresses, however, his doubt whether this knowledge
can be attained by man. The
theological origin of the idea is revealed by a Latin quotation, speaking of
“the work operated by God from the beginning to the end”. In the Novum Organum (1620) the
term “law” is very often used synonymously with “form”. “When we speak of forms”, Bacon says,
51 “we mean nothing else but those laws and determinations
of the pure act which set in order and constitute a simple nature… The form of
heat and the law of heat are the same thing.” These “laws” or “forms” were treated as
rather mysterious entities by Bacon him-
46. I, 3
§8.
47. I, i
§9.
47a. Preface to Billingsley’s Euclid
translation, Sig. dj ro.
48. Essais 2, 12: there is no
natural law, since the customs of the various nations are different (ed. Villey,
Paris 1930, vol. II p. 494f.).
49. 2 Henry IV, III, 2
last lines; Cymbeline V, 4 verse 37.
50. Works (Spedding and Ellis) VI
222.
51. Nov. Org. II, 17 (Fowler,
2nd ed., Oxford 1889), p. 389. 6f. cf. ibid. I, 51 p. 228f., I,
75 p. 268; 11,2 p. 346; II, 4 and 5 p. 348ff.; II, 17 p. 399; II, 52
p. 597.
260
self. They are nearer to alchemy than to modern
science, are considered by Bacon as the very essences of things and qualities,
and are, obviously, survivals of the Aristotelian and Scholastic formae
substantiales. The only
question is how Bacon came to introduce the term “law” for this medieval
concept. As the passage in the
Advancement of Learning indicates, the Bible suggested this expression.
Thus Bacon’s terminology again
reveals the theological roots of the concept of physical law. How far remote, however, Bacon still is
from this concept is illustrated by the remarkable fact that he was ignorant
even of the law of the lever. 52
8. Rising of the Natural
Sciences
8. Now we have approached the period
of rising natural science and it is time to look for the concept of natural law
among its pioneers. The result,
however, differs considerably from expectation.
Copernicus (1543) speaks of
the “machine of the world founded by the best and most regular artificer”,
53 but never of laws of this machine or of the solar
system. The same holds of William
Gilbert, who was among the earliest adherents of Copernicus in England. In his De Magnete (1600), when
discussing the precession of the vernal point, he once speaks of a “rule and
norm of equality” that may be ascribed to complicated astronomical movements by
some hypothesis. 54 This corresponds almost exactly to the modern concept of
physical law, though the term is not used. The isolated passage must not be
overestimated. De Magnete is the first printed book on experimental
physics by a scholar. Gilbert makes
careful and numerous empirical observations, but still restricts himself in his
theoretical explanations to metaphysical generalities on the animation of the
globe and the magnet. In his
extensive discussions of magnetic phenomena he once makes three rather vague
statements which may be called magnetic laws.
55 They are, how-
52. De Augmentis V, 3,
10.
53. De Revolutionibus, preface
to Paul III. Thorn edition (Curtze) p. 5 1.32.
54. De Magnete VI, 9 p.
237.
55. Ibid. II, 32 p. 99.
Since they are for the most part
overlooked, they may be discussed here. They state that equal loadstones approach
each other with equal “incitation”. The same holds for both magnetized and
non-magnetized iron bodies. - In Gilbert’s time theoretical mechanics in general
and an exact concept of force in particular were not yet developed. His three laws compare magnetic forces
dynamically by the “incitation” of the movement they cause, “incitation”
probably being something vague between velocity, impulse, and kinetic energy.
He restricts himself to the case of
equality of forces and [does not give a
real measurement. His laws
correspond approximately to Newton’s third law (action equals reaction).]
HHC: [bracketed] displayed
on p.262 of original.
261
ever, given in a short chapter,
entitled “some problems”, are not referred to further, and are called neither
laws nor rules.
An abundance of physical laws is to
be found in Galileo. In his
manuscript Le Mecaniche, composed in about 1598 when he was a young
professor in Padua, he discusses the lever, the windlass, and the pulley, and
gives the conditions of equilibrium in quantitative terms.
56 Yet the term “law” is never used. His Discourses and Mathematical
Demonstrations on two new Sciences (1638) laid the foundation stone of
modern mechanics and mathematical physics in general. In this work
57 he discusses
the dependence of the period of a pendulum on its length, the dependence of the
number of vibrations of a string on its length, tension, cross section, and
specific gravity, in quantitative terms. He does not express these relations by
mathematical formulas, but paraphrases them in words. And he never calls them “laws” or
“rules”, but occasionally refers to the law of the pendulum as a “proportion”.
58 The same work contains his greatest achievement, the
statement of the law of falling bodies, and his discussion of projection.
59 Again the terms “law” and “rule” do not occur. The results are given in the form of
numbered theorems, propositions, lemmata, and corollaries, connected by
mathematical demonstrations. Though
the investigation is a model of experimental research, its literary exposition
clings to the traditional deductive form of Archimedes and Euclid.
60
Apparently Galileo did not know the
term “natural law”. When he
occasionally mentions the law of the lever in the Discorsi, he
paraphrases it by a long sentence and refers to it, a few lines later, as the
“ratios” (ragioni) of the lever and as “that
principle”
56
Opere, edizione nazionale, II, 147ff.
57.
Ibid. VIII, 139ff. and 143ff.
58. Ibid. 139,
I29ff.
59. Ibid. 197ff. and
288ff.
