The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Edgar Zilsel
Problems of Empiricism *
Content |
|
I. The Rise of Experimental Science
1.
Experiment and Manual Labor
2. Causal Research: The Mechanical Conception of Nature
II. The Philosophy of Modern Classical Empiricism
3. The Opposition of Outer and Inner World
III. The Advance of Empirical Science
IV. The Decline of the Mechanical Conception of Nature |
[1941] in Social Origins of Modern Science Edgar Zilsel, Diederick Raven, Wolfgang Krohn, R. S. Cohen
Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000, 171-199. |
I. The Rise of Experimental
Science
1.
Experiment and Manual Labor
Modern science is accustomed to decide all
questions about reality by experience and experiment.
This remarkable attitude is not at all
self-evident. It is rather a late
achievement in the history of mankind, and its import cannot be fully
understood as long as that fact is not realized.
We shall start our exposition,
therefore, with a retrospective view of the rise of empirical thinking and the
experimental method. Though at the
beginning of the modem era empirical research proceeded from certain empirical
achievements of antiquity, classical empiricism can be omitted in this brief
survey. In antiquity the empirical
sciences were considerably surpassed in intellectual influence by metaphysics
and rhetoric, and empiricists always were but a small minority among ancient
philosophers and scientists. It will
be sufficient, therefore, to begin with the Middle Ages.
The seats of medieval civilization were not
towns, which in the early centuries were rare, but monasteries and castles in
the country. The castles and the
cultural accomplishments of the knights have little bearing on theoretical
thinking. The monasteries, being the
centers of medieval scholarship, are more important for the present study.
Monks, by the conditions of their
lives, are not much disposed to look at the world with open eyes.
Inclosed within walls, intrusted with
the task of transmitting established doctrines to successors by scholastic
instruction, they were compelled to indulge in abstract reasoning and to
develop their sagacity. This attitude
of mind was later taken over by the universites of the late medieval cities.
Up to the thirteenth century the
method of investigating that appears to be the most natural one to modem
science was practically unknown. When
medieval theorists, or theologians, intended to solve a problem, they looked
first for relevant passages in the Holy Scripture, the patristic writings, and
certain works of Aristotle. Then they
compared affirmative and negative statements of colleagues and predecessors
and, finally, drew conclusions by means of logical deduction from the premises
collected. It
* [Zilsel, as in his essay ‘The Methods of
Humanism’, makes use of ‘supporting evidence paragraphs’ which are given in
smaller print. The original endnotes
have been replaced with footnotes; Eds.]
171
cannot be a surprise, therefore, that the
scholastic theory of syllogism is the chief contribution of medieval science.
By the end of the Middle Ages, however, a few
scholars, among them Roger Bacon in England and Albertus Magnus in Germany,
had begun to understand the importance of experience. [1]
Their contemporary, the French
nobleman Petrus de Maricourt, even experimented successfully upon magnets.
This rise of new scientific methods in
the thirteenth century is connected with a fundamental change in society.
Towns had gradually grown up, the
rural monasteries and castles were losing their social importance, and a new
social class - the townsmen - entered upon the stage of history.
Money and profit began to rule the
lives of nations.
The period of transition from feudalism to early
capitalism lasted until the fifteenth century.
At its beginning, the craftsmen of the towns, to prevent economic
competition, organized themselves in guilds which took care lest the working
traditions of the past be broken. But
when, with the strengthening of capitalism, competition proved stronger and
destroyed the guilds, guild constraints upon working began to crumble.
The craftsman who worked exactly as
his master and his master’s master had done, was surpassed by less
conservative competitors; one’s own spirit of enterprise, one’s own experience
and inventive genius, made the successful man.
The age of inventions had begun. Some
great inventions of this period - the manufacturing of paper, gunpowder, and
guns, the mariner’s compass, the printing press - are generally known.
The invention of the blast furnace and
the stamping-mill, the introduction of ventilators and hauling-engines in
mining, numerous improvements in construction of weaving looms, ships, canals,
and fortresses are scarcely less important. With
the inventions of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries the technology of the
Middle Ages was completely revolutionized. Similar
effects were produced by the great geographical discoveries.
On new shores animals, plants, and
things never seen before were found, which even the most acute monk would not
have been able to deduce from his authorities.
Authorities and syllogisms had been beaten by experience; a new,
empirically minded type of man went out to conquer the world.
In virtue of their occupations these men were
craftsmen and navigators belonging to the lower ranks of society.
They were not esteemed too highly
either by the noblemen or by the bankers and rich merchants of plebeian
origin. Since the literati, the
humanists, who wrote for upper-class publicity were not interested in such
plebeian people as craftsmen, the biographies and even the names of most of
the inventors are seldom known. There
are few detailed and reliable literary reports even on the great discoverers.
[2] The craftsmen and
sailors themselves were not literary men but rather uneducated people. Their
[1] The empirical achievements of Bacon and
Albertus are often overestimated (cf. L. Thorndike, A History of Magic and
Experimental Science [New York, 1923], Vol. II).
[2] On the contemporary writings on inventors and
discoverers cf. E. Zilsel, Die Entstehung des Geniebegriffes (Tubingen,
1926), pp. 130-143.
172
empiricism, very far from being science, was a
matter of practical life and casual observation and, for the most part, was
lacking in systematic method.
But gradually, especially in Italy, a more systematic technique of empirical research developed among certain groups of superior craftsmen whose professions required more knowledge than did their colleagues’. We are speaking of the artists, the makers of nautical and of musical instruments, and the surgeons. In the Middle Ages the painters, sculptors, and architects had not been distinguished from the whitewashers, stonedressers, and masons. With the decay of their guilds they slowly separated from handicraft and eventually, about the middle of the sixteenth century, became free artists. During the course of this evolution a remarkable group developed within their ranks. We may call them artist-engineers, for they did not only paint pictures and build cathedrals but also constructed lifting-engines, earthworks, canals and sluices, guns and fortresses, discovered new pigments, detected the geometrical laws of perspective, and invented new measuring-tools for engineering and gunnery. Many of them composed diaries and treatises on their experiences and inventions for the use of their colleagues. As they belonged neither to the Latin-speaking university-scholars nor to the humanistic literati, but were artisans, they wrote their papers in the vernacular. All of them were already accustomed to making experiments. They were the true forerunners of modem experimental science. [3]
Brunelleschi (1377-1446), the constructor of the
cupola of the cathedral of Florence, was the first of these artist-engineers.
Among his successors are the bronze
founder Ghiberti (d. 1455), the architect and painter Lione Battista
Alberti (1407-1472), who - as an exception - had had a classical education,
the architect and military engineer Giorgio Martini (1425-1506),
Leonardo da Vinci (1452-1519), and, finally, the goldsmith, sculptor,
and gun constructor Cellini (1500-1571). The
architect and gunnery expert Biringucci (d. 1538) may be mentioned
because of his book on metallurgy, Della pirotechnia.
His paper is the first treatise on
chemistry based on sound experience and avoiding any alchemistic superstition.
The inventors and constructors of the
new clavicembali and harpsichords, and the compass-makers also belonged to the
experimenting superior craftsmen. A
third group was formed by the surgeons. They
dissected animals and often human bodies, whereas the learned physicians
seldom dared to do such untidy and sinister work.
By their common interest in anatomy
there were often connections between artists and surgeons.
Experiment requires manual work, and, therefore,
in both antiquity and the modem era its use began in handicraft.
In antiquity scientific
experimentalists were extremely rare. Since
rough work was generally done by slaves, contempt of manual labor formed an
obstacle that only the boldest of ancient scholars dared to overcome.
A similar obstacle, though by scarcity
of slaves less unsurmountable, obstructed the rise of experimental science in
the modem era.
[3] On the artist-engineers and their papers cf.
Leonardo Olschki, Geschichte der neusprachlichenwissenschafllichen
Literatur, I (Heidelberg, 1918), 45-447, and Zilsel, op. cit.,
pp. 144-157.
173
The educational system under early capitalism
took over from the Middle Ages the distinction between liberal and mechanical
arts. In the seven liberal arts
(grammar, dialectic, rhetoric, arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and music)
thinking and disputing were alone required; on them alone was the education of
well-bred men based. All other arts,
as requiring manual work, were considered to be more or less plebeian.
There are numerous instances to indicate that up to the sixteenth
century even the greatest artists of the Renaissance had to fight against
social prejudice. And by the same
reason the two components of modern scientific method were kept apart:
methodical training of intellect was reserved for university-scholars and
humanistic writers who belonged, or at least addressed themselves, to the
upper class; experiment, and to a certain extent observation, was left to
lower-class manual workers. Even the
great Leonardo, therefore, was not a true scientist.
As he had never learned how to inquire
systematically, his results form but a collection of isolated, though
sometimes splendid, discoveries. In
his diaries he several times discusses problems erroneously which he had
solved correctly years before. Gradually,
however, the technological revolution transformed society and thinking to such
a degree that the social barrier between liberal and mechanical arts began to
crumble, and the experimental techniques of the craftsmen were admitted to the
ranks of the university-scholars. Rational
training and manual work were united at last: experimental science was born.
This was accomplished about 1600 with
Galileo Galilei, Francis Bacon, and William Gilbert.
One of the greatest events in the
history of mankind had taken place.
The scientific work of Copernicus (d. 1543),
being rational not experimental, may be omitted here.
