The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
September
2002Edwin G. West
iProperty Rights in the History of Economic Thought:
From Locke to J. S. Mill
Carleton Economic Papers,
2001-01
Index
HHC: Index added.
This paper
1 is designed to acquaint the reader with the historical background of the concept of property rights and several surrounding controversies by reviewing early work on property by economists and philosophers (with the main emphasis on the former). The survey focuses on significant contributions from the seventeenth to the nineteenth centuries, setting the stage for the following chapters that reflect more recent thinking. The first section offers a critical assessment of the seventeenth-century work of John Locke which, to this day, has provoked the most intensive discussion and controversy. ii The second section attempts to detect Lockean natural law or natural rights components in the influential writings of Adam Smith, the eighteenth-century father of economics. The third section analyzes Jeremy Bentham’s hostile criticism of the Locke and Smith views on property and his preference for his own philosophy of “utilitarianism,” which can be summed up as the principle of the “pursuit of the greatest happiness.” In addition, the third section examines the practical attempt of Bentham’s disciple, Edwin Chadwick, to achieve egalitarian legislation. The fourth section is reserved for the remarkably influential utilitarian (and egalitarian) writer, John Stuart Mill, and explores the connection between him and the “scientific socialists,” including Marx and Engels. The fifth section considers David Hume’s concentration on the initial tendencies to conflict among men and the prospects for ultimate mutual improvement and practical coexistence through market exchange. The final section offers the main conclusions.1. Please note that the paper has
derived from my contribution to a symposium, which explains frequent references
to “this symposium” etc.
1
When John Locke’s Two Treatises of Government
first appeared in 1690, nothing could have shocked the ruling classes
more. Property had been viewed,
hitherto, as exclusively something created by government. Locke maintained that it was instead the
source of government. As a
consequence, “Government has no other end but the preservation of property”
(Locke [1690] 1991, 329). The
message, in other words, was that property and property rights existed prior to
government. To what extent Locke’s
proclamation was in support of the English Revolution of 1688 is a matter of
debate. In his preface, he
expressed the hope “to establish the throne of our great restorer, our present
King William…, to justify to the world the people of
Locke’s reference to “natural rights” so early in his
treatise symbolized his central thrust. But to understand fully Lockean natural
rights, it is first necessary to examine the arguments of his chief adversaries,
the supporters of absolute monarchy. Their position was represented in Sir
Robert Filmer’s celebrated Patriarcha, published in 1680. As Filmer believed that the relation
between King and subject was the same as that between father and child, it
followed logically that individual property could be granted only by the crown.
It was this argument that Locke
firmly rejected. God, he insisted,
had not bestowed property rights on the monarchy exclusively. Not only was private property already in
existence previous to government, but it was also upheld by natural law and the
doctrine of natural rights.
Locke’s pregovernment “state of nature” was not a “state
of war” (in striking contrast with the position of earlier philosopher, Thomas
Hobbes (1651), and men became acquainted with the law of nature through their
reason. Mistakes could certainly be
made, especially since it was potentially rancorous for each and all individuals
to do their own separate policing of their individual property rights. It was dangerous, in Locke’s words, that
“every Man hath a right to punish the Offender, and be Executioner” of this law
(Locke [1690] 1991, 272). Men
will
2
consequently find it practical to consent to a social
contract to form a government that is primarily a trustee for its citizens.
At the same time, there was also
the possibility that governments might run into error so that, on occasion, they
too should be subject to appropriate discipline. “If government is bound by the Law of
Nature, then deviation by the rulers from the tenets of this law was sufficient
grounds for their overthrow” (Valcke 1989, 943). This right of revolution in Locke was
justified because, to repeat, private property was antecedent to, or independent
of, government.
Locke’s moral philosophy sees man’s evolution in terms
of conquering his surrounding nature. At first, his appropriation of land stems
from his need for basic subsistence and survival. Eventually, however, private property
also expresses man’s ability to reason and to develop his personality. But Locke places such a heavy emphasis on
economic production that one is tempted to look for some connection with the
mercantilism of his time. Mercantilism urged the encouragement of
exports and discouragement of imports, with the purpose of increasing relative
economic power over one’s neighbors.
In his section Of Property, Locke ([1690]
1991, 286) maintains that “God… has given the Earth to the Children of Men,
given it to mankind in common.” The
use of the phrase “in common” might at first sight suggest elements of
collectivism, what today would be called commonly owned or communally owned
property. But some interpreters
understand Locke’s common ownership to mean simply the absence of ownership, or
open access property owned by no one or thing. “That which is common is not ownership”
(Valcke 1989, 957). As for Locke’s
natural rights, these range from the broad and philosophical, to the narrow and
materialistic. Among the former are
the rights to one’s own life and liberty. The latter relate to rights to produce
not only usefull consumer goods but also to any concomitant producer-good. The main example of a producer-good was
improved land, as explained in section 27 of Locke’s Second Treatise
([1690] 1991, 287):
3
Though the earth, and all inferior Creatures be common
to all Men, yet every Man has a Property in his own Person. This no body has any Right to but
himself. The Labour of his Body,
and the Work of his Hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then, he removes out of the
State that Nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his Labour with,
and joyned to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his Property.
It being by him removed from the
common state Nature placed it in, hath by this labour something annexed to it,
that excludes the common right of other men.