60. Ibid. 266 Archimedes,
Euclid, and Apollonius are referred to. The deductive expositions are given in
the Latin, the experiments in the Italian, sections of the Discorsi. This is a survival of the social
prejudice against manual labor. Respectable science deduces and uses the
Latin language; experimentation is the business of vernacular speaking
craftsmen. - Ibid. pp. 156-165ff. he discusses quantitatively, how the strength
of a pillar depends on its breadth, weight, and length. The results are not called “laws”, but
are numbered as propositions and corollaries on the margin.
(questo principio).
61 It is significant that the modern English and German
translations often speak of physical laws, when Galileo expresses himself
differently. When the translator
speaks of the most perfect laws of nature, Galileo only speaks of the “most
orderly world” (mondo ordinatissimo); when the translator denies that
anything can happen against the laws of nature, Galileo only says “against
nature” (contro a natura).
62
Galileo came nearest to the law-metaphor when he
discussed theological objections. A
few years before the condemnation of the Copernican doctrine by the church he
defended the rights of free investigation in a letter to Castelli (1613). The Holy Writ, he writes,
63 and Nature
both originate in the Divine Word, the former as a dictation of the Holy Ghost,
the latter as “an executor of God’s orders” (ordini di Dio) - orders, not
laws.
The law-metaphor originates in the
Bible, but what was new in Galileo’s investigation was not influenced by the
Bible. It cannot be verified here
that Galileo’s concept of science sprung from the method of contemporary
technology, since the verification would imply an analysis of the origin of
modern natural science in general.
The superior craftsmen of the sixteenth century, the artists and military
engineers, were accustomed not only to experimentation, but also to expressing
their results in empirical rules and quantitative terms. The substantial forms and occult
qualities of the scholars were of little use to them. They looked for serviceable, and, if
possible, quantitative rules of operation when they had to construct their
lifting engines, machines, and guns. In the manuscripts of Leonardo da Vinci
(about 1500) over and over again such quantitative rules of operation are given.
They are usually formulated in the
manner of cooking recipes: “If you want to know”, Leonardo says explaining the
drawing of a bent lever, “how much more than MB AM weighs, look how many times
CB is contained in AD” etc. 63a
The mathematical function-
61. Ibid. VIII, 152 1. 3ff.,
13 and ~6 (Dialogo).
62. Ibid. VII, 431.6
(Dialogo) and VIII, 6o 1.14 (Discorsi).
63. Ibid. V, 282 1.30.
Literally conforming his letter to
the Grand Duchess of Tuscany (1615) ibid. 316 1.25.
63a.
Ravaisson-Mollien, Les Manuscripts de Leonard de Vinci, Paris 1891, vol.
6, Ms. 2038 fol 3r. On the other hand Leonardo, discussing the propagation of
light, says in a more poetical and theological vein: “0 marvellous Necessity… by
a supreme and irrevocable law every natural action obeys [thee by the directest
possible process.. thou by thy law containest all effects to issue from their
causes in the briefest possible way” (Codice Atlantico, ed. Pinnati,
Milan 1901, III, 1161.
263
concept, applied to physical
phenomena, appeared for the first time in the literature of mankind in a
prescription for gunners. In 1546,
eighteen years before the birth of Galileo, Tartaglia, in a booklet on gunnery,
fortification, and applied mathematics, pointed out that an elevation of 25°
gives a gun a certain range; if the elevation is 300 the range is “much
greater”, if 350 “greater”, if 400 “somewhat greater”, if 45° “a bit greater”,
if 500 “a bit smaller”, if 550 “somewhat smaller” and so forth. One can make a table of the ranges,
Tartaglia continues, and give it to the officer; the officer can tell the gunner
how to level the gun, but the table itself can be kept secret, just as “the
apprentices can carry out the prescriptions” according to the directions of the
apothecary. Tartaglia was a quite
poor, self-educated mathematics teacher and adviser to gunners, architects, and
merchants, ten pennies a question. He was not a university scholar but
belonged with the superior artisans.
63b
These quantitative rules of the
early capitalistic artisans are, though they are never called so, the
forerunners of the modern physical laws. Galileo set the investigation of
functional relations between physical quantities as the main task for science.
64
The
concept of physical law and its paramount scientific importance was perfectly
familiar to him. But the term “law”
was never used by him, since he cared more for his experiments than for the
writings of the theologians and the Corpus Juris.
Stevin and Pascal proceeded in a way
similar to Galileo’s: both were entirely familiar with the concept without ever
using the term “natural law”. Stevin (1585 and 1608) views the
mechanical problems with the eyes of an engineer. Still he explains important laws of
statics (the mechanical advantage of the inclined plane, the principle of
Archimedes) in the deductive way of Euclid, giving numbered definitions,
postulates, and propositions. 65
Pascal
63b Quesiti et inventioni I, I
; “ten pennies” (scudi) ibid. III, 10.
64. Galileo himself declared the
problem of the curve of projection (which puzzled the gunners of the period) as
the starting point to his study of the law of falling bodies. Opere, letter 2300 to Marsili
(1632), XIV, 386.
65. “Hypomnemata Mathematica,
,6o8, vol. 4, Statics.
264
(1663) expressly rejects the
doctrines of abhorrence of vacuum and of occult qualities.
66 He knows that all machines satisfy the principle of
work, that the heights of two liquids in a communicating tube are inversely
proportional to their densities, and discusses the principle of Archimedes - all
this without ever speaking of laws. 67 Occasionally he mentions meteorological “rules” for the
variations in the height of the barometer.