Galileo (1564- 1642) [4] got his education at
the University of Pisa and for more than twenty years he was professor at the
universities of Pisa and Padua. His relations to handicraft and technology,
however, are often underrated. During
his student days there was no mathematical instruction at Pisa. [5]
He learned
mathematics privately, his tutor, Ostilio Ricci, being an architect and
teacher at the Accademia del disegno which had been founded in 1562 by the
painter Vasari as something between a modern academy of arts and a technical
college. [6]
Thus Galileo’s first
mathematical education was directed by persons who were artist-engineers.
As a young professor in Padua he
lectured at the university in mathematics and astronomy and gave private
instruction on engineering in his home. For
his experimental studies he established working-rooms in his house and hired
craftsmen as assistants. [7]
This was the first
university laboratory in history. His
scientific research started with studies on pumps, the regulation of rivers,
and the construction of fortresses. Ever
since his student days he had liked to visit dockyards and arsenals.
His first printed publication (1606)
described a new measuring-tool for military
[4] On Galileo cf. Olschki, op. cit., III
(Halle, 1927), pp. 117-467.
[5] Galileo, Opere (ed. nazionale), XIX,
32 fT.
[6] Before the foundation of the Academia del
disegno, young artists had always received their education at the workshop,
like all apprentices. The new school
clearly shows how engineering gradually penetrated the province of academic
instruction.
[7] Galileo, op. cit., XIX, 130 ff.
174
purposes. Even in his last work
of 1638, which initiated modern mechanics, the setting of the dialogue is the
arsenal of Venice. His greatest
achievement, the discovery of the law of falling bodies, also originated in
connection with the contemporary technology. Among
the gunnery experts of the period there were many discussions on the shape of
the trajectory. Galileo realized that
the question could not be answered before the problem of falling bodies was
solved. Free falling, however, was too
fast to be measured exactly. In
order to slow down the movement, Galileo took brass balls, made them roll down
an inclined groove, and measured the spaces, times, and velocities.
He succeeded in correlating his
results by means of a mathematical formula and finally determined the shape of
the curve of projection. In Galileo’s
classical inquiry the two pillars on which modern science is based stand out:
experiment and mathematical analysis. The
experiments of the craftsmen, alone, would never have issued in science.
Francis Bacon (1561-1626) did not make any
important discovery in the natural sciences. His
writings abound with magical survivals and errors; he did not understand well
the achievements of Copernicus, Galileo, Gilbert, and Harvey; the
methodological prescriptions he gave in order to promote empirical research
were too pedantic to be of great use to scientists.
But he was the very first writer who
fully realized the importance of science for human civilization.
The scholastics and humanists, he
explained, have only repeated sayings of the past.
Only in the mechanical arts has
knowledge been furthered since antiquity. Bacon,
therefore, spoke of craftsmen and mariners with enthusiasm and proclaimed
their works as models for the scholars. He
is an enthusiastic advocate both of scientific induction and of the ideal of
progress. Both ideas are closely
connected: they are nothing else than the working method of early capitalist
handicraft seen with the eyes of a philosopher.
His whole philosophy is one great
attack against the ideals of the seven liberal arts.
Bacon himself performed numerous
experiments: he died from a cold which he caught while stuffing a dead chicken
with snow. Most of his learned
contemporaries probably considered that experiment more fitting for a cook or
flayer than for a former lord chancellor of England.
The first learned book of the modem era on
experimental physics had appeared before Galileo’s and Bacon’s publications.
It was William Gilbert’s De magnete
(1600). Gilbert was physician to
Queen Elizabeth I. His experimental
method originated partly in contemporary metallurgy and mining, partly in the
experiments of the retired mariner and compass-maker, Robert Norman. [8]
Why is experiment so essential to empirical
science? Mere observation is a passive
affair. It means but “wait and see”
and often depends on chance. Experiment,
on the other hand, is an active method of investigation.
The experimenter does not wait until
events begin, as it were, to speak for themselves; he systematically asks
questions. Moreover, he uses
artificial means of producing conditions such that clear answers are likely to
be obtained. Such preparations are
indispensable in most cases. Natural
events are usually compounds of numerous effects produced by different causes,
and these can hardly be separately investigated until most of them are
eliminated by artificial means. There
is, therefore, in all empirical sciences a distinct trend toward
experimentation. Sciences in which
experiment is not feasible are handicapped. They
try to solve their problems by referring to other sciences in which
[8]. Cf. “The Origins of William Gilbert’s
Scientific Method” [this volume pp. 71-95, Eds.].
175
experiments can be performed.
Thus meteorology, geology, seismology,
and astrophysics make use of laboratory physics and laboratory chemistry.
Sociologists and economists attempt to
utilize results of psychology. A few
modern geologists have even attempted to imitate formation of mountains on a
diminished scale in laboratories. To a
large extent the poor results of the social sciences might be explained by
lack of experiments. The only
substitute which, under favourable conditions, can to a certain degree
compensate for the lack of laboratory experiments is the use of a great number
of observations when carefully compared and worked up by means of statistical
methods. Until now, however,
experiment has been by far the most efficient empirical method.
It is noteworthy that one of the oldest
empirical sciences, astronomy of the solar system, was highly successful
without any experiment. This is due to
the extraordinary fact that in our solar system superimposed effects belong to
very different orders of magnitude and therefore can be separated
comparatively easily. The solar system
is exceptionally well isolated and the sun surpasses by far all planets in
mass. Were the solar system
continually bombarded by heavy meteorites or, what is the same, were it
passing through a dense star-cluster, and were Jupiter’s mass of the same
order of magnitude as that of the sun, Copernicus, Kepler, and Newton would
not have achieved much.
2. Causal
Research: The Mechanical Conception of Nature
The young experimental science was forced to
fight hard battles with pre-scientific thinking.
Primitive man does not distinguish
exactly between animate and inanimate objects; he apprehends all natural
events as if they were manifestations of striving, loving, and hating beings.
This animistic conception of nature is
predominant in all civilizations without money economy and dominated medieval
thinking too. When a comet appeared in
the sky or a monster was born, medieval man questioned rather the meaning, the
aim, and the purpose of these events than their causes.
The scholars did not think very
differently either. Certainly
“entelechies” and “substantial forms” of Aristotle and the Scholastics are not
primitive ideas; they are complicated and highly rational constructs.
Yet their animistic kernel has, as it
were, only dried up; something like a soul, striving to reach its aims, still
glimmers through the rational hull. The
same holds of the “occult qualities” that were liked so well by the
Scholastics. These could never be
observed but were supposed to adhere to most objects and to produce effects by
sympathy and antipathy, as if they were little ghosts.
Animistic survivals like these were of
no use to modern technology and had to be cleared away.
Teleological explanations were
gradually replaced by causal ones. Purposes
of inanimate things, the meaning of natural events, and soul-like powers of
physical objects cannot be ascertained by observations.
On the other hand, the regular
connection of cause and effect is testable by experience and experiment.
Moreover, engineers are able to
produce the effects they want if they know the cause.
Causal explanation, therefore, became
the chief aim of experimental science.
176
The discarding of teleological explanations may
be illustrated by two well-known instances. The
Scholastics, with Aristotle, explained the falling of bodies by the theory of
natural places. Each body was supposed
to have its correct place to which it moved when it had been brought to a
wrong one. Obviously inanimate bodies
were conceived as though they were cattle striving to the accustomed stable.
As the theory of natural places did
not give any information on the empirical details of falling, it was of no use
to the artillery men of the modern era who wished to level their guns
correctly. It had to be replaced by
Galileo’s law of falling bodies and his calculation of the parabola of
projection.
The working of suction pumps was explained in
the late Middle Ages by the doctrine of horror vacui.
Water was supposed to rise in
pump barrels because nature had an antipathy to empty space.
Since the well-diggers of the new era
could not calculate from this theory how long they might make their pipes, two
pupils of Galileo, Viviani and Toricelli, experimented on pipes filled with
mercury and discovered and measured atmospheric pressure.
The causal mode of investigation gave rise to a
basic, and previously unknown, conception. In
a well-governed state there are laws which are prescribed by the government
and, for the most part, observed by the citizens.
Lawbreaking is rare and is punished
when detected. Let us now suppose the
government to be omnipotent and the police to be omniscient.
In this case laws would always be
observed. The seventeenth century
began to compare nature with such a perfect state, ruled by an almighty and
omniscient king. [9]
Thus the recurrent associations
of natural processes were named natural “laws” by the scientists who
investigated them - especially if they had succeeded in expressing the
regularities by mathematical formulas. The
term “law” became so common that people soon began to forget that it
originated in a metaphor; the idea arose that all events, without
exception, were subject to natural laws. This
deterministic conviction dominated philosophy and science from Descartes,
Hobbes, and Spinoza, and from Galileo, Huyghens, and Newton almost up to the
present time. It impelled all
naturalists to look for more and more natural laws and thus proved to be
extremely fruitful.
Nevertheless, we must distinguish the empirical
and the metaphysical and theological components in these ideas.
The statement that there are regular
connections between certain events or qualities undoubtedly is an empirical
one, for such connections are observable. The
case is different with the assertion that events are connected not only as a
matter of fact but that, moreover, some necessity subsists, forcing one event
to follow the other. Necessity never
is observable; it transcends the province of experience.
Metaphysical and
[9] In fact, the metaphor is not older.
In scholasticism the term “natural law” had an entirely different and
merely juristical and ethical meaning. The
Middle Ages could not produce the modern concept of natural law for the simple
reason that the feudal state was governed not by statute but by unwritten and
loose traditional law. As far as
medieval princes issued regulations at all, they were for the most part
privileges given to single noblemen, monasteries, and towns.