Here, some writers interpret Locke as saying that mixing
a man’s labor with an external object results in an extension of his
personality, moving one step further toward human self-realization. Two centuries later, Karl Marx would
extend this proposition radically to claim that capitalism “alienates” and
dehumanizes its workers because markets obliged them to part with their output,
output that was a revered extension of their personalities. Locke would obviously not have approved
of this interpretation of his argument. iii
In the passage quoted above, Locke offers a normative
theory of the creation of property rights. Also in section 27 of his Second
Treatise ([1690] 1991, 288), he amplifies and qualifies his theory of
appropriation, or creation of property, as follows, “For this labour being the
unquestionable Property of the Labourer, no Man but he can have a right to what
that is once joyned to, at least where there is enough, and as good left in
common for others” [Emphasis added]. For several scholars, this so-called
Lockean “proviso” has somewhat obscured his general argument, and much has
subsequently been written in attempts to fully understand it. One common and obvious question has been
whether unqualified appropriation of a resource by one worker interferes with
the liberty of others. Nozick
(1974, 174) for instance observes: “A process normally giving rise to a
permanent bequeathable property right in a previously unowned thing will not do
so if the position of others no longer at liberty to use the thing is
thereby
4
worsened.”
It has been this last word, “worsened,” that has been the focus of attention in the appropriation
debate.
Narveson (1991, 3) raises the query, “worsened compared
with what?” He goes onto review
what he finds to be at least five interpretations of Locke’s proviso, and
contends that those who interpret it to mean that the individual
worker-appropriator is thereby causing others to have less, in the sense of
depriving others of something, are wrong on two counts. First, there is an implicit assumption
that there is a fixed or finite quantity of a potential resource such as
land. This static view is
erroneous, however, because when people own territory, they proceed to land
clearance, ditching, fertilizing, and irrigating. More dynamically then, ownership results
in expanded resources for everyone: ‘They [owners] transform what is less useful
into what is more so, thus increasing resources… And secondly, what he
‘deprives’ others of isn’t a ‘good’. It is merely a chunk of the material
world, awaiting someone who will turn it to good use” (Narveson 1991,
13)
Much of the Lockean discussion relates to normative (as
distinct from positive) analysis. Locke was particularly absorbed with
morality and “justice issues.” The
focus of much modern deliberation, in contrast, is on positive analysis such as
the question of how property rights emerge in practice, regardless
of the reasoning of moral philosophy. The chapters that follow in this volume
are essentially positive. Nevertheless, justice remains important.
As Lueck (this volume, XXX)
observes, “Locke’s theory of property remains a powerfil defense of individual
rights.” More particularly, Locke’s
defense of rights “remains more or less consistent with real-world application
of the rule of first possession” (Lueck, this volume, XXX)
Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations was, and remains, a powerful work of economic science, rather than philosophy. Nevertheless, there has been considerable debate about how much of Smith’s work is infused with Locke’s Natural Law/Natural Rights Tradition
. iv It is certainly easy5
to point to Smithian quotations that are very
reminiscent of Lockean language.
Consider, for instance, Locke’s opposition to idleness in society and his
belief that active production is conducive to human development. This is also suggested in Smith’s
statement that “Man was made for action, that he may call forth the whole vigor
on his soul, and strain every nerve in order to produce those ends which it is
the purpose of his being to advance. Nature has taught him that neither
himself nor mankind can be fully satisfied with his conduct... unless he
actually produced them” (Smith [1759] 1976b, 106).
A more striking Lockean sentiment appears in Smith’s
moral championship of the rights of employees and employers to produce mutually
agreed upon labor contracts. To
hinder a man from employing his labor howsoever he desires without injury to his
neighbor, Smith insists, is a violation of the “most sacred property.” Indeed, “The property which every man has
in his own labour, as it is the original foundation of all other property, so it
is the most sacred and inviolable” (Smith [1776] 1976a, I. xc, 12,
138).
In his “Lecture on Justice,” Smith made one important
distinction in Locke’s reasoning: natural rights he confined to the rights to
liberty and life, whereas the right to property was an acquired right depending
on the current disposition of society. “The rights which a man has to the
preservation of his body and reputation from injury are called natural…” (Smith
1896, 401). Smith’s separation of
natural rights from the rights to property are further expressed in the
following quotation from his
The origin of natural rights is quite evident. That a person has a right to have his
body free from injury, and his liberty free from infringement unless there be a
proper cause, nobody doubts. But
acquired rights such as property require more explanation. Property and civil government very much
depend on one another. The
preservation of property and the inequality of possession first formed it, and
the state of property must always vary with the form of government. (Smith 1896,
401)
6
Smith’s placement of liberty in the category of natural
rights is interesting and significant because what he calls “natural liberty”
pervades the whole political economy of The Wealth of Nations. Thus he condemns all legislation
that interfered with free individual trading. But such freedom to trade affected the
incentive to create and maintain property. Because of the existence of continuous
markets, prices were being kept reasonably stable and thus incentives to further
capital (or property) accumulation, were emerging. Capital accumulation, in turn, was
encouraging further divisions of labor (specializations) and these were
resulting in sustained technological progress.
So far it seems that several of Smith’s arguments echo
John Locke’s reasoning, although Smith’s separation of natural rights from
property rights was a substantial modification. The duties of government reported by both
writers also reveal striking similarities. Just as Locke argued that “Government has
no other end but the preservation of property” (Locke [1690] 1991, 329), Smith
maintained that “Till there be property there can be no government, the very end
of which is to secure wealth and to defend the rich from the poor” (Smith 1896,
291).
Economists now attempt a fill rationale of Smith’s
position as follows. Even where
property rights exist independently of government, there are significant costs
of defining and protecting them. Anderson and Hill (Chapter 5) call these
transaction costs and provide illuminating examples. McChesney (Chapter 9) identifies the role
for government as justified by its lower costs of defining and defending rights.