68 His ignorance of the law-metaphor is remarkable, since
he was intently dealing with theological problems; his physical and his
religious interests seem to have been separated by an impenetrable wall. The doctrine of natural law in the
juridical meaning, however, was known and agreed to by him.
69
9. Kepler seems to be the first
naturalist who, occasionally, used the law-metaphor. His well known three laws of planetary
movement, however, never are called laws by him. The first and second, given in his
Astronomia Nova (1609), are paraphrased in long expositions;
70 the third,
published in Harmonices Mundi (1619), once is called a “theorem”.
71
On the other hand Kepler frequently
compares the inverse proportion of velocity and solar distance of a planet
(which is the basis of his second law) to the analogous proportion between the
force and arm of a balanced lever. And in this context he sometimes speaks
of the “law”, more frequently however of the “ratios”, of the lever.
72 Sometimes he uses the term law as almost synonymous with
measure or proportion. Once he
draws a diagram in order to clarify the question “which laws are required” in
representing a planetary orbit. Or
he remarks that the earth receives “the laws of its celerity and slowness” in
proportion to its approach to and its movement away from the sun.
73 Other passages are
66.
Traitez de l’équilibre etc. Oeuvres (ed.
Brunschvieg-Boutroux III, 224 and 254.
67. Ibid. 163, 171,
178.
68. Fragments, Oeuvres, II,
520.
69. Pensées, Oeuvres XIII, 216
no. 294.
70. III cap.
59f.
71. V cap. 3 (Opera, ed. Frisch V,
280).
72. Astr. Nov., Opera III, 392:
lege staterae; Epitome Astr. Cop. Opera vol. VI, 373: quae sunt
huius celeritatis et tarditatis leges et exempla? Exemplum genuinum est in statera. -
Rationes staterae; Astr. nov. Opera III, 300, 390, 391 and Ep. Astr.
Cop., Opera VI 405.
73. Astr. Nov. Opera III, 315: quibus legibus opus sit ad... orbitam repraesentandam; ibid.
149: leges celeritatis et tarditatis suae accipere ex modulo
accessus... et recessus.
nearer to modern terminology. He discusses the spread of forces from
the sun and points out that the force diminishes either with the second or with
the third power of the distance; this follows “from the very law of emanation”,
for the force, although being immaterial, is “not free from geometric laws”.
74 The background of these expositions is formed by
theological ideas. Kepler ends a
long astronomical discussion with the remark that some “geometrical incertitude”
is implied in the problem. “And I
do not know”, he adds, 80
“whether this is not repudiated by
God himself, who, up to now, is always found (deprehenditur) to be
proceeding in a mathematical way.” From this the Pythagorean doctrine in
Kepler’s Harmonices mundi follows quite consistently, stating that God
ordered the universe according to the principle of “geometrical beauty”. In a letter to Fabricius (May 1605)
Kepler reports that he has most laboriously treated the irregularities of the
planetary movement “until they were at last accommodated to the laws of nature”.
76 It can hardly be doubted that these
laws of nature are nothing else than the divine principles of mathematical
beauty.”
Kepler was at the same time a
Pythagorean and a devout Protestant. His first work, the Mysterium
Cosmographicum (1596), explained the solar system by means of the five
Platonic bodies. His Harmonices
Mundi (1619), which gave the third law among numerous mathematical relations
without any physical importance, advocated the harmony of the spheres. He considered it his scientific task to
reveal the mathematical order of the universe, to describe its beauty, and to
praise God as its founder. Thus he
changed the divine laws of the Bible into geometric prescriptions and used the
term “law” almost as synonymous with ratio or proportion. He is distinguished from the numerous
Neo-Pythagoreans of the late Renaissance by his care for empirical observation
and his mathematical genius which succceeded in discovering the regularities in
apparently most irregular phenomena. His interpretation of these laws,
however, still is animistic. After
having stated “the laws and quantity of the variation” of the planetary
velocity, he
74. Ibid. 303.
75. Ibid. 397.
76 Opera III,
37.
77. In his Ad Vitellionem
Paralipomena (1604, Opera II) he gives many optical laws (not yet the
law of refraction). The term “law” is never used; they are numbered as
propositions and corollaries in the manner of Euclid.
266
raises the question “whether the
laws are such, that they probably can be known to the planet”. He explains extensively that the movement
of the planet probably results from the “wrestling” of its animal and its
magnetic faculty, the “mind” of the planet perceiving a certain angle and
reckoning its sine. This
sense-perception without eyes does not seem impossible at all to him. For an analogy he refers, on the one
hand, to the sublunar bodies adjusting their behavior to the stars and, on the
other, to his own mother who has born all of her children under the same
constellation without making use of eyes.
78 Obviously Kepler’s
concept of law is quite near to astrology.
79
The concept of natural law occurs
fully developed in Descartes. In
his Discours de la Méthode (1637) Descartes starts the short exposition
of his new philosophy of nature with the declaration that he has found “laws
which God has put into nature”. God
has impressed the ideas of them on the human mind in such a way, that their
universal validity cannot be doubted.
80 In the following
81 it is
explained that God, after the creation of matter, let nature develop from chaos
in accordance to these laws. Even
if God had created several worlds the “laws of nature” (loix de la nature)
would be valid in all of them. The laws themselves, however, are not
given in the Discours. When
discussing the circulation of the blood Descartes only mentions that “the rules
(règles) of nature are identical with the rules of mechanics”.