They compare, consequently, rather
with exceptions than with regularities in nature.
Also with the ancient authors the
metaphor of natural law appears but seldom and in a rather vague form.
Antiquity, however, was familiar with
the mythological idea of “fate”.
177
theological additions become the more marked
when necessity is interpreted as the order of a personal deity or of
impersonal nature. But even without
drawing in necessity, difficulties emerge and experience is transcended when
it is asserted that an observed regularity will always hold.
Obviously no statement speaking of
more than a finite number of objects and containing the term “all” can be
completely verified by observation. All
these unempirical components were ascertained and criticized by Hume.
Before Hume no scientist and no
philosopher conceived natural laws merely as empirically ascertained
regularities, and even nowadays the idea of lawful necessity has not entirely
vanished.
The logical difficulty just mentioned is
repeated on a higher level in the thesis of general determinism.
What exactly does it mean to say that
regularities hold “everywhere” or, which is the same thing, that there is “no”
fact that is not subject to some regularity? In
mathematics, if any finite number of cases is given, an equation covering the
given cases can always be found. Does
general determinism maintain only this analytic proposition or does it
maintain more? When the
nineteenth-century determinists spoke of regularities and laws, they had in
mind the equations of classical mechanics. Yet
those equations have since then proved inadequate.
Plenty of physical facts became known
in the last decades which are covered neither by mechanical equations nor by
equations of a similar type. Nevertheless,
it is instructive to observe how well determinism turned out - up to the
twentieth century at least. Even vague
and dubious assertions can render good services to empirical research as a
heuristic stimulus.
As we have indicated, determinism for the most
part was conceived in a special form. Up
to the late nineteenth century nature was interpreted as a gigantic but
lawfully functioning mechanism. Since
movements, pressing, pushing, and pulling are the only essential factors in
mechanical devices, in nature, as well, all processes and qualities were
reduced to such movements. All other
qualities, though comprising the greater portion of everyday experience - as
colors, sounds, and smells - were not regarded as “real” ones.
They were interpreted as “illusions”,
and no scientific explanation and no natural law was considered to be
definitive until it was reduced to laws of mechanics.
The mechanical conception of nature began as
early as Galileo. It appeared in
almost all philosophers from Descartes to Kant and dominated physics from the
beginning of the seventeenth to the end of the nineteenth century.
As is generally known, mechanical
theories of sound, heat, light, and electromagnetism were constructed in
complete detail. Such theories were
not completed in chemistry and remained only programs in the provinces of
smell and taste.
How can the rise of this remarkable conception
be explained? Man himself is, in a
certain respect, a mechanical being. All
actions by which he influences the world around him consist in movements, in
pushing and pulling. From the days
178
when he learns as a baby to control his limbs,
he regards that way of reacting as the only natural one.
Unless he happens to be a
physiologist, the more subtle chemical and electrical processes within his
muscles, nerves, and bowels are unknown to him.
Small wonder, therefore, that, when he
looks at the external world, he takes for granted the movements, pushing, and
pulling that he finds there. On the
other hand, he feels that all processes differing from his own actions require
further explanation and tries to reduce them to mechanical ones.
An electric eel, gifted with
intelligence, might behave in an analogous manner.
Imagine an animal of this kind, not
only defending itself and attacking by electric shocks but also attracting
prey by electromagnetism, splitting and absorbing its food by electrolysis!
If it were a physicist, such an animal
would probably look for electromagnetic explanations everywhere.
To summarize, then: the mechanical
conception of nature is anthropomorphic and interprets natural processes after
the pattern of human actions.
Unfortunately, more facts seem to be accounted
for by this biological explanation than actually prove to be correct in
history. Though men have always had a
like biological organization, mechanistic theories are met with only very
seldom and in very few civilizations. Mechanistic
physics appeared only with ancient atomists and Epicureans and in the period
we are just discussing. Obviously,
some additional conditions are required if theories of this type are to
develop. Apparently, the state of the
contemporary technology can give the additional explanation we need.
Man of the seventeenth century had
outgrown primitive animism and begun to see the world with the eyes of an
engineer. But since the only machines
with which the period was acquainted were, without exception, mechanisms such
as printing-presses, weaving-looms, pulleys, and clock-work, it was rather
natural to think that the whole world was a mere mechanism as well.
This prejudice was shaken only when
technology had entirely changed, and nonmechanical engines had become more
frequent than mechanical ones. This
happened in the late nineteenth century.
The scientific value of the mechanist conception
of nature cannot be overlooked. Distances
and shapes, pressure and movement, can be measured comparatively easily: that
is to say, can be co-ordinated to numbers without great difficulty.
On the other hand, qualities such as
blue and cold never, themselves, appear among the results of any calculation,
and their measurement is considerably more complicated.
So reduction of all qualities to
mechanical ones enabled the physicists to co-ordinate numbers to qualities,
and this again made it possible to grasp the physical world by mathematics.
By the mathematization of physics, the
building-up of deductive theories was immensely furthered.
We need not point out how
philosophical rationalism was stimulated by this development, as these
achievements belong with an account of the rational side of knowledge. The
heuristic value of the mechanist conception, however, was not slight.
Everyone who knows the history of
physics also knows how many new empirical facts were discovered and causally
explained for the first time by means of mechanistic models.
Both the rational and the empirical
value of the mechanical conception of nature cannot be doubted.
Yet, being based on a
179
prejudice, that conception had its dangers as
well. Distinction between a “real”
world of mechanics and an “illusory” one of qualities has produced a confusion
of concepts that has interfered with the analysis of knowledge and philosophy
for almost three centuries. This will
be discussed in the next section.
II. The Philosophy
of Modern Classical Empiricism
3. The Opposition of
Outer and Inner World
After natural science had adopted the
experimental method from the craftsmen, it developed rapidly during the
seventeenth century. It was engaged in
its special questions and, consequently, does not offer many problems to
epistemological investigation. The
case of contemporary philosophy was different.
The most remarkable fact in empiricist philosophy of the classical
periods might be said to be the tendency gradually to transfer its interest
from objects to the subject. By this
remarkable tendency it soon became entangled in pseudo-problems.
Medieval animism and the Aristotelianism of the Scholastics were
scarcely overcome when a new metaphysics developed, originating in the
contrast of object and subject, of outer and inner world.
With Francis Bacon (1561-1626), interest in
objects still prevailed; subjective components of knowledge are only mentioned
in his doctrine of idols. Bacon is
convinced that knowledge gives a rather accurate picture of nature if only we
take care in avoiding a few errors and prejudices.
These fallacies are induced partly by
social, partly by individual, conditions by which the judgment of the observer
is disturbed. They can, however, be
eliminated if attention is called to them. As
is generally known, such biases are called “idols” by Bacon and are discussed
by him in an entirely empirical way without involving metaphysics.
The beginnings of the new
subject-object metaphysics appeared in empiricism with Hobbes (1588-1679).
Hobbes was a radical mechanist.
Since in his opinion all processes
consist in movement, he was faced with the task of explaining the origin of
all other qualities that are perceived by us.
He tried to master the difficulty by his terministic theory of
sensation. In his epistemology
sensations are distinguished from objective qualities.
Sensations are not at all copies of
the physical world but only correspond to physical qualities as symbols or
terms do to their objects. Plato has
already duplicated the world by opposing the realm of Ideas to the world of
phenomena. Platonic Ideas, however,
are extremely vague constructs, originating chiefly in certain ethical
considerations and in the philosophy of mathematics; they were scarcely
designed to help naturalists in interpretation of their scientific
observations: the metaphysical background of the Platonic Ideas is obvious.
Into natural science and empirical
philosophy the two-worlds theory was introduced by Hobbes.
Although his terministic theory of
sensation contains valuable elements (which were not, however, developed until
the time of the modern logic of relations), his distinction between the “real”
world of movements and the subjective world of qualities has entangled the
philosophy of
180
nature in pseudo-problems for more than two
centuries. They are the more serious
as they are inevitable implications of the mechanistic interpretation of
phenomena. As long as the latter was
considered the only possible philosophy of nature, the pseudo-problems
connected with the contrast of external world and subjective awareness could
scarcely be eliminated.
The decisive step that changed empiricist
epistemology into an introspective psychological theory of knowledge was taken
by Locke (1632-1704). As generally
known, Locke’s theory of knowledge reduced all statements, both in everyday
life and in science, either to sensation or to reflection.
It belongs to the character of his
philosophy that he spoke rather of ideas and sensations than of facts,
observations, and statements. Modern
logical empiricism restricts itself to analyzing the methods by which
statements are tested and verified, whereas empiricism of the seventeenth
century proceeded psychologically and investigated how ideas are obtained.
Locke’s polemic against rationalism
became a psychological analysis of abstract ideas, on the one hand, and an
attack upon innate ideas, on the other. Since
innate ideas played a rather prominent part in Descartes’s epistemology, this
attack is of considerable historical importance in the further development of
empiricism. But Locke soon turned to a
discussion of the mind of the newborn child and revealed the concept of soul
as the metaphysical background of all his psychological analyses.
Mechanistic philosophy was considered
so self-evident by Locke that its physical implications were not even pointed
out by him; it appears only as his well-known distinction of primary and
secondary qualities. The metaphysical
background of his psychology of knowledge becomes most obvious in his
exposition of the idea of substance. Substance
to Locke was the “unknown support” of qualities.