Adam Smith observed that property
rights always require the ability to exclude others (nonowners): “It is only
under the shelter of the civil magistrate that the owner of that valuable
property, which is acquired by the labour of many years... can sleep a single
night in security” (Smith [1776] 1976a, 710). Several other contributors to this
volume, however, would qualify Smith’s argument that property can survive only
via the protection of government.
Beyond this, others would point out that government can
typically lower the costs of defining private rights only because of its
monopoly on the use of force. This
being so, it may be naïve to believe that such government monopoly is always
used for the public good
7
(McChesney, this volume). Ultimately the justification of
government is an empirical matter, a point that is repeatedly made by Smith’s
historical case studies. Consider,
for instance, his empirical analysis of slow economic growth in
In a country too, where, though the rich or the owners
of large capitals enjoy a good deal of security, the poor or the owners of small
capitals enjoy scarce any, but are liable, under the pretence of justice, to be
pillaged and plundered at any time by the inferior mandarines, the quantity of
stock employed in all the different branches of business transacted within it,
can never be equal to what the nature and extent of that business might admit.
In every different branch, the
oppression of the poor must establish the monopoly of the rich, who, by
engrossing the whole trade to themselves, will be able to make very large
profits. (Smith [1776] 1976a, 112)
Smith’s view that a central duty of the sovereign was
the preservation of property via a proper legal framework is also emphasized in
the following:
When the law does not enforce the performance of
contracts, it puts all borrowers nearly upon the same footing with bankrupts or
people of doubtful credit in better regulated countries. The uncertainty of recovering his money
makes the lender exact the same usurious interest which is usually required from
bankrupts. Among the barbarous
nations who over-ran the western provinces of the
In all, there were three duties of the sovereign
according to Smith:
8
(1) Protection against invasion by other
countries.
(2) The duty of protecting as far as possible every
member of society from the injustice and oppression of every other member, that
is, the duty of establishing an exact administration of
justice;
(3) The duty of erecting and maintaining certain public
works and certain public institutions, “which it can never be for the interest
of any individual, or small number of individuals to maintain because the profit
could never repay the expense to any individual or small number of individuals…"
(Smith [1776] 1976a, 688).
The natural law (rights) tradition is located most
clearly in the second of these three duties. As for the third, Smith has been
criticized by libertarians for outlining a positive (public works) role for
government that went further than upholding justice and protecting property.
Duty number 3, in fact, has been
described as representing the philosophy, not of natural law/rights, but of
Benthamite utilitarianism (reviewed below) which instructs government to
supersede the market in many areas. Such criticism, however, is somewhat
off-target. Smith’s argument with
respect to the third duty is commonly misunderstood and must be evaluated in its
eighteenth-century context. In
particular, the arguments involve the role of government in allowing large-scale
stockholder-owned firms to exist. Smith’s discussion of the third duty
clearly shows his increasing awareness of the advantages of the extension of
limited liability. There was a
growing need at the beginning of the industrial revolution for ‘instrumentality”
in carrying on a large business. There was, in other words, a general a
demand for much more legal variety in the structure of property rights. To merchants and entrepreneurs, the
commercial advantages from incorporation were becoming obvious: continuity of
existence, management independent of that of members, ease of suit against third
parties or against members, transferable shares, unlimited divisibility of the
equities, and the distinct limitation of liability for a company’s debts and for
those of its shareholders.
Traditionally, the major ways that a corporation
(company) could be created were (a) by judicial interpretations of the common
law, or (b) by the king’s charter. This area of royal
(and
9
later parliamentary) discretion to create new property
rights, substantially explains Smith’s discussion of public works under the head
of the “third duty of the sovereign”; and indeed, it was traditionally the
sovereign’s responsibility long before that of legislatures. Most of the corporations formed from 1485
to 1700 were created exclusively by royal charter. The Russia Company (1555), the East India
Company (1600), and the
Later on, the additional sanction of the legislature was
demanded more and more to accompany privileges created by the crown. In the latter half of the eighteenth
century, incorporation by special act became increasingly common for utilities
such as canal and water companies. Charters and private acts of
incorporation usually included special provisions regulating the activities of
the organization in question. It is
arguable that the nature of the complex procedure necessary to secure
incorporation would have been viewed by Smith as another hindrance to private
business freedom. His third duty of
the sovereign, therefore, could have been seen by him, not as an instruction to
government to undertake discretionary and utilitarian economic intervention, but
rather as another demand for the enlargement of the whole legal framework and
therefore the area of natural liberty, a demand that was, of course, consistent
with natural law tradition.
In the late eighteenth century, special deliberation was
called for in deciding how to satisisfy the increasing needs of new projects
that required large sums of capital. And it was in such a context that Smith
expounded the sovereign’s third duty. This was a time when the joint-stock
organization was very widely suspect after the calamity of the South Sea Bubble
of 1720. We now know that the great
shortcoming in that period lay not so much in the joint-stock system itself as
in the way it was then applied and the need for more experience with it. In any case, the disaster had more to do
with government failure than market failure. Holders of
government
10
bonds were allowed to exchange them for stock in the new
South Sea Company. The Company,
moreover, had been given a monopoly of British trade with islands of the
There is an interesting parallel between Smith and Frank
Knight (1924) on the subject of incentives. Harold Demsetz’ essay (Chapter 11)
usefully reminds us of the famous article by Knight criticizing Pigou’s
contention that the existence of external costs demands government imposition of
a corrective tax. The context of
the debate was a scenario containing two roads, one of which is superior and the
other inferior (in terms of congestion, road surface, etc.). Pigou argued that drivers would make
excessive use of the superior road and ignore the consequent additional
congestion cost (i.e. the external cost). This situation then allegedly calls for a
government tax on the use of the superior road that is large enough to optimally
reduce the congestion on it. Knight, however, argued that Pigou had
neglected the issue of ownership of the road. “Once this is done, decisions made by
resource owners are clearly shown to eliminate potential externalities”
(Demsetz, this volume, XXX). In
other words, the private owner of the superior road can charge for its use an
appropriate toll. Because ordinary
economic reasoning shows that such a toll will exactly equal Pigou’s ideal
government tax, the latter then becomes quite superfluous.