82 As an appendix to the
78. Astr. nov. cap. 57
(Opera III, 392-397) ; Cf. ibid. cap. 39 pp. 317-320. The
astrological passage p. 319.
79. The question how the planets
manage to move regularly results from the elimination of the solid spheres by
Tycho Brahe, as Kepler himself states (ibid. p. 319). The same problem had been discussed a few
years before (1591) by Patrizzi (Nova de Universis Philosophia, Pancosmia
12; 2nd. ed. Venice 1593, fol. 91 col. 3). Though Patrizzi does not speak of
laws and contrasts only the “order of the world” to chaos, he is quite near to
an embryonic concept of natural law. Like Kepler he refers to the animae
rationales of the stars obeying “God’s providence” and compares them to
manoeuvring soldiers, obeying the order of the officer. God corresponds in this metaphor to the
officer and the natural laws to his orders. - Patrizzi’s military metaphor
reveals the importance of social changes for the history of ideas. He himself gives ancient Spartans and
Macedonians as examples. A medieval
author, however, could not have thought of the military metaphor, since battles
in the feudal period consisted of a multitude of duels with very little
discipline. Obviously Pafrizzi is
inspired by the new infantry tactics which, in early capitalism, had developed
from the armies of Swiss mercenaries.
80. Disc. (Oeuvres, ed.
Adam-Tannery, VI 41).
81. Ibid. 42f. cf. 451.
I Iff.
82. Ibid. 541.
26f.
Discours Descartes published his Dioptrique. There the laws of reflexion and (for
the first time) of refraction are discussed. In connection with the latter the term
“law” is used too. 83
The Principia Philosophiae
(1644) is the new work announced in the Discours. There Descartes explains in the
second book 84 that the product of mass and velocity remains constant
in nature, since God and his operations are perfect and immutable. “And from this immutability of God”,
Descartes continues, “some rules or laws of nature which are the causes... of
the various motions, can be understood.”
85 He gives three laws, the first and second expressing the
law of inertia, the third stating that in every impact “one body gives as much
of its movement to the other as it loses”.
They are alternately and repeatedly called laws and rules. The immutability of God and his
operations and the creation of the world are mentioned several times.
80
In order to make quantitative calculation of movement
possible Descartes adds seven “rules” of impact which, however, are partly
incorrect. 87
He closes the section with the remark
that in his opinion no other “principles of physics” are necessary in the
explanation of all phenomena in nature.
88 Being a mechanist, he believes he has
exhausted not only all mechanical but all physical laws by his
enumeration.
Descartes discusses natural laws in
a few more places. In the third
book of the Principia he states that it is a “law of nature” that all
bodies moving in circles try to recede from the centre.
89 He immediately explains that he does not
intend to ascribe minds to moving bodies by this statement and thus shows how
carefully he avoids the vitalistic concepts of the middle ages.
90
A quantitative determination of the
centrifugal force, however, is not yet given. Near the end of the work he states,
summarizing, that it has discussed “what must follow from the mutual impact of
the bodies according to mechanical laws, confirmed by certain and everyday
experiments”. 91 His laws or rules of impact are
discussed
82. Oeuvres VI, 100 1. 27f.
The law of refraction was
discovered by Snell in 1621 and first published by
Descartes.
84. Princ. II §36. Oeuvres
VIII 61.
85. Ibid. II §37 (p. 62).
In the Discours also
Descartes had stated that his laws of nature are derived from no other principle
but God’s perfection (VI 43 1. 5).
86 Ibid. II
§§37-42.
87 II §§45-52.
88. II §64.
89. III §55.
90. III §56.
91. IV §200.
268
frequently in his correspondence,
among others in a letter to Christian Huyghens.
92
Descartes was a consistent
mechanist. Convinced that in the
last analysis all physical phenomena consist in movement and impact, he strictly
denied any teleological, anthropocentric, or animistic explanation of nature.
The soullike substantial forms of
the Scholastics were discarded by him. On the other hand he was a devout
Catholic. Adapting the traditional
ideas of God and soul to the new mechanistic science, and stressing the idea of
indestructibility, he created a new concept of substance, able to cover both
matter and mind. To substantial
souls he clung as firmly as he eliminated all soullike components from the
physical world. Thus he introduced
into human thinking a dualism of matter and mind, of outer and inner world,
which in similar rigor had nowhere and never before existed. There is hardly any other philosopher as
characteristic of the modern era and Western culture as is Descartes.
93 When we compare with other cultures and omit details,
all modern Western philosophers appear more or less as Cartesians, since all of
them deal with the mind-body-problem and the problem of the external world.
At the end of the nineteenth
century only, since the breakdown of mechanistic physics (and with the fading of
religious orthodoxy), the influence of Cartesian metaphysics is beginning to
decline.
The Cartesian concept of the world
combined the basic ideas of the Bible and the new physics. By the same combination of ideas he
became the most important pioneer of the concept of natural law which influenced
the thinking of the modern era as strongly as his dualism. Like Galileo, he took over the basic idea
of physical regularities and quantitative rules of operation from the superior
artisans of his period. And from
the Bible he took the idea of God’s legislation. By combining both he created the modern
concept of natural law. 94
Galileo understood the scientific importance of
the
92. “Laws” and “rules” alternately;
No. 114 to Huyghens (II, 50); No. 371 to Clerselier (IV, 183ff.); No. 179 to
Mersenne (IV, 396); No. 514 Burman (VI, 168); No. 566 to Morus (VI,
405).