Although in his opinion that support
is, and ever must stay, “unknown to us”, he did not hesitate to distinguish
material and spiritual substances and to raise the problems of their
interdependence. Locke, the
empiricist, accepted the metaphysical dualism of Descartes without question
and discussed an interdependence, never testable by experience, between
constructs that could not be tested either. The
outstanding scientific and historical importance of Locke’s analyses is
generally known; but the metaphysical pseudo-problems, which are connected
with them, must not be overlooked.
The contradiction between Locke’s empiricist
principle, and his theory of substance was noticed by Berkeley (1685-1753).
Berkeley adopted the principles and
the introspective method from his predecessor but rejected Locke’s theory of
substance. He started with a criticism
of Locke’s theory of abstract ideas. Since
he found by psychological introspection that he was not able to form, for
instance, the idea of a color which is neither red nor blue nor green, he
rejected Locke’s analysis and flatly denied the subsistence of abstract ideas.
By leaving differences out of
consideration and by marking common properties only, one word can obviously
represent quite a group of different objects.
Thus abstract ideas may and must be replaced by abstract words.
Applying this analysis to the concept
of substance, Berkeley concluded that substance is a mere word, void of
content. The unknown “support” of
qualities, which had been assumed by
181
Locke, although it could never be perceived,
Berkeley thought could, and should, be eliminated: matter, being an abstract
construct, does not exist at all. Actually
there are perceivable qualities only, and these are nothing else than
perceptions. Thus Berkeley’s
well-known equation, esse = percipi, resulted.
The only point that strikes us in Berkeley’s
remarkably consistent argumentation is that he failed to apply his analysis to
the concept of mind or soul. Can souls
ever be experienced? Are they not
abstract supports of perceptions or qualities just as matter is?
No doubt it was Bishop Berkeley’s
religious attitude that prevented him from drawing this dangerous consequence.
Avoiding the term “idea”, he always
spoke of the “notion” of soul and would not admit that it is no less abstract
than the idea of matter. Thus he built
up his odd metaphysical system, constructing the world out of souls, ideas,
and God. The tendency in empiricism
both of turning to subjectivism and of getting involved in pseudo-problems has
reached its peak in Berkeley.
Why did English empiricism tend to introspective
psychology and how could it be invaded by subject-object metaphysics?
Both in ancient and in medieval
philosophy only slight beginnings of analogous ideas are to be found.
The modern dualism of inner and outer
world might be correlated with the dualism of soul and body and probably can
be explained by the influence on mechanistic physics of theology.
Belief in immortal souls and the
mechanical conception of nature had never been united in one philosophical
system before the seventeenth century. In
antiquity the atomists and Epicureans were mechanists, but they did not
believe in spiritual substances; Platonists and Stoics, on the other hand,
distinguished souls and bodies but were not mechanists.
Medieval theologians were not
compelled to stress a chasm between spiritual and physical substances, since
in their philosophy all physical objects were imbued with more or less
soul-like powers; they could content themselves with Aristotelian entelechies
which, being forms, were rather connected with than opposed to matter.
Actual and radical dualism was introduced into philosophy by Descartes,
mechanist and devout Catholic. It is
comprehensible that, apart from direct Cartesian influence, similar tendencies
invaded English empiricism as soon as it turned to mechanism.
In their business of investigating
phenomena, natural scientists are faced with the task of separating constant
relations, on which all observers can agree, from the variable and unstable
aspects which are offered under different conditions or to different observers
in a different way. This is the sound
basis for the distinction between objects and subjects.
Bacon, for instance, did not misuse
it. But this separation was
misinterpreted as soon as the mechanistic philosophy of physical phenomena
separated “real” qualities, such as motions, from merely “apparent” ones, such
as colors. The rationalistic
mechanist Descartes became guilty of the misinterpretation as did the
empiristic mechanist Hobbes.
Obviously, it was the rise of mechanistic physics that turned the harmless
distinction between subjective and objective components of observation into a
dualism of inner and outer world. And
it is rather comprehensible that, under the influence of religious tradition,
this dualism was more or less identified with the contrast of soul and matter.
Thus analysis of experience turned
with Locke to
182
introspective psychology - that is, to
investigation of soul. Experience
became a psychical duplicate of the “real” external world, and
pseudo-questions arose: whether both halves of the world actually exist and
how it happens that they correspond.
Locke’s and Berkeley’s principles were
consistently applied to the concept of spiritual substance by Hume
(1711-1776). As is generally known, he
eliminated substantial souls and replaced them by heaps or bundles of
impressions. Berkeley’s philosophy,
which had denied the existence of physical objects but approved the existence
of souls, seemed paradoxical to common sense.
To critics entangled in the problems and language of the period,
Hume’s position of rejecting spiritual substances as well as physical ones
seemed, of course, even more paradoxical. Actually
the paradox was rather diminished by him, for he treated objects and subjects
in the same way and thus approached common-sense realism again.
His analysis is a most important step
toward overcoming the pseudo-problems of a subject-object metaphysics.
In Hume’s time, however, theological
ideas and the mechanistic interpretation of physical phenomena still blocked
the way to a complete understanding and elimination of such pseudo-problems.
Moreover, his analysis was impaired by
his dealing with impressions and ideas rather than with statements.
This predilection for elements of
knowledge which are too minute to be very useful in analysis had originated
with Locke and can be traced in the development of empiricism up to Mach and
the nineteenth century. The same
phenomenon occurs when Berkeley, for instance, as he often does, turns
philosophical criticism to criticism of language.
In this case he is discussing words
rather than statements. This
noteworthy but prejudicial predilection apparently also originated in the
psychological attitude of classical empiricism, for statements are too logical
to attract the attention of psychologists. Analysis
of experience shifted from ideas to statements only when axiomatic methods in
mathematics of the late nineteenth century had roused interest in statements
and their concatenation, and when non-Euclidean geometry and modern symbolic
logic began to influence empiricism. With
rationalists and with Kant, on the other hand, statements always had played an
important part.
Among the most important achievements in the
history of philosophy is Hume’s analysis of the concept of causality.
With surpassing clarity he showed that
we speak of cause and effect if phenomena are connected regularly with one
another. Since cause and effect are
not linked by logical necessity, even the most common causal statements of
everyday life depend entirely on past experiences and never can be inferred a
priori. Induction, therefore, differs
radically from deductive logic and is based psychologically on custom and
belief. Even today the man in the
Street is inclined to conceive cause as a thing that by its activity
produces another thing. Hume’s
criticism destroyed this idea of active production - that last remainder of
primitive animism. Therewith it is
implied that not things but processes, qualities, and relations alone are
causes. And, by
183
stressing regularity of connection, he adapted
the concept of cause to the concept of natural law, the very form in which it
is used in any mature empirical science. His
theory of causality would not have been possible in a period in which laws
were not yet known, and it was obviously inspired by Newton’s and his
followers’ successful investigation of physical laws.
Moreover, it made feasible the future
development of physics. Without Hume’s
concept of cause, nonmechanistic physics of the late nineteenth and the
twentieth centuries scarcely could have come into existence.
Among later philosophers, however, his
analysis has met with considerable criticism, opposition, and - even worse -
complete neglect. As to induction,
later philosophy has made little progress beyond Hume’s remarks.
During the eighteenth century, empiricism, by
emphasizing sensations, turned in France to sensationalism and, with many
philosophers, to materialism. On the
other hand, empiricist philosophy of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
developed important methods and results of psychological investigation.
The laws of association were discussed
again and again; contemporary reports on customs of primitive peoples were
used by Locke in his polemics against innate ideas, and the anthropological
method was successfully developed and applied to the investigation of religion
by Hume; the psychology of people with defective senses was occasionally
referred to in Berkeley’s Theory of Vision and was considerably
furthered in Diderot’s Letters on the Blind (1749) and Letters on
the Deaf-Mute (1751). For the
first time perception of space was investigated psychologically, and the
visible, tactual, and muscular components of the experience of space were more
or less exactly distinguished in Berkeley’s Theory of Vision.
III. The Advance of Empirical
Science
The last remarks have brought us to that field
in the evolution of empiricism which is the most fertile one - the special
sciences. Only the general expansion
of the domain of empirical research can, however, be discussed here.
The empirical spirit of the modern era is
entirely contrary to the spirit of medieval scholasticism and, consequently,
was compelled at first to overcome the resistance of theological tradition.
The rise of empiricism, therefore, is
connected, though not identical, with the spreading of the Enlightenment.
The beginnings of religious
Enlightenment, that is, the ideas of natural religion (Herbert of Cherbury,
1624), were based rather on rational construction than on empirical
investigation of the various systems. Little
attention was paid by Herbert and his followers to the variety of modes of
worship; priests and ceremonies were rather disliked by them.
As is generally known, the main theses
of natural religion stated the existence of God, immortality of the soul, and
reward and punishment in the other world. They
were primarily products of abstract reasoning and were based on empirical
comparison only in so far as they
184
expressed the components common to the three
great monotheistic religions - the only religions well known in this period.
Obviously, the articles of natural
religion indicate the common content of Judaism, Christianity, and
Mohammedanism. Yet the articles were
void of emotional content and do not occur, as they were formulated by Herbert
and his followers, in any living religious system.
The religious attitude of most of the
empiricist thinkers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries was, however,
more or less determined by these rather lean ideas.
It is remarkable that the first empirical
contribution to scientific investigation of religion was made in the modern
era by one of the most consistent rationalists - by Spinoza.