Adam Smith very much anticipated Knight’s analysis.
He treats roads under “the third
duty of the sovereign,” based on the need for what Smith called “public works.”
When it came
to
11
the issue of who should pay for them, Smith insisted that the greater part of the public works be self-financing. “A highway, a bridge, a navigable canal, for example, may in most cases be both made and maintained by a small toll upon the carriages which make use of them.” (Smith [1776] 1976a, 724). In the same way, other public works were already being supplied by joint-stock firms in the areas of banking, insurance, canals, and bridges. Although Smith classified public works as those which it “would not profit an individual or small number of individuals” (Smith [1776] 1976a, 723), eventually, he argues explicitly, it would profit a large number of individuals, organized in for-profit joint-stock enterprises. It is clear, therefore, that, like Frank Knight, Smith did not neglect the issue of resource ownership and the incentives it creates. If he had done so, it is likely that, like Pigou, he would have simply assumed central government was the only route to the supply of public works
. viIt is useful, finally, to refer to a common belief that
Smith disliked large joint-stock enterprises. What he was mainly critical of was the
frequent habit of governments in attaching a monopoly of trade to the grant of
joint-stock status. The South Seas
Company was one example, but there were several others. In contrast, those enterprises such as
the Hudson Bay Company (without the monopoly privilege), met his unqualified
approval. And as just seen, his
opinion of joint-stock companies in domestic activities was also favorable, as
was his whole discussion of the need for “public works” (the sovereign’s third
duty), properly understood. Indeed,
this led to Adam Smith’s recommendations for allowing joint-stock enterprises in
the “public works” of banking, canals, water supply, roads, and bridges. Such enterprises would not only have much
needed access to large capital markets but would also be able to avoid ambiguous
title to their property
Adam Smith was influenced in natural law thinking by
writers other than, and somewhat different from, Locke. He was introduced to two of these by his
mentor, Francis Hutcheson; they were the Dutch jurist Hugo Grotius (1583-1645)
and the German legal specialist Samuel Pufendorf (1632-1694). Smith and Hume agreed with them on
several matters, but especially on the conviction that man could not live
without society. This meant, in
practice, that individuals
12
could not survive without a commonly-agreed system of
law. Man indeed was now seen
primarily as a “legal or juristick person rather than the citizen-warrior of the
civil humanist tradition” (Teichgraeber III 1986, 21).
Grotius asserted himself most strongly against views on
property that had been inspired by Aristotle and repeated by his followers in
the Middle Ages. Aristotle had
conflated exchange justice (also known as commutative justice) with distributive
justice. The latter was connected
with the notion that there had once been a common ownership of all things and
that equity demanded that individuals enjoy a natural right to a potential share
of them even if they do not yet possess them. Grotius seems to have opposed this
concept without compromise. There
was, in fact, he insisted no such category as distributive rights (Teichgraeber
III 1986, 23).
It is interesting that the fullest respect for
individual property rights, according to both Grotius and Pufendorf, required
the absolute power of one ruler. Pufendorf went so far as to call for a
social contract. But both Smith and
Hume objected to this inference as they also did to Locke’s social contract
argument. They believed that such a
project was too rational and would threaten or delay the emergence of
spontaneous (naturalistic) liberty
John Locke’s natural law/rights system of thought and
his conviction that private property existed prior to law received hostile
criticism from Jeremy Bentham in his Theory ofLegislation which
was first published in 1795, five years after the demise of Smith. He protested that the advocates of
natural law and natural rights, such as John Locke and his followers, had
advanced no proof. Their systems,
moreover, varied unpredictably in content. Natural rights, in fact, were dangerous
metaphors (nonsense on stilts”) based on capricious and subjective feelings.
The only true conception of right,
Bentham insisted, was one that was based on “real laws.” Property, which involves a guarantee of
security of possession into the future, cannot exist without government:
“Property and law are born together and die together” (Frankel Paul 1979, 50).
And
13
property in the real world can change following
alterations in law. To assert
dogmatically a natural right in property would be to claim that government had
no freedom to tax it without the consent of the owners.
Lockean followers would probably answer that Bentham was
confusing the concept of right with the concept of power. Accordingly, Jonathan Macey
observes:
Merely because the government or some other organization
has the raw power to take away my wealth, or my ability to earn wealth, does not
mean that it has the right to do so… Thus, a state’s mere exercise of its power
to deprive citizens of their property rights does not mean that these rights do
not exist. The idea of natural
rights refers to those rights that human beings possess by virtue of their
status as human beings. (Macey 1994, 186)
This response again brings into focus the idea that
natural law is based on some version of morality.
Despite his dismissal of the nature theory of government
and property, Bentham was not averse to interjecting his own system of morality,
a system that describes not only what we in fact do, but also asserts what we
ought to do. In Bentham’s
words:
Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two
sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we
ought to do, as well as to determine what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right and
wrong, on the other the chain of causes and effects are fastened to this throne.