93. Cf. Edgar Zilsel,
Problems of Empiricism, Encyclopedia of Unified Science, II/18, Chicago
1941, §3.
94. The relations of Descartes to
contemporary technology recede to the background in his writings. Yet in his Discours he stresses
the utility of his principles and refers to the “various crafts of our artisans”
(Oeuvres [VI 62). The Cartesian dualism presupposes
the New Testament (concept of soul), his law-concept the old (God, the
lawgiver).]
HHC: [bracketed] displayed
on p.270 of original.
269
interdependence of physical
quantities at least as clearly as Descartes and made use of more and of more
complicated mathematical functions. But the law-metaphor was unknown to him.
Kepler did speak of laws, but his
law-concept was too animistic to influence rising physics greatly. Descartes only combined the law-metaphor
with a mechanistic concept of natural law. His influence both on philosophy and on
physics can be [HHC added: seen] in Spinoza, in the physicists of the Royal
Society, and in Newton.
10. The Universal Laws of
Nature
10. Spinoza gives a chapter on
divine law in his Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (1670). In this he distinguishes the laws
“depending on necessity of nature” from the laws resulting from human decrees.
As an instance of the former he
gives the principle of the conservation of the quantity of motion following
Descartes. He amplifies, however,
the extent of the Cartesian law-concept from physics to psychology by adding the
law of association by contiguity (as it is called today). Moreover he stresses universal
determination: “everything is determined”, he says, “by the universal laws of
nature.” 95
This idea is emphatically repeated in the chapter on
miracles. The immutable and
universal laws of nature are mentioned again and again and are expressly
identified with the “decrees of God”. Miracles which apparently contradict them
are denied and explained by human ignorance.
96
The opposition of “natural law” and miracle, repeated in
the following period over and over again, apparently occurs here for the first
time. In the
Theologico-Political Treatise Spinoza is still trying to hide his
pantheism. He speaks, therefore, of
the decrees of God in a rather ambiguous way. Since he did not believe in God’s
personality, however, he noticed, in contrast to Descartes, that application of
the term “law” to physical things is based “on a metaphor
(per
translationem)”. 97 Possibly this insight was also
influenced by Suarez, who was known to Spinoza.
95. Tract. Theol.-Pol. cap. 4.
Opera (ed. Vloten-Land in 4 vols., The Hague 1914) II
134.
96 Cap. 6 (ibid. 156-170
passim).
97. Cap. 4 p. 135. - In his first
work (1663), the Renati Des Cartes Principia Philosophiae, he gives the
Cartesian seven “rules” of motion (II, prop. 24-31). In the annexed Cogitata Metaphysica
he often speaks of the “decrees” of God (I, cap. 3).
270
The determinist explanation of
mental phenomena is carried out in Spinoza’s Ethics. The famous preface to the third part
begins with the statement that human affects too “follow the common laws of
nature”. Alluding to the origin of
the term “law”, Spinoza explains that man in nature does not form a state within
the state and expressly denies Descartes’ doctrine of free will. Actually “the laws and rules of nature,
according to which everything happens and is transformed, are the same
everywhere and always”. Therefore
he will deal with human behavior in a strictly causal way without any valuation
- a modern author would have said, in the manner of the natural sciences. Since Spinoza, however, considered the
deductive method of Euclid the most scientific, he says he will treat human
actions as if the question were of lines, planes, and bodies. In the following this program is carried
out more geometrico. Yet
Spinoza is, of course, not able to give quantitative laws of psychology. The laws of nature are occasionally
mentioned in later sections also of the Ethics and in his correspondence.
98 One passage is interesting, since it occurs in a letter
to Oldenburg, the secretary of the Royal Society, and since it expressly states
that all physical processes follow “the laws of mechanics”. Like Descartes and virtually all
physicists of the period he is a consistent mechanist.
On the whole Spinoza has taken over
the theistic concept of natural law from Descartes and has reinterpreted it in a
pantheistic way. At the same time
he has extended it to the province of mental phenomena. His ethical ideals being entirely Stoic,
he is a determinist. Yet his
determinism is neither magic nor theological but mechanistic, as it is in Hobbes
and as it became in the natural sciences of the following period. Spinoza is the first author combining
general metaphysical determinism with the modern concept of natural
law.
In 1638, six years before
publication of his Principia, Descartes had written to the young
Christian Huyghens on his laws of impact.
99 With these “laws” or “rules” Huyghens occupied himself
in various manuscripts for many years, since he noticed the
incur-
98. Ethics 4, app., cap. 6f. -
Letter no. 13 (to Oldenburg, leges mechanicae). Cf. letters no. 31, 33,
42.
99. Cf. above footnote 92.
Huyghens was then 19 years old.
rectness of Descartes’ statements.
He discovered the conservation of
kinetic energy in elastic impacts and published his results in a letter to the
Journal des Scavans, Sur les régles du mouvement dans la rencontre des corps
(1669). After his death a
treatise of his on the same subject De Motu corporum ex percussione
appeared in his Opuscula Postuma (1703). In all these papers the laws of impact
are alternately called “rules” and “laws”.100
A Latin translation of his letter to the
Journal des Scavans was published also in the Philosophical
Transactions (1669), the new journal of the newly founded Royal Society.