In analyzing the worldly literature of
antiquity, the humanists of the Renaissance had already created and developed
the methods of philological criticism.
Hobbes, in his Leviathan (1651), had advanced a few critical
remarks on the composition of the Old Testament.
Spinoza, however, was the first who,
in his Tractatus theologico-politicus (1670), dared to apply,
consistently, philological methods to the Old Testament.
If painstaking philological criticism
is considered an empirical achievement, Spinoza’s successful attempt to
determine the time of composition of parts of the Old Testament may be
reckoned with the major advances of empiricist thinking.
The next step in this field was taken
by Hume. Hume’s dissertation on the
Natural History of Religion (1753) tried for the first time to give an
empirical theory of general religious development and started comparative
investigation of primitive religions. Hume,
however, knew for the most part only the religious ideas of a few primitive
nations, of ancient Greece and Rome, and, of course, the three great
monotheistic systems. Actual knowledge
of the great religious systems of India and China came to Europe not before
the early nineteenth century. In the
later nineteenth century the empirical science of religion rose considerably,
using the philological and anthropological methods of Spinoza and Hume as well
as modern psychological and sociological ones.
Obviously, empirical thinking could not have spread in the field of
religious and anthropological research were it not for the expansion of
world-trade and the colonial system that made the white race acquainted with
exotic civilizations. In Locke and
Hume these connections had already become visible.
The natural sciences are more than two centuries
older than the science of religion and comparative anthropology.
In the field of astronomy and physics
empirical research had reached its first overwhelming successes as early as
the seventeenth century, in the period from Galileo to Newton.
Chemistry joined the advance in the
eighteenth century and later was followed by mineralogy, geology, and
meteorology. From the methodological
point of view success was obtained in the physical sciences by three means:
they did not restrict themselves to mere observation but experimented wherever
physical processes could be influenced by technological devices; they
investigated the quantitative relations of phenomena; and they considered
discovery of natural laws as the most
185
important goal of research.
Application of mathematics to the
empirical findings and the construction of deductive theories cannot be
separated neatly from those empirical methods and scarcely are less important;
but, as they belong with the rational side of science, they need not be
discussed here.
The biological sciences developed considerably
more slowly. Among them, medicine is
the most ancient one. In the
modern era medical investigation, as well as physical research, was hampered
at first by the social prejudice against manual work.
This prejudice was overcome in the
late sixteenth century, and dissection came in use in anatomy about the same
period as experiment did in physics. As
early as the beginning of the seventeenth century Harvey experimented with
animals in his embryological research and occasionally used quantitative
methods in his investigation of the circulation of the blood.
Nevertheless, the practical tasks of
medicine affect the emotions of men so intensely that metaphysical,
teleological, and even superstitious ideas and traditions were eliminated from
medicine more slowly than from any other natural science.
In zoology and botany quantitative and
experimental methods did not come into general use before the nineteenth
century. Up to that time, biologists
restricted themselves chiefly to observation, non-causal description, and
classification. Classification of the
material must precede the investigation of causes and laws in all empirical
sciences, as in business the stock of goods must be ordered and inventoried
before actual trading starts. In the
field of physics, as well, solid and liquid bodies, acoustical and optical
phenomena, for instance, were distinguished before they were investigated
scientifically. Whereas in physics,
however, most classifications are elementary and, therefore, can be followed
rather soon by causal research, the vaster variety of objects in the fields of
zoology and botany is much harder to survey. Biological
research, as a result, has, during almost three centuries, scarcely passed
beyond classification and non-causal description.
Moreover, it is far more difficult
with plants and animals to produce alterations artificially than it is with
physical and chemical objects. For all
these reasons experimental methods and causal explanations were adopted by
biology rather late. Instead of the
concept of cause, prescientific teleological interpretation ruled the
biological sciences until the nineteenth century.
The eighteenth century, however, was already
aware of the difference between “artificial” and “natural” classification.
Linnaeus, the most eminent biologist
of the period, gave both artificial and natural classifications of plants and
animals. Since plants are extremely
numerous and varied, it is often not easy to determine the species to which
some individual plant belongs. In
order to facilitate that task, Linnaeus classified the plants by the number of
their stamens; he was well aware, however, that this classification was merely
artificial and hardly more than a technical device of nomenclature.
His natural classifications, on the
other hand, aimed at putting together plants or animals in one group which
“actually” are connected with one another. Thus
natural classifications includes the viewpoint of empirically ascertained
relationships and, therefore, is the first step in the direction of causal
research and the theory of evolution.
186
Lamarck’s, and especially Darwin’s, achievements
opened entirely new ways to biological investigation.
Empirical thinking was furthered by
the theory of evolution in four respects. Linnaeus
had still considered animal and plant species as absolutely rigid; there are
as many species, he explained, as have initially been created by God.
By the theory of evolution this rigid
immutability was liquified, as it were: “to be” was replaced by “to become”.
Certainly, the concept of temporal
process is not necessarily involved in the concept of natural law.
There are in physics non-temporal laws
of coexistence as well as laws of temporal change, though the former might be
less numerous. Moreover, the latter
seem to interest men more intensely; human actions are processes themselves
and always aim at influencing the future. At
any rate, the precursor of the concept of law - the concept of cause -
contains the element of temporal change as an essential component.
For that reason interpretation of
living beings as subjects of a permanent temporal process was indispensable if
description and classification were to be supplied by causal explanation and
later by investigation of natural laws. Second,
Darwin’s theory of natural selection (1859) made the first successful, though
yet incomplete, attempt to explain causally the obvious fact that organisms
are well adapted to their environments. Since
the decline of Aristotelian scholasticism, prescientific teleological
traditions had been removed from the field of physics.
With Darwin they suffered the first
serious blow in biology. Third,
Darwin’s exposition of the descent of man (1871) destroyed traditional
anthropocentric philosophy and thus decidedly helped eliminate obstacles to
the empirical investigation of mankind. In
anthropology, sociology, psychology, and ethics this influence became
conspicuous very soon, even if the animal ancestors of man and natural
selection were not discussed at all. Darwin’s
ideas throughout fitted in with the trend of modern empiricist philosophy.
Already, Hobbes, Hume, and a few
representatives of the French Enlightenment had, without even thinking of
animal ancestors of man, consistently treated all human problems as natural,
merely empirical ones. This
interpretation was confirmed and enormously spread by Darwinism.
And, finally, Darwin’s theory called
scientific attention to a few characteristic traits which can be found in any
evolution - even beyond the province of biology.
As it was pointed out by Herbert
Spencer, for instance, specialization, or family-tree-like ramification,
appears in the historical development of occupations and sciences and in the
intellectual development of the human individual as well as in the
phylogenetic evolution of organisms. Thus,
empirical investigation of society, civilization, and mind was also
considerably furthered by Darwin’s ideas. On
the other hand, however, the scientific value of the concept of evolution was
sometimes overestimated. The
merely descriptive statement of some “evolutionary” process in society or
culture is only a preliminary step by which the solution of the scientific
problem is prepared but not given. A
final statement of causes and laws cannot be supplied simply by description of
some one evolutionary process.
Darwin’s theory was based on the practice of
cattle-breeders and on comparative observation.
He did not perform experiments.
This most successful and
187
most exact method of empirical research was
applied to biological problems in the investigation of heredity and physiology
in the late nineteenth century. Mendel
discussed his experiments on heredity (1865) in statistical terms, whereas
some physiologists of the nineteenth century transferred the ordinary methods
and concepts of physics and chemistry to biology and adapted them to the new
problems. Moreover, both modern
genetics and modern physiology investigate quantitative relations and are
seeking natural laws.
At the end of the nineteenth century teleology
seemed to revive again in biology. In
the final analysis Darwin’s causal explanation of the fitness and adaptation
of organisms deals with a statistical phenomenon only.
It discusses the survival of the
fittest within large groups of plants or animals, but it is not interested in
the problem as to how the processes which are characteristic of life are
accomplished in individuals. Such
processes as the development of the fecundated egg, regeneration of injured
organs, and others, were interpreted teleologically by Driesch.
Even the Aristotelian concept of entelechy was reintroduced by him - a
concept which two centuries before had been eliminated from science after long
and arduous intellectual conflicts. The
strangest phenomenon in this resurrection is that it is connected with a
considerable advance of experimental method. For
the aforesaid processes were investigated by Driesch by means of experiments
that proved to be most fruitful. They
showed that processes in one part of an organism are often influenced not only
by conditions in that part but also by other, if not all, parts of the
organism. Driesch and the neovitalists
assume the influence of all parts and speak, therefore, of the efficacy
of “wholeness”; wholeness, however, is interpreted by them as a nonspatial,
soul-like entelechy which aims at ends. This
neovitalistic “explanation” is highly contestable.
Non-spatial entelechies are in no way
observable, and, consequently, the entelechies of a frog and a hydra cannot be
distinguished. It is not clear,
therefore, what help they can give in explaining, predicting, and controlling
the rather different processes occurring in these different animals.
Obviously, entelechies are additional
metaphysical ingredients and do not contribute anything to a solution of the
empirical problems. The phenomena of
regeneration and formation are now actively investigated.
They cannot yet be explained
satisfactorily, though many partial successes have been achieved.
Nevertheless, there is no reason to
assume that, in this field, solution of the scientific problems will be
achieved by other means than by experiments, causal explanation, and
investigation of laws.
The beginnings of psychology in the modern era
appear rather remote from empirical research.