(Bentham 1948, quoted in Frankel Paul 1979, 52)
Bentham’s ultimate principle: the pursuit of the
greatest happiness, implied the need for equality of material possessions, an
objective that Bentham himself tried initially to keep
within
14
bounds, but which in the hands of followers such as J.S.
Mill, eventually inspired an intellectual if not political, revolution. The predictability of enjoyment of
property into the future that Adam Smith had urged, on behalf of his free market
vision, consequently faced a frontal challenge.
Bentham’s happiness principle spawned a substantial
catalogue of what he called his “agenda” for government intervention. His list was in effect based on
cost-benefit analysis of each individual issue. If the expected increase in benefit
(happiness) was greater than the expected increase in cost (pain), then
government should undertake the project and not otherwise. On this principle, he approved of
government aid in the construction of canals, railways, hospitals, and public
workhouses. Meanwhile, despite
Bentham’s complaint that the doctrine of natural law (rights) advanced no method
of proof, his own principle of utility (greatest happiness) failed also in this
respect. He was defensive as well
on the question of how the legislators were to be selected. And once selected, from where were they
to obtain the precise information concerning the propensities of given projects
to bring happiness or pain? These
questions will be addressed in more detail when we examine further property
implications of Benthamite Utilitarianism.
The fuller fruition of utilitarianism can best be seen
in the hands of Bentham’s disciples, Edwin Chadwick and John Stuart Mill (the
latter of whom warrants a separate section below). Chadwick was Bentham’s last secretary and
became one of the most influential utilitarian policy maker in
nineteenth-century
The waste that Chadwick was out to eradicate appeared at
first to be mostly associated with what we call natural monopoly. This market structure, however, was
often assumed rather
15
than demonstrated.
His typical “reform” plan was to allow competition “for the field,” with
a government-run auction for the right to produce, and the winning bidder
agreeing to undertake centralized contract management of the whole industry or
service. One of Chadwick’s
immediate examples was the postal service. Efficiency improvements, he argued,
stemmed from the successful bidder being awarded an exclusive contract, an
arrangement that, he argued, reduced transaction costs, excess capacity, and
uneconomic overlapping (or duplication). The reformed, nationalized undertaking
would not be run by government personnel, however, because, Chadwick insisted,
government was utterly incapable of direct management. The alternative he favored was public
ownership together with a “special executive commission” to run
things.
As shown, on the subject of efficient resource
allocation, Adam Smith focused on private resource ownership and the useful
incentives that accompanied it. Bentham, in contrast, asserts that
public, i.e. government ownership, is more desirable. But public ownership was a vague concept
and rarely did it receive full definition or analytic rigor. Within a collectivity, one’s share of
public assets is not likely to be exactly the same as that of other individual
citizens. Even if such shares are
initially equal, the question arises about the rules of collective decision
making. Does public ownership mean
that priority is to be given to the preferences of the median voter, bearing in
mind that individual preferences will vary across the population of
voters?
More important is the question of the influence of
government employees. De Alessi
(this volume, XXX) emphasizes that “Government employees with authority to
manage government-owned resources… do not bear the economic consequences of
their decisions. Accordingly, they
have incentive to take them into account only in so far as they generate
political pressures, bribes, or personal utility.” None of those considerations accompanied
Chadwick’s recommendations of public ownership and “special executive
commissions.” As Buchanan (1978, 3)
has observed,
One example affords a particularly graphic insight into
Chadwick’s general policy approach. The London Cab Market, he declared,
displayed wasteful excess capacity because, at
16
any one time, at least one-third of the cabs were
unemployed. Therefore, instead of
continuing to allow inordinate competition within the field,
In contrast to Smith’s rejection of a large
redistribution function of government, John Stuart Mill gave it pride of place.
In so doing, he attacked, in
effect, the whole foundation of Smithian political economy including the role of
property. Focusing on economic
methodology, Mill drew a sharp distinction between positive and normative
issues. The laws of production
(such as the law of diminishing returns), Mill emphasized, were inexorable
(positive economics), whereas, in strong contrast, the laws of distribution were
malleable according to society’s disposition (normative economics). Prevailing divisions of the national
produce should accordingly be subjected to the Utilitarian tests for maximum
happiness. The latter objective was
now considerably clarified by the belief that the true Utilitarian creed
implied, not simply the greatest happiness, but “the greatest happiness of the
greatest number.” Since each
individual had an equal claim to happiness, he had an equal claim to the means
of happiness. This same assertion,
of course, implied the need for the collectivization of property and income of
all kinds.
17
One new element in the writings of the Utilitarians was
an enthusiasm for the contemporary spread of a democracy based on simple
majority voting. This too, of
course, had profound implications for property rights. It was well known, even in Mill’s time,
that democracy often encouraged transfers to special interests. Since, in effect, these interests are
given the right to determine the disposition of wealth created by others,
property rights are correspondingly attenuated. In contrast, Adam Smith’s efficiency
generating “invisible hand” system depended crucially upon the existence of
private property rights that were stable and well defined. In addition, Smith assumes the natural
liberty of all individual participants to choose what they believed were the
best suppliers, employers, and employees.