In the brief English introduction
Oldenburg, the secretary of the Society, speaks alternately of the “laws” and of
the “rules” of motion. 101
On the same problem two Latin papers
of Wallis and Christopher Wren had appeared one year before (1668) in the
Philosophical Transactions. The whole discussion was started by
the Royal Society. Wallis’ paper
has the title A summary account given by Dr. John Wallis of the General Laws
of Motion. Wren’s article is
called Lex naturae de Collisione Corporum.
102
As these papers show, the term “law” first became
customary among physicists with the laws of impact. In this the influence of Descartes is
obvious, though the papers of Huyghens, Wallis, and Wren, no longer contain
theological remarks. Possibly the
terminology of the Tranactions was influenced also by Spinoza, the
friend of Oldenburg.. The first
volumes of the Transactions occasionally speak of natural laws in other
contexts too. They report on a
paper of a French Gentleman, Mr. Auzout, who believed he had found laws of
cometary movement. 103 And they mention “odd laws” of variation of the
barometer and the “laws of refraction” in optics.
104
The last two passages refer to two
new physical instruments
100. Huyghens, Oeuvres Complètes
(ed. Soc. Holl. d. Sc.) XVI 95 (ms. of 1652), 104 (ms. of 1654), 139 (ms. of
1656), 181 (letter to the Journ.d. Sc.), pp. 33, 91 (de motu corp.). - In his
Horologium Oscillatorium (Ibid. XVIII 69ff.) and his De vi centrifuga
(ibid. 366ff.) the term “law” is not used, though important physical laws
are stated for the first time.
101 Phil. Trans. IV (1669),
925. - The Royal Society was founded in 1663; the Trans. appeared first
in 1665.
102. Ibid. III (1668)
864ff.
103. Phil. Trans. I 4. Auzout
speaks of “laws” also in his French pamphlet on the comet of 1664/65, printed in
1665 in Paris (pp. i and 7). - He believes that the comet in question moves in a
circle. He is proud of having found
this hypothesis upon three observations only (Phil. Trans. I
19).
104 Phil. Trans. I
31f.
272
of the eminent microscopist and
experimentalist Robert Hooke and are almost literally taken from the preface to
his Micrographia (1665). Hooke was Curator of the Society and had
to prepare the experiments for their meetings. He discovered the so-called law of Hooke,
stating that the stress of an elastic body is proportional to its strain. In his Lectures de Potentia
Restitutiva (1678) he calls it a “Rule or Law of Nature”.
105 This is the first time that a physical law, referred to
in modern textbooks under the name of its discoverer, is called a law by the
discoverer himself. As early as in
1662 Hooke used the term “law” occasionally also in his notes on his experiments
on Boyle’s law. 106
Sir Robert Boyle was among the
eminent members of the Royal Society. He published his law (the volume of a gas
is inversely proportional to its pressure) in his Defense of the doctrine
touching the Spring and Weight of the Air (166o) without using the term
“law”. It is always called a
hypothesis by him. 107 On the other hand he frequently speaks of natural laws
in his theological writings. In his
Free inquiry into the vulgarly received Notion of Nature (composed in
1666) he declares the term “law”, when applied to inanimate things, “an improper
and figurative expression”, explaining this at great length.
108 In the explanation he strangely assumes that the
law-metaphor ascribes teleological tendencies to physical objects. When an arrow, shot by a man, he says,
moves towards the mark, “none will say that it moves by a law but by an
external... impulse”. 109
Nevertheless he himself speaks in what
follows very often of the “laws of motion prescribed by the author of things”.
110 He
confesses to belong to the “modern naturalists and divines”, explaining the
phenomena through “physico-mechanical principles and laws”. Animistic interpretations of nature,
therefore, are combatted by him, but he immediately adds that “sometimes” there
are miracles. 111
The paper contains numerous biblical quotations and a
long polemic against Descartes.
112 It is significant that twenty-one years before the
pub-
105. Reprinted in R. T. Gunther,
Early Science in Oxford, Oxford 1938, VIII 334 and
336.
106. Ibid. VI
83.
107. Works (ed. Birch) I 158,
162.
108. Ibid. V
170ff.
109. P. 171.
110. P. 177, cf. pp. 194,
225, 251, 252.
111. P. 215.
112. P.
242.
lication of Newton’s Principia
the memory of the metaphysical character and theological origin of the
concept of natural law is completely alive in a treatise of a physicist of the
Royal Society.
Newton’s Philosophiae Naturalis
Principia Mathematica (1687) has definitely made the term “law” a familiar
component of the scientific vocabulary. Particularly his famous three “laws of
motion”, given at the beginning of the work, 113
were taken over by all physicists of
the following period. The reference
to Wren, Wallis, and Huyghens, and their laws of impact, in this section
114 reveals the
origin of the terminology. The term
“law” is applied by Newton also to his gravitation-formula. The “laws and measures of gravitation”
appear as early as in the preface. And at the end of the Principia,
just after the famous refusal to invent hypotheses about the cause of
gravitation, Newton states: “it is sufficient that actually gravitation exists
and acts according to the laws given by us.
115 In several problems the mathematical and
formal side is conspicuous in his concept of law. He looks for “the law of the centripetal
force”, given the orbit of a moving body. In one special case the solution is: the
force is proportional to the distance from the center. On the other hand a different “law” (the
law of gravitation) results, if other orbits are given.
116 Here “law” is obviously almost synonymous with
“proportionality” without any tinge of metaphysics.