Descartes and Spinoza, when discussing human passions, gave
theoretical constructions which were intended primarily to support the ethical
ideals and theories of each philosopher. Yet
it cannot be doubted that their “psychological” studies are based on a good
deal of introspection into their own minds and comparative observation of
fellow-men. The same methods were used
more consistently by Locke, Berkeley, and Hume in their analysis of
188
knowledge. Most
psychologists of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries were highly
impressed by the scientific success of Newtonian physics; they were,
therefore, seeking psychological laws, and considered the laws of association
to be analogous to, and as important as, the laws of mechanics.
Such physical analogies become rather
conspicuous in the psychological treatises of both the physician Hartley and
the chemist Priestley. Morals, also,
were again and again investigated psychologically.
By application of psychological
methods to the problems of ethics, certainly a major advance in empirical
thinking was made. On the other hand,
in the eighteenth century, psychology still dealt chiefly with knowledge and
rather neglected emotions, volitions, and actions.
Psychology in the nineteenth century developed
considerably, both as to its subjects and as to its methods.
In the psychology of knowledge the
constructs of the deductive sciences began to be investigated.
It was even assumed that logic could
be reduced to psychology. Quite a
number of epistemologists were convinced that all problems of logic would be
solved if the psychological origins of logical concepts and logical
propositions were found out. By their
critics their line of thought was called “psychologism”.
Psychologism in the nineteenth-century
epistemology distinctly mirrors the empirical tendencies of the period and
even exaggerates them. It obviously
committed the same error a chess player would make if he thought that
knowledge of the historical and psychological origin of all chess rules could
answer the question of which chess problems are solvable and which are not.
On the other hand, psychologists with
a leaning toward the natural sciences investigated sensations in close
connection with psychological research. Thus
experimental and quantitative methods were introduced into at least one branch
of psychology.
With the decline of the Enlightenment, the
irrational sides of the human mind also began to attract attention.
In the early nineteenth century German
romanticists were already highly interested in passion and emotion and,
moreover, paid a great deal of attention to hypnotism, somnambulism, and
insanity. Philosophers and
psychologists belonging, as did Schelling and Schubert, to the Romantic
current of thought, began to deal also with the irrational and abnormal
components of mind. These were
interpreted, both by writers and by theorists, metaphysically, and even more
or less magical ideas frequently occur in the expositions.
Again a new and fruitful field of
research was discussed at first in prescientific terms, as often happens in
the history of science. This initial
stage, however, was overcome about the middle of the nineteenth century.
Scientific psychology divested itself
of magic and metaphysical ideas without resuming the eighteenth century’s
overestimation of intellect. It turned
to voluntarism and investigated emotions, appetites, and instincts
empirically, frequently in close connection with biology, physiology, and
animal psychology. Psychiatrical
research arose, and the comparison of normal and abnormal mind contributed
fruitful data to psychology. Investigation
of neuroses, and of hysteria especially, added unconscious processes to the
objects of physiological research.
189
The new conception that mind is composed of
unconscious as well as conscious elements apparently is exposed to
methodological objections. [10] Viewed
empirically, mind seems to be equivalent to awareness.
Unconscious mental processes,
therefore, seem to be a contradiction in terms and to be metaphysical
constructs which can never be tested by experience.
Yet, these objections do not hold.
Psychology of the nineteenth century
is, for the most part, based either on introspection or on empathic
interpretation of the behavior of fellow-men.
In this behavior, however, speaking and intentional communications
form but a small part; other, and unintentional, reactions are far more
numerous. No psychologist, therefore,
bases his scientific assertions only on the words by which his fellow-men
describes their awareness but makes use of their physiological reactions - for
instance their blushing, their actions, and their omissions of action - as
well. Is there any reason to abstain
from investigating processes which do produce such reactions, actions, and
omissions, though they cannot be described by the individual in whom they
happen? Since the individual in whom
they occur is not aware of them, it might be objected that they ought to be
called physiological processes. Actually,
we may hope that in the future they will be explored by physiological means,
and certainly physiological investigation would furnish more exact results
than the psychological investigations of the present time.
Nevertheless, the above procedure can be justified.
When an individual acts in a certain
way because of some past experience which is perfectly well remembered by him
but is so disagreeable that he does not like to speak of it, and when another
individual has “repressed” an extremely painful experience so that it has
become entirely “unconscious”, both kinds of behavior can greatly resemble
each other. The similarity becomes
manifest in the fact that the observer can put himself psychologically in the
place of both persons by means of empathy. The
very possibility of empathy in both cases is the link by which conscious and
unconscious processes are connected. This
is the empirical reason why we are justified in using psychological terms and
psychological methods in investigation of the unconscious.
Physiological processes, on the other
hand, work quite differently from unconscious ideas, wishes, and purposes and
are not accessible to empathy.
We have made use of empathy as of an empirical
symptom of the relationship between conscious and unconscious mental
phenomena. It must be remarked,
however, that it cannot be used as a definitive method of research.
When we interpret the behavior of
fellow-men by means of empathy, our interpretation mirrors experience which we
happen to be familiar with. Empathy,
therefore, is subject to major errors and always needs farther examination by
means of more reliable methods. We may
strongly feel that a man is angry, and yet all inferences based on our feeling
may later prove to be wrong. When, on
the other hand, his further behavior conforms with our expectations, then and
only then our opinions of him are verified. Since
empathy works much faster than careful scientific examinations, it supplies
most of the psychological judgments in everyday life.
[10] We need not distinguish here between
unconscious and subconscious processes.
190
Yet scientific predictions, based on empathy,
may be relied on only in so far as they are confirmed by observable actions
and reactions of the individuals concerned. The
method of empathic interpretation may be used in scientific psychology as a
preliminary heuristic tool. Certainly,
it is fruitful if its results are tested later by observation of the
perceivable behavior. But it is highly
fallible, and the scientific content of all assertions obtained in this way
consists solely in those components which can be confirmed by observation.
The precariousness of empathy has led
to the rise of behaviorism, which is discussed at another place in this
Encyclopedia. At any rate, it is
an empirical fact that man can experience empathy in certain cases and is
unable or less able to experience it in other ones.
The cases in which it can be
experienced - that is, the conscious and the unconscious mental processes -
obviously have certain empirical features in common.
To summarize: if and only if empathy is more or
less feasible, may an unconscious process be named “psychological” and be
reckoned among mental phenomena. Nevertheless,
empathy is a symptom only. With it a
certain type of functioning, that is, of causal connection, becomes manifest
that, apparently, is common to conscious and unconscious mental phenomena.
Or, to put in a different way:
conscious and unconscious components of mind are subject to kindred laws;
physiological processes, to entirely different ones.
The unconscious elements of mind have
been introduced into psychology in order to fill the gaps of its causal
explanations and to complete the domain of validity of psychological laws.
This method of completing the
scientific domain is entirely legitimate and is used in the physical sciences
as well. Astronomers, for example, do
not hesitate to discuss multiple stars with partly bright and partly dark
components. Psychology of unconscious
mental phenomena is not less empirical than astronomy of invisible stars.
Another point, which need not be
discussed here, is that, in its present state, the method of exploring
unconscious phenomena needs improvement. Psychology
of the unconscious is young and fruitful; but it is as inexact as all young
sciences have been initially. Greater
exactness may be obtained in the future by experiments and by comparison with
animal psychology. In this article,
however, we are not concerned with empirical details and special questions.
It has only been necessary to discuss
the basic question of empirical testability.
Among empirical sciences, the social sciences
are youngest. They have developed
gradually from at least three different sources.
Jurists, political writers, and
philosophers of the seventeenth century dealt with public law and political
philosophy. They were, however, more
concerned with rationally establishing their political aims and theories than
with careful and unbiased observation of empirical facts.
Hobbes, for example, was more a
rationalist than an empiricist in his theory of society.
He was among the most consistent
representatives of the doctrine of social contract, which dominated political
philosophy until the end of the eighteenth century; and this doctrine’s
disregard of experience is obvious today. Primitive
man subscribes to rational agreements just as little as he believes in the
rational articles of “natural religion”. With
the
191
advance in overseas trade, savage nations
gradually became better known in eighteenth-century Europe, and an increasing
number of authors began to criticize, with empirical arguments, the hypothesis
of a social contract.
About the same period, French writers, among
them Voltaire, Raynal, and Condorcet, started investigating the history of
human civilization and the development of social institutions.
In political historiography, also, the
advance of empirical thinking and the gradual disappearance of theological
ideas might be traced. Yet, the
political historians still dealt with single events and individuals and hardly
belong among the predecessors of the sociologists.
On the other hand, the writers who cultivated “philosophical” history,
as it was called in the period of the Enlightenment, helped to prepare the way
for the social sciences. They
discussed general processes in the development of civilization and the
interdependence of these processes. The
ideas of such writers were mixed with unexamined assumptions concerning human
progress and contained a good deal of wishful thinking; but, in the last
analysis, their philosophy was based on empirical observation and comparison:
the “philosophical” components of their expositions were but vague - and often
incorrect- formulations of sociological causes and laws.
Reports on exotic peoples were also
published more frequently in the eighteenth century; they greatly influenced
the writings of the “philosophical” historians and, therefore, may be counted
among them.
A third source of the social sciences springs
from the practical needs of economy. In
contrast to more primitive forms of economy, capitalism requires rational
regulation of economic activities. This
holds true of private as well as of political economy.