Utilitarianism seriously ignored these crucial Smithian
conditions. In several instances,
the emergence of Benthamite government suppliers resulted in the crowding out of
private suppliers via unfair competition. This result, of course, was to the
detriment of the latter’s property rights. Consider, for example, Mill’s argument
([1848] 1969, 953) that government can provide better education than that
supplied in private schools that were freely selected by
parents
Now any well-intentioned and tolerably civilized
government may think, without presumption, that it does or ought to possess a
degree of cultivation above the average of the community which it rules, and
that it should therefore be capable of offering better education and better
instruction to the people, than the great number of them would spontaneously
demand. Education, therefore, is
one of those things which it is admissible in principle that a government should
provide for the people.
In the above quotation the words “well-intentioned” and
“tolerably civilized” to describe government is illustrative of the increasing
faith in reformed democracy that Mill hoped was arriving by the mid-nineteenth
century.
18
It must be said that of all economists discussed herein,
none seem to have exceeded Mill in the intellectual energy devoted to the
question of property and in the search for various possible and reasonable
social policies towards it. vii Among all the classical writers, Mill was
the first to include in his major work two whole chapters on the subject of
private property. Chapter 2 of Book
2 in Mill’s Principles of Political Economy ([1848] 1969) suggests the
strong influence and guidance of his wife, Harriet Taylor. The chapter starts with a
noncontroversial Lockean approach that recognizes in each person a right to the
exclusive disposal of what he or she has “produced by their own exertions, or
received either by gift or by fair agreement, without force or fraud, from those
who produced it” (Mill [1848] 1969, 218). Each person, however, is not entitled to
the whole produce because capital as well as labor has contributed to
production; and capital, Mill makes clear, is the consequence of saving and
abstinence.
In his fuller definition of property, Mill contended
that, although it involves, among other things, a legitimate right of bequest,
or gift after death, “the right of inheritance, as distinguished from bequest,
does not” (Mill [1848] 1969, 221). Mill here began to inject his Utilitarian
value judgements as to how the wealth of recently deceased persons should be
disposed of The two chief
beneficiaries, he contended, were (a) relatives, even distant ones, and (b) the
state. Mill insisted that “in a
majority of instances the good not only of society but of the individuals would
be better consulted by bequeathing to them a moderate, than a large provision”
(Mill [1848] 1969, 224). To the
extent moderate bequests meant there was money leftover, the state should take
the residue. The confidence with
which Mill expressed his implicit claim to know the “good” of society plus that
of individuals, and to determine what is a desirably “moderate” bequest to
children in individual cases, is striking. It seems relatively easy to conclude that
his position was colored by the new enthusiasm for governments run by persons
well-versed in, and motivated by, Bentham’s maximum happiness
doctrine.
Mill conceded that bequest is one of the attributes of
property. “All the reasons, which
recommend that private property should exist, recommend pro tanto
this extension of it. But
property is only a means to an end, not in itself an end (Mill [1848] 1969,
226, emphasis added).
19
Mill personally preferred a restriction, not on what one
might bequeath, but on what any one should be permitted to acquire, by bequest
or inheritance (Mill [1848] 1969, 227). Bequests should not be allowed to enrich
one individual, beyond a certain maximum, “which should be fixed sufficiently
high to afford the means of comfortable independence” (Mill [1848] 1969,
228).
Mill ends his chapter with some searching questions
concerning the justification of property in land.
When the ‘sacredness of property’ is talked of, it
should always be remembered, that any such sacredness does not belong in the
same degree to landed property. No
man made the land. It is the
original inheritance of the whole species. Its appropriation is wholly a question of
general expediency. When private
property in land is not expedient, it is unjust. (Mill [1848] 1969,
233)
It is of course important to remember that Mill was
writing in 1848 when the Irish Potato Famine was fresh in his mind. Ownership of land had caused suffering,
he complained, not only because of the incompetence of some landlords but also
due to an improper legal framework. The main example of the latter was the
continuation of primogeniture (the legal requirement that the eldest son inherit
his father’s estate), a practice against which, like Adam Smith, Mill strongly
objected. The system of
landownership had reduced welfare, Mill protested, because many proprietors were
not improvers of the land. Moreover, they frequently granted the
liberty of cultivation “on such terms as to prevent improvements from being made
by any one else” (Mill [1848] 1969, 231). Again, much of this inefficiency was due
to the institution of primogeniture. “When the land goes wholly to the heir,
it generally goes to him severed from the pecuniary resources which would enable
him to improve it, the personal property being absorbed by the provision for
younger children, and the land itself often heavily burthened by the same
purpose” (Mill [1848] 1969, 231).
20
The logic of such argument would suggest a solution, not
in the crude form of land nationalization, but in amending the constitution to
reduce or end the practice of primogeniture. This was the strategy of Adam Smith.
While Mill might be seen as arguing
implicitly in the same direction, he nevertheless proceeds to spend much time in
condemning the character of existing landlords. “The community has too much at stake in
the proper cultivation of the land... to leave these things to the discretion of
a class of persons called landlords, when they have shown themselves unfit for
the trust” (Mill [1848] 1969, 234). But if Mill was intimating that there was
another class of persons more suitable to the task, he did not follow up with
fully explicit suggestions.
It is interesting to consider Mill’s approach as it
relates to John Locke’s “proviso” discussed earlier. Locke had claimed, “For this labour being
the unquestionable Property of the Labourer, no Man but he can have a right to
what that is once joined to, at least where there is enough, and as good left in
common for others” (Locke [1690] 1991, Second Treatise, Section
27, 288). Narveson’s 1991
interpretation of Locke, it will be recalled, includes the assumption that when
individuals obtain pieces of land, they improve it and so actually expand
resources. In this way, others
benefit, at least in the long run. Mill would not have accepted this claim.