Still theological components have
not vanished in Newton’s physics. Though he never mentions the divine
origin of the natural laws, he declares that only creation of the world by an
intelligent Entity can explain the remarkable coincidence of the directions and
planes of the planetary movements. The planets stay in their orbits “by the
laws of gravitation, but they could not, initially, receive the regular position
of the orbits by these laws”. 117
There
113. Opera (ed. Harsley) II.
13ff. They state, as is generally
known, the principle of inertia, the proportionality of force and change of
momentum, and the equality of action and reaction. The section is named “Axioms or Laws
of Motion”.
114. P. 23. As in Descartes, Wren, Wallis, and
Huyghens, the laws of impact are alternately called “laws” and
“rules”.
115. Opera III, 174. His third letter to Bentley says:
“Gravity must be caused by an agent acting constantly according to certain laws”
(IV 438).
116. I sect. 2 prop. 10,
probl. 5. Cf. I sect. 3, prop. ii, probl. 6, and prop.
12f.
117. Lib. 3, scholium generale
(III 171).
274
follows a long exposition,
explaining with classical and biblical citations and a footnote on the etymology
of the word “God”, that everything is in God. Altogether in the Principia
theology has retreated from the laws to (as the modern physicist would put
it) the initial conditions. However, Newton would have certainly
admitted, if he had been asked, that the laws too were established by God. Of course Newton knew also
Descartes. It cannot be explained,
as he states, by Cartesian vortices “that the movement of the comets follows the
same laws as the planets”. 118
Newton realized the novelty and
scientific importance of the concept of physical law. He starts his work in the preface with
the statement: “the modern scientists, omitting the substantial forms and the
occult qualities, have undertaken to explain the phenomena of nature by
mathematical laws.” The essential
point of the modern scientific method is explained here with surpassing clarity.
And he concludes his work
regretting the imperfect state of knowledge in the fields of cohesion, nerve
activity, and electricity. It is
not yet known, he writes, “by which laws” these phenomena must be explained.
Thus the first and the last
sentence of the Principia deal with natural laws. Still the term “law” occurs more rarely
than in a modern textbook on physics. It does not occur at all in his
Lectiones Opticae and his Op ticks, not even in the sections on
reflexion and refraction. 119
We need not trace the origins of our
concept further. Whoever knows the
immense influence exerted by Newton’s Principia on the science and even
the whole literature of the following period, will not be surprised at the rapid
spread of the idea of natural law in eighteenth-century physics, philosophy, and
deistic theology. The concept was
simply taken over in the shape in which it appears in Newton. As a consequence, the physical meaning of
the term “natural law” gradually displaced the juridical. Voltaire, who contributed most to the
popularization of Newton’s ideas on the continent, is already entirely familiar
with the idea that nature is governed by laws, successfully investigated by
scientists. 120 No
118 Ibid
170.
119. Opera III,
IV.
120. Elements de la philosophic de
Newton (1738) 3, I: (Oeuvres, Firmin Didot, V, 721), les lois
de l’attraction; 3, 5 (p. 726) : lois de la chute de corps
trouvées par Galilee; 3, 5 (p. 730) : lois de la gravitation, règles de
[Kepler.
Essai sur la nature du feu 2, 3, (ibid. p. 776): eight “laws”. His Dictionnaire Philosophique
(1764), however, gives the juridical meaning only s.v. “loi naturelle” (VIII
21ff.).]
HHC: [bracketed] displayed
on p.276 of original.
275
doubt Newton’s Principia
(1687) is the turning point in the rise of this idea. Whereas Locke’s Essay concerning Human
Understanding (1690) does not yet know the concept of natural law in its
physical meaning, it already is a matter of course in Berkeley’s Treatise
concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710). In 1655 Hobbes’ De Corpore
does not speak of laws. In 1642
his De Cive and in 1645 his Leviathan discuss natural law in its
juridical meaning only. 121
In 1748, on the other hand, Montesquieu’s
L’esprit des lois dedicates the first chapter to physical
laws.
11. Finally, we must try to give an
explanation of the development described. Why has it taken place in the way and at
the time given? We cannot explain
here why at the time of Galileo the idea of mechanical regularities arose. This explanation exceeds our present
task, since it is linked with the much more general problem of the origin of
experimental science and the quantitative spirit, and will be attempted at
another place. Here it may be
indicated only that in all civilizations experimentation originates in
handicraft. In the period of
nascent capitalism experimenting artisans began to look for quantitative rules
of operation. The roots of these
mechanical rules, therefore, must be searched for in the sociological and
technological conditions of handicraft in the early modern era. They rose to science in Galileo.
121a
However, why were these mechanical
regularities eventually interpreted as divine laws of nature? This is not a mere question of
terminology. Without the
metaphysical components, contained in the law-metaphor, they could hardly have
obtained their scientific and philosophical impetus. Reference to the strength of religious
tradition does not give a sufficient answer to our question. The idea of laws, given by God to nature,
does not occur in all religions. It
is lacking in ancient Egypt, 122
and special investigations would be
required to decide whether similar ideas were known
121. Locke, Essay I, 3 §13,
mentions the juridical meaning only. Berkeley, Principles §30. Hobbes, De Cive cap. 2-4,
Leviathan I, chap. 14f., II chap. 26.
121a. 5 Cf. Edgar Zilsel, “The
Sociological Roots of Science,” The American Journal of Sociology XLVII
(1942) 545 if.
122. Cf. §2 footnote
4.