Since the beginning of the modern era,
the princes - or rather their secretaries and counsellors - were compelled to
form opinions on the question of how taxes and duties influence commerce and
manufacture and are, in turn, influenced by the prosperity of the latter;
their revenues depended on these questions. When,
in the middle of the eighteenth century in France, problems of agriculture
also became urgent, public officials and private writers began to study
economies more systematically. And,
finally, Adam Smith, the friend of Hume, published his comprehensive theory of
economic processes (1776). He thus
created the science of political economy and started a scientific development
which has continued up to the present day. Political
economy is the oldest among the social sciences.
As it originated in the needs of an
eminently rational and antitraditionalist form of economy, it was from its
very beginnings based on reasoning and experience.
It never went through an animistic
stage and was spared controversy with Aristotelian entelechies. [11]
Control and prediction of economic
processes were among its aims from the beginning.
Consequently, theoretical economists
immediately began looking for causal explanations and very soon for economic
laws. They obtained, and still obtain,
the empirical material for their theories by comparative observation; in the
nineteenth century
11 In the twentieth century, however, a few
German economists attempted to introduce entelechies in political economy.
192
statistical methods were added and proved to be
highly successful. Experiments have
not yet been performed in the field of economics.
The hazardous steps, in politics and
business life, that are often called economic experiments are done neither for
scientific purposes nor with the necessary scientific precautions.
Rational deduction and mathematics do play a
large part in certain economic theories. Political
economy might be the only empirical science in which, for the reasons
mentioned above, the empirical elements are likely to be impaired rather by
excess of rational deduction than by prescientific tradition.
It is still a rather imperfect
science. It is about two centuries
younger than physics, and its subject matter is more complex; economic
experiments are not performed, and economic research is exposed to more
selfish interests, political pressure, and wishful thinking than is the case
in any other science. It is
comprehensible, therefore, that in political economy scientific agreement
could be reached only on comparatively unimportant questions; in fact, there
are separate schools which do not even recognize each other.
Some of them cling to experience; the
results of their inquiries are collections of material rather than theories in
which facts are causally explained. Others
deal with nothing but laws of economy; they investigate them by means of
rational analysis of a few basic concepts and construct large deductive
systems based upon scanty observations. And
yet, after all, political economy might be considered the most advanced among
the social sciences.
Sociology originated in the beginning of the
nineteenth century. Two rather
different thinkers, Hegel (1770-1831) and Comte (1798-1857), may be called the
first sociologists. Hegel comes from
German Romanticism. His Philosophy
of History employs the dialectical method, which is claimed to be rational
and forms the backbone of his whole philosophical system.
This method can be traced back to
Plato. The metaphysical mill of
thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, however, is as empty as inexact; it could
yield almost any result. In Hegel’s
system it begins its work with the concept of being.
It cannot be doubted that the method’s
rich output has, unconsciously, been supplied by and adapted to experience,
for it would be sheer magic if reasoning alone were able to derive an
abundance of concrete details from a concept which is devoid of content.
However, while Hegel’s exposition of
philosophy of nature is rather sterile and sometimes strangely contradicts
later experience, his philosophy of history, law, and religion abounds with
fruitful results. Apparently, the
artificial mechanism of dialectic fits, approximately, certain processes which
often occur in history, society, and civilization.
The exact and empirical description of
those processes, and the demarcation of provinces in which they occur and in
which they do not, has not yet been accomplished.
Hegel discussed the general lines of
development in law and ethics, in morals and political institutions, in art,
religion, and philosophy. He did not
describe isolated events but comprehended numerous single facts in one
construct and saw relationships which no one before him had noticed.
These relationships always refer to
temporal succession of cultural phenomena. As
they are repeated in an analogous way in various fields, they may be taken as
preliminary intimations of laws of sociological succession.
193
Regularity, however, was always interpreted as
necessity by Hegel. Fruitful empirical
knowledge often appears at first in vague and metaphysical expressions;
Hegel’s philosophy of history is possibly the most impressive case in point.
Comte, the disciple of Saint-Simon, stemmed from
the philosophical historians of the French Enlightenment.
His attitude was entirely empirical
and antimetaphysical. He was well
trained in the natural sciences and regarded prediction as the main goal of
knowledge. For him, to know
meant to foresee, and science, in his system, is identified with the
investigation of laws. Like Hegel, he
investigated only the main lines of historical development and comprehended
numerous single facts in very general statements.
Utilizing the ideas of predecessors,
he affirmed the sequence of a theoretical, a metaphysical, and a positive
stage in the history of civilization. This
succession is supposed to appear in different fields in the same way.
His theory of civilization, therefore,
may be taken as a preliminary formulation of a sociological law of succession.
Comte coined the names of both
sociology and positivism. Compared
with Hegel, his expositions contain less speculation, but their empirical
results are probably poorer.
It is not necessary at this point to survey the
development of sociology after Comte. And
even achievements so important as the introduction of the concept of evolution
by Spencer and the emphasis on economic facts and economic groups by Marx need
not be discussed here. But a few
methodological aspects should be pointed out.
Among sociologists there are today various schools and many
controversies; some schools even disregard the investigations of most of the
others. It might be generally agreed
that sociology is an empirical science. It
is based on observation and comparison, if not yet on experiment.
As it does not deal with individuals
but investigates groups and mass phenomena, the general sociological
statements which appear in still rather uncritical forms in Hegel and Comte
must be based on careful and complete collection of material if reliable
results are to be achieved. It is here
that statistical and sometimes even quantitative methods were successfully
introduced in sociology. They were,
however, largely applied to quite elementary phenomena and their use
frequently resulted in mere collections of material.
Causal and comprehensive sociological
theories, based on statistics, are still lacking.
Apart from the difficulty of putting
them into practice, there is no reason why statistical methods might not be
employed in the investigation of Hegel’s and Comte’s problems as well, that
is, in investigation of cultural processes. Sociological
processes are usually interpreted psychologically, that is, by empathy.
It has already been pointed out that
empathy proves to be fruitful as a heuristic method but that its results must
always be tested by observable facts.
As to sociological laws, modern sociology does
not restrict itself to the investigation of laws of succession but seeks laws
of coexistence as well. There are,
however, sociological schools which deny the possibility of any sociological
laws. These maintain that in social
research causes and laws have to be replaced by “types”, by “understanding” -
that is, empathy, by “wholeness”, entelechies,
194
and values. The
preliminary methods of non-causal description and classification and,
moreover, all pre-scientific and teleological concepts of the past are revived
as ultimate goals of science in this rebellion against causality.
No convincing reasons, however, have
yet been given proving that causes and laws must be discarded.
In everyday life we are wont to
predict, more or less successfully, such social phenomena as overcrowdedness
of railroad trains, the outcome of elections, and the trend of public opinion.
Predictions like these presuppose that
social phenomena are connected more or less regularly. It may be that in any
society regularities practically always have exceptions and, consequently,
hold only approximately. Social groups
are seldom isolated and usually interact with one another; the number of their
members is always comparatively small; the members are very different, and
some of them exert disproportionate influence.
These conditions do not favor group laws.
With a gas inclosed in a vessel with
permeable walls and consisting of only a million molecules, a few of them
being extremely large, rather inexact gas laws could be ascertained.
It is possible that in sociology,
also, only very inexact regularities can be discovered.
Yet, no physicist or astronomer would
entirely disregard a regularity on the ground that it did not always hold.
One more point must be considered.
The classical gas laws deal with the
interdependence of temperature, pressure, and volume of the gas.
Nevertheless, the single molecules of
which the gas consists have neither temperature nor pressure; they whirl at
random, have kinetic energy and impulse, and are, in classical mechanics,
subject to laws entirely different from gas laws.
In an analogous way sociological laws
might connect quite different variables than psychological laws do, though
social groups consist of human individuals. Thus
we have come back once more to the question of empathy.
If we look for social regularities by
means of empathy, we may never find them, since ideas, wishes, and actions
might not appear in them at all. That
is, social regularities may belong to a type of connection entirely different
from psychological ones. At any rate,
if there are sociological laws, they can be discovered only by actually
looking for them and not by discussing their possibility.
And what methods are to be employed in
this investigation? The empirical
methods of causal research have, in all sciences, proved to be so fruitful
that we shall not rashly give up hope of finding them successful in the field
of sociology too.
We have surveyed the advance of empirical
thinking in the domain of the special sciences.
We have found that, though different
means of inquiry were adapted to the various subjects of the various sciences,
in the final analysis success was achieved by the same methods everywhere.
These methods are: collection of the
material, observation, and comparison; experiment wherever objects can be
influenced by technological means; counting and measuring, if possible; causal
investigation and investigation of laws. As
to methods, there are no basic differences among empirical sciences.
The empirical methods are best
developed in physics, and physical patterns, consequently, have influenced the
other sciences in an increasing degree, despite the remarkable countercurrents
in sociology and biology of the last decades.
As to methodological maturity and
195
scientific success, biology is today next to
physics. Sociology, on the other hand,
is the least mature among the empirical sciences.
Whether psychology or political
economy is better developed is an open question.
When such questions are to be decided,
the deductive theories in the various sciences and the application of
mathematics to their problems must be taken into account as well; the rational
methods, however, have not been discussed here.
As to historical sequence, the
physical sciences are the oldest. It
is noteworthy that causal psychology, which originated in the middle of the
eighteenth century, and even causal political economy, which originated in the
late eighteenth century, are considerably older than causal biology, which
originated with Darwin and the physiology of the late nineteenth century.