From the very nature of the case,
he insisted, “whoever owns land, keeps others out of the enjoyment of it.” Whereas the Narveson interpretation of
Locke takes it for granted that those who “join their labour” with the land will
then proceed to improve it, Mill was not convinced and demanded advance proof.
To him it seemed almost an axiom
“That property in land should be interpreted strictly, and that the balance in
all cases of doubt should incline against the proprietor” (Mill [1848] 1969,
234). In the case of land, he
emphasized, “no exclusive right should be permitted in any individual, which
cannot be shown to be productive of positive good” (Mill [1848] 1969, 235).
Notice too that Mill was
automatically adopting non-Lockean language in his Benthamite assumption (in the
previous sentence) that rights to land had to be “permitted” by
government.
21
As for the postulated leading causes of the overwhelming
Irish famine, several do not stand up. viii But Mill’s explanation does not stand up,
either. Why were Irish farmers
incompetent, as Mill claimed?
In his book Why Ireland Starved (1983),
Joel Mokyr restates the issue as ‘Why was Ireland Poor?” In emergencies, the poorest have no
cushion of modest savings to help them purchase other foods (imported or
otherwise). This is not an academic
point. It is true that the disease,
caused by the fungus Phylophthora Infestans, spread alarmingly
beginning in 1845, and savagely reduced the crucial potato crop. Yet the same blight also “struck
Having first attributed Ireland’s problem to
overpopulation, economist Thomas Malthus identified another and more important
clue following a visit to Ireland in the 1830s: “There is indeed a fatal
deficiency in one of the greatest sources of prosperity, the perfect security of
property, and till this defect is remedied, it is not so easy to pronounce upon
the degree in which the redundant capital of England would flow into Ireland
with the best effect” (Malthus [1836] 1951, 349-500). The lack of “security of property” had
several causes. One was “the
chronic guerrilla war between tenants and landlords” (Bethel 1998, 252). Added to that violence and resulting lack
of secure property rights was the profound and continuous religious hostility
between Catholics and Protestants.
Another and even more important factor was the stiffing
restrictions on manufacturing imposed by a protectionist English government that
prevented the Irish from realizing the full value of their property. Adam Smith had already warned about this
in a letter to Henry Dundas in November, 1779. The letter is quoted in full by Viner
(1965, 350-52). Speculating on what
the Irish Parliament had meant when speaking of a “free trade,” Smith
observed:
22
They may perhaps understand by it no more than the power
of exporting their own produce to the foreign country where they can find the
best market. Nothing can be more
just and reasonable than this demand, nor can anything be more unjust and
unreasonable than some of the restraints which their Industry in this respect at
present labours under. They are
prohibited under the heaviest penalties to export Glass to any Country. Wool they can export only to
They may mean to demand the Power of importing such
goods as they have occasion for from any Country where they can find them
cheapest, subject to no other duties and restraints than such as may be imposed
by their own Parliament. This
freedom, tho’ in my opinion perfectly reasonable, will interfere a little with
some of our paltry monopolies. Glass, Hops, Foreign Sugars, several
sorts of East Indian goods can at present be imported only from
They may mean to demand a free trade to our American and
African Plantations, free from the restraints which the 18th of the
present King imposed upon it, or at least from some of those restraints, such as
the prohibition of exporting thither their own Woolen and Cotton manufactures,
Glass, Hatts, Hops, Gunpowder, etc. This freedom, tho’ it would interfere
with some of our monopolies, I am convinced, would do no harm to
They may mean to demand a free trade to
23
opinion, would be more highly advantageous to both
countries than this mutual freedom of trade. It would help to break down that absurd
monopoly which we have most absurdly established against ourselves in favour of
almost all the different Classes of our own manufactures.
Whatever the Irish mean to demand in this way, in the
present situation of our affairs I should think it madness not to grant
it.
The fact that Smith’s warnings were not heeded, and that
Understanding the true, property-based reasons for the
Irish famine is important, for many have drawn incorrect conclusions from the
episode. Mokyr (1983, 294)
observes:
The facts above show, on the contrary, that in
24
Mill wrote at a time when different varieties of
socialism were appearing throughout
To understand the Scottish philosopher and economist,
David Hume, it is helpful initially to compare him with others, and especially
with Jean Jacques Rousseau. Rousseau believed primarily in what he
called “social property.” Distribution was to be left to the
“general will” of collective society. Locke had maintained, in contrast, that
the initial distribution of property was,
25
in the words of Walron (1994, 85), “Determined in large
part by morally legitimate acts of unilateral
acquisition.”
Hume was convinced that it was better to avoid being
obsessed with a search for the appropriate code of ethics that would govern
issues concerning property because there were several to choose from and they
were subject to constant disagreement. Among the many, potentially discordant
value systems were altruistic ethics, egoistic ethics, Christian ethics, and
utilitarian ethics. Even if
agreement could be reached among the participants, there remained the question
whether government was stable enough to fulfill the distributional objective.
Government corruption, for
instance, had to decrease before appropriate progress could be
made.
Like Smith, Hume looked to decentralized commercial acts
in a developing free market as the best agency for attainable harmony. The focus was upon the process of trading
with the help of increasingly efficient contracts. And such a scenario, of course, implies
increasing respect for property rights. Smith observes in The Wealth of
Nations that Hume was the only writer so far to have noticed the connection
between the market and order and good government. The improvement in the latter, Hume
believed, was a function of the growth of contractual commerce and per capita
economic output. Unlike the
romantic Rousseauesque philosopher, Hume based his conclusions on substantial
empirical evidence located largely in his numerous wide-ranging historical
surveys.