276
in Persia and India. In Babylonia with its Hammurabi code and
in the Old Testament with its abundance of ritual and other law it has
developed, but everyone who knows how in Christianity different ideas were
emphasized or receded to the background in different periods, will not doubt
that the divine commands to nature in the Book of Job could have easily
stayed uninfluential in the history of ideas. In fact God’s “eternal law”, as we have
met with it in Thomas Aquinas, was not a leading idea of medieval Catholicism.
The idea of divine providence
certainly was important, as far as human fates were concerned, since it gives
consolation and hope. As far,
however, as it implies eternal laws of nature, it was confined to being
mentioned by learned theologians. The Middle Ages perceived the reign of
God much more in miracles than in the ordinary course of nature. Comets and monsters were of greater
moment to medieval piety than the daily sunrise and normal offspring. How was it that in the modern period the
idea of God’s reign over the world shifted from the exceptions in nature to the
rules?
The expressions “reign over the
world” and “law of nature” spring from a comparison of nature and state. Is it not almost a matter of course that
the concept of the divine reign changed with changes in the structure of the
state? In the feudal state of the
middle ages government and law differed entirely from the corresponding
institutions of the modern era. Thomas Aquinas lived in a period when
Italian feudalism was already disintegrating under the influence of the rising
money economy. Yet he mentions
traits of human law, in his discussion of eternal and natural law, which would
hardly fit the physical laws of modern science. There are, he says, “special laws” for
the various estates of society; to priests it is “law” to pray, to princes to
govern, to soldiers to fight. 123
This would still agree with physical laws: the laws of
mechanics differ from the laws of electricity. But Thomas thinks the individual can
occasionally change his estate and “law” by order of his lord; e.g., a
“soldier” (a nobleman) can be turned out of the “army” (of nobility) and can
become subject to rural or mercantile law.
124
123. Summa Theologica, II, 1
qu. 95, art, 4, resp. 2.
124. Ibid, qu., 91, art, 6, resp.
To this there is no analogy in
modern physics. The “laws” Thomas
is here speaking of are, obviously, the bonds of feudalism, varying according to
the estate of the individual. They
are not based on statute law but on sacred tradition and do not derive from
rational regulations of a legislator. Which paragraph of which code orders the
prince to rule and the priests to pray?
The feudal state was an extremely
loose organization. The bonds by
which it was tied together were irrational and considered a matter of course.
If the prince issued regulations
they were most frequently privileges given to single noblemen, monasteries, and
towns, corresponding rather to exceptions than to rules. The medieval interpretation of nature
seems to correspond to this organization of the state: the Lord does miracles,
they are noteworthy; the regular course of nature, on the other hand, is sacred
but a matter of course. At any rate
the idea of a comprehensive multitude of rational physical “laws” could not have
arisen in feudalism, even if the corresponding physical facts had been
known.
It is generally admitted that the
Stoic doctrine of the one Logos ruling the universe is correlated with
the rise of monarchies after Alexander the Great. The analogy might hold for the modern
concept of natural law. It will be
remembered that Patrizzi had explained the orderly course of the stars by
comparing them to soldiers obeying the command of their officers:
125
the loose
knightly armies of feudalism had been displaced by the mercenary armies of early
capitalism with their rational discipline. The application of the law-metaphor to
physical phenomena has probably been produced by the analogous change of the
entire state. Money economy
disrupted the bonds of feudalism and traditionalism, made rational regulations
and statute law necessary, and increased immensely the power of the prince.
Even in England, where Roman law
was not introduced, this process took place under the Tudors; it reached its
peak, however, in seventeenth-century absolutism on the continent. It is not a mere chance that the
Cartesian idea of God, the legislator of the universe, developed forty years
after Bodin’s theory of sovereignty. Perhaps it is not even a
coincidence
125. Cf. §9 above, footnote
79.
278
that both thinkers were French:
France was the native country of centralized absolutism. At any rate the doctrine of universal
natural laws of divine origin is possible only in a state with rational statute
law and fully developed central sovereignty. Possibly the change in the structure of
the state also gives the explanation why the metaphorical character of the term
“law”, when applied to unreasonable beings, was not noticed before Suarez.
126 Under feudalism even animals and things could be
summoned and punished. Thomas
hardly thought of legal actions against animals, when discussing God’s eternal
law; but only rational statute law is, with necessity, restricted to rational
beings. Man is a social being.
He seems to be inclined to
interpret nature not only according to the needs but also after the pattern of
society. Yet one difficulty in our
sociological explanation must be mentioned. How could medieval theologians speak of
the legislature of God, when the power of the prince was very limited? The idea, however, had not originated in
feudalism. It had been conceived
under entirely different sociological conditions. Its authors were Jews who had outgrown
their past of Bedouin clan-organization centuries ago, and its sociological
pattern was the despotism of ancient oriental states. The idea could be preserved in a
rudimentary form through two thousand years, even through a period in which it
did not fit the sociological conditions, till it awoke to new life in early
capitalistic absolutism. This fact,
and there are numerous analogies, is very important for the theory of history.
Ideologies are extremely
conservative. They never can be
explained by present conditions alone, but mirror the whole past too. At any rate historical problems are very
complex. Even if this sociological
explanation should be falsified by future investigations, the material here
collected on the genesis of the concept of physical law
remains.
EDGAR ZIL5EL
THE INSTITUTE OF SOCIAL RESEARCH,
NEW YORK, N.Y.
136. After Suarez (1612) this insight
was to be found in Spinoza (1670)and Boyle (1666). In Thomas (about 1270) it
is still lacking.
279