Yet biology has since then outstripped
by far its older competitors. The
historical sequence and historical development of the sciences do not exactly
conform to the various degrees of complexity of their problems.
They are greatly influenced by
economic needs and the great struggle of ideas and can be explained only in
connection with the general process of history.
IV. The
Decline of the Mechanical Conception of Nature
9. The elimination of
mechanical models
In the second half of the nineteenth century
important physical discoveries resulted in the breakdown of the mechanical
theories of light, electricity, and magnetism.
As philosophy, since the period of Galileo, had been influenced by
physics to a higher degree than by any other empirical science, this physical
revolution also reshaped philosophical thinking and the analysis of knowledge.
The process began with Maxwell’s inquiries on
electricity (1865). Using the experiments and ideas of Faraday (1791-1867),
Maxwell succeeded in comprehending all laws of the spread of electromagnetic
actions in two fundamental equations. Faraday, on the other hand, had
interpreted electromagnetic processes mechanically and pictured electric and
magnetic lines of forces as invisible ropes, acting in accordance with
mechanical laws. Maxwell also obtained
his equations by means of a mechanical (namely, a hydrodynamic) analogy, but
the mechanical model turned out to be extremely complicated this time.
Maxwell was forced to imagine a model
consisting of rotating, invisible ether whirls and interspersed invisible
particles pushed on by the rotations. In
addition, his equations connected electrodynamics with optics, since they
contained the velocity of light as an essential constant and covered all laws
of propagation of light-waves as well. When
H. Hertz twenty years later (1888), by his famous experiments, ascertained,
for the first time, the existence of electromagnetic waves, the wave theory of
light definitely became a part of Maxwell’s theory of electromagnetism.
Still, electromagnetic waves were
supposed to spread as a kind of movement in the ether.
The ether, however, had on the one
hand, to penetrate everything and, on the other, to behave mechanically as a
solid body, if observable optical phenomena were to be represented correctly.
Thus,
196
mechanical models gradually came to be regarded
as tools with which science might possibly dispense.
Why should one derive both
electromagnetic and optical from mechanical laws by means of highly complex
models if all laws of optics can be derived directly from simply constructed
electromagnetic equations? Possibly
mechanisms do not have any preferred place over other physical phenomena.
If equations, wherever they are
derived from, present all the observable facts in the simplest way possible,
they may very well fulfil the task of science better than theories attempting
to reveal a “real” world behind the phenomena.
At first, ideas like these ventured forth
hesitatingly, and their implications were either not realized or met with
considerable resistance from physicists. Even
before the experiments of Hertz, Kirchhoff, the founder of modern
astrophysics, advocated, in his Lectures on Mathematical Physics
(1874), the opinion that physics had to “describe” rather than explain
phenomena. Similar ideas were
supported by Helmholtz four years later (Tatsachen der Wahrnehmung,
1879). The physical and
epistemological implications of such ideas were developed, with greater
radicalism, by the philosophical physicist Ernst Mach (Mechanik in ihrer
Entwicklung, 1883). Mach analyzed and consistently refuted the belief in
the priority of mechanics to the other branches of physics.
In his conception of science,
scientific explanation is equivalent to “economical description” of the
observed facts; science has to represent, as he pointed out, as many facts as
possible by as few concepts as possible, and it is irrelevant whether the
concepts used are taken from mechanics or elsewhere.
Moreover, Mach disclosed the
philosophical pseudo-problems originating from the mechanical conception of
nature. The opposition of an objective
world of quantities and a subjective world of qualities, which had confused
philosophy for three centuries, has been overcome in his analysis of
scientific knowledge. Starting from
different problems, the historian of physics, Pierre Duhem, and the chemist
Wilhelm Ostwald helped to destroy the mechanical prejudice.
Duhem (La Théorie physique, son
objet, sa structure, 1906) pointed to the different styles of thinking
favored by the English and the French, respectively, in their physical
theories; he ascertained that the theories of the French, representing the
facts solely by means of mathematical equations, were not less efficient than
the English theories based on mechanical models.
On the other hand, general energetics,
advocated by Ostwald, was also suited to weaken the overestimation of
mechanics; for energetics restricted itself to discussing transformations of
energy in all fields equally and disregarded mechanical models.
Mechanism suffered its decisive defeat, however,
in the theory of relativity and modern atomic physics.
Influenced by Mach’s ideas, Einstein
published his fundamental papers on the special theory of relativity in 1905
and on the general theory in 1916. As
is generally known, the theory of relativity pointed out the connection
between certain paradoxes of light-propagation and of all spatial and temporal
measurements and gravitation. Those
highly general connections could no longer be represented by mechanical
actions of one ether. A mechanical
model of all relativistic laws has not yet been mathematically constructed in
197
every detail.
If, after the theory of relativity, a physicist still intended to be a
mechanist, he would have to take refuge in a “great-” if not a
“great-great-ether” behind the ether, in order to represent all relativistic
facts. Evidently overcomplicated and
patched up, a mechanism like this could not stand competition with the
mathematical conciseness of the relativistic equations. And, finally, in 1913
Niels Bohr’s paper appeared, which succeeded in representing the hydrogen atom
by a planetary system of particles of electricity.
From this day modern atomic physics
has, with increasing success, derived all properties of matter itself - among
them pushing and pulling - from actions of particles of electricity.
These actions follow entirely
non-mechanical laws. It can be
explained only by history why modern microphysics has been named quantum
mechanics. As is generally known,
Bohr’s original model of an electrical planetary system has since been given
up and only equations are left. In
Heisenberg’s, Dirac’s, and Schroedinger’s quantum mechanics there is, for the
most part, no question of even spatial movements of particles, let alone their
pushing and pulling. Thus we have come
to realize that it amounts to the same thing whether attraction of electric
charges is explained by the pulling of invisible cords or the pulling of cords
by the behavior of electrons and protons. We
accept that theory which covers the observable phenomena and which, at the
same time, is the more comprehensive, the more consistent, and the simpler.
The mechanical prejudice has
definitely been overcome. It needs not
be mentioned that the breakdown of the mechanistic conception does not mean at
all a return to premechanical animistic or teleological ideas.
The statistical laws of quantum
mechanics are as rational and mathematical as the laws of classical mechanics
and not a bit nearer to the behavior of living beings or spirit. [12]
The breakdown of mechanistic physics took place
during a period of complete revolution in technology.
The levers and pulleys of the
seventeenth century had receded to the background long ago.
The steam engine and, in the second
half of the nineteenth century, the electromotor, the dynamo, and the
internal-combustion engine had taken their place.
The working of all of these is based
on non-mechanical processes. Merely
mechanical machines, as bicycles, typewriters, and foot-driven sewing
machines, have been comparatively unimportant in the economy of the last sixty
years. The textile industry, in
which mechanisms played a comparatively greater part, had been the leading
industry up to the early nineteenth century but was fifty years later
surpassed by far in economic importance by the electrical and then by the
chemical industry. Men, and even the
children, of the twentieth century do not feel at all strange about the
working of an electric bulb, a telephone, a photographic camera, a radio set;
what is even more important, they do not feel any different toward the working
of these implements than toward the working of a typewriter.
The movements by which man influences
the world around him have, with the technology of the twentieth century,
shriveled down in many cases to turning on a switch; the elec-
[12] Cf. Philipp Frank, Interpretations and
Misinterpretations of Modern Physics.
198
tromagnetic, chemical, and caloric processes
which are then initiated do the rest. If
man is inclined to conceive natural processes after the pattern of how he
himself influences nature, it is scarcely a surprise that the priority of
mechanics has completely dwindled. Certainly,
modern technology and economy have not only influenced modern physical
theories but have been influenced by them as well.
The electrical engineer, Marconi, did
succeed the theorists Hertz, Maxwell, and Mach.
On the other hand, however, Mach
succeeded the steam-driven factories, the dynamo, and the electromotor, and,
certainly, electro-engineering and radiobroadcasting helped immensely to make
the nonmechanical conception of nature less paradoxical.
The breakdown of mechanistic physics could not
fail to give a new impetus to empirical thinking.
With the failure of mechanistic
physics, the assumption of a second world behind experience had lost its
scientific support. Now the
subject-object metaphysics, the pride of all philosophers, who looked down on
the naïve laymen, was badly shaken; its problems began to appear as
pseudo-problems. Since causes and laws
were employed in the new physics as functional connections and mere
regularities, the unempirical components of those concepts, already criticized
philosophically by Hume, became suspect for scientists as well.
All these implications were
consistently developed by Mach. On the
other hand, physical hypotheses and models had suddenly turned out to be
unsuitable, though having proved fruitful for three centuries.
Necessarily, general methodological
questions arose as a result of that fact, and, for the first time in the
history of modern physics, the whole internal construction of science became
problematic. What part is played by
simplicity in scientific theories? Which
natural laws should one consider as fundamental, and which as derived, when
constructing a theory? What service
can be rendered to science by working hypotheses, by fictions, and by
conventions? Most of these problems
deal rather with the deductive side of theoretical knowledge than with its
empirical components. They were raised
by Mach, by fictionalism and conventionalism of the late nineteenth century,
and were more or less suggested by the physical revolution.
Poincaré’s conventionalism, however,
was influenced by modern mathematics as well as by the new physics.
In the early twentieth century those
mathematical and logical influences increased, united with the empiricist
tradition, and resulted finally in logical empiricism - a subject which must
be reserved for later treatment.
199