Ryan (1989, 229) observes that “a crucial question to be
asked of any system of property rights is whether it favors political stability
and political liberty.” To a large
extent this question looks for answers that are sociological. In our review of the treatment of
property and property rights in the history of economic thought, it is Smith and
Hume who stand out as having emphasized most the relationship between freedom
and property (capital) accumulation. To Smith, both items together constituted
a necessary condition for new divisions of labor that resulted not only
in
26
lower prices, but alsotechnological progress via
invention and innovation. The
mercantilist system that Smith was attacking was one of politically imposed
preferences that slowed productivity by robbing property rights of much of their
proper (undistorted) functions. In
contrast, well-respected property rights placed in a clear and secure legal
setting, together with guaranteed liberty, were sufficient to set the wealth of
nations on a course for almost perpetual growth. In Smith’s words ([1776] 1976a,
42):
All systems either of preference or of restraint,
therefore, being thus completely taken away, the obvious and simple system of
natural liberty establishes itself of its own accord. Every man, as long as he does not violate
the laws of justice, is left perfectly free to pursue his own interest in his
own way, and to bring both his industry and capital into competition with those
of any other man, or order of men. The sovereign is completely discharged
from a duty, in the attempting to perform which he must always be exposed to
innumerable delusions and for the proper performance of which no human wisdom or
knowledge could ever be sufficient; the duty of superintending the industry of
private people, and of directing it towards the employments most suitable to the
interest of the society.
Some relationship between property rights and liberty is
also to be found in John Locke, although it is not as definite as in Smith.
This is partly because Locke’s
perspective was more that of moral philosophy than political economy or
sociology. Locke certainly wished
to defend the liberty of citizens against the despotism of absolute monarchy.
He aimed also to elevate liberty to
a natural right, and the latter stemmed from natural law which, in turn, is
based on the reasoning of free people. True, quotations from Adam Smith strongly
suggest the natural law approach of Locke, especially Smith’s reference to labor
as the “most sacred property.” But
this appears to be in addition to Smith’s main preoccupation with the history,
political economy, and sociology of property and property
rights.
27
With the utilitarians of the nineteenth century, the
emphasis and reasoning changed almost completely. They seem undisturbed that taxation
beyond some minimum was a strong potential eroder of the value of property owned
by those taxed. The revolutionary
change in sentiment was expressed clearly in John Stuart Mill’s separation of
the laws of production from the laws of distribution. The distribution of wealth
via taxation, Mill asserted, was a matter of discretionary human institution.
“The things once there, mankind,
individually or collectively can do with them as they like” (Mill [1848] 1969,
200). The flaw in this statement,
of course, is that the political distribution of ‘The things once there” will be
a serious brake on the things being there in the future. Investment, after all, is a function of
its expected net (after tax) proceeds
With Mill, connections between property rights and
liberty became ambiguous. Instruction to voters to use taxation to
do as they wished with the fruits of other people’s investments would have been
seen by Locke and Smith primarily as an invasion of others’ rights. The same can be said of Chadwick’s
arbitrarily appointed “special executive commissions” to run his nationalized
undertakings. Crowning the whole
utilitarian program was its liberty-threatening subjection of all individuals to
instructions about how to achieve maximum happiness. In presenting his education bill to
Parliament in 1833, the Utilitarian J. A. Roebuck claimed that people could not
be happy by themselves; they had to be taught how to be
happy.
It is true that the natural law tradition that the
Benthamites attacked was itself based on some deep notions of human equality.
Natural law equality was not,
however, the equality of wealth or income that Mill had in mind. To John Locke, it was mainly equal
natural rights to appropriate, and so ultimately benefit from, natural
resources. To Adam Smith, it was
the equality of all to enter the market system. Both Locke and Smith thus saw equality in
terms of opportunity to prosper, not in terms of the final prosperity people
achieve. The implication in both
Locke and Smith is that some eventual inequality would ensue, at least for a
time. And if this was a problem,
what was the solution? For Smith,
the constant incentive of workers to
28
improve their property (i.e., their labor power) could,
to a large extent, be relied on to improve things much more than government
intervention.
Griswold (1999) concludes that Smith (unlike the
utilitarians) was very skeptical about the ability of the state to organize a
plan of redistribution that would be fair and efficient. In part, he saw the problem partly as one
of the state’s inadequate knowledge of the particular circumstances that
determine each person’s opportunities. Because one family, for instance, will be
more responsible than another in preparing its offspring for the labor market,
some inequality is unavoidable. And
with regard to the state’s possible efforts to redistribute in favor of the
deserving, Griswold (1999, 252) interprets Smith as emphasizing: “Assessing in a
consistent manner who the deserving are, and just what they are due, lies beyond
the ken of the legislator or statesman.” But in any case, the self-interest of the
bureaucrat in siphoning off to himself much of the income that is intended for
redistribution would itself block suitable action to achieve equity or precise
commutative justice.
Some admirers of Adam Smith may be sensitive to the
presence of religious language and concepts in his work, and especially in his
adoption of the theocentric principles of natural law. Pufendorf, one of Smith’s mentors on this
subject, started with the proposition that reason alone shows us that man may
live in society successfully only if basic rules are observed and that these
included protection of property rights.
But to go further than reason alone, Pufendorf urged, the question of
what determines whether actions are right or wrong can only be settled by law,
and the basic natural law presupposes the will of a superior. “Natural law binds by virtue of the
divine will… Since God created our nature and fitted us with the capacities that
make social life possible, it must be his will that we should live in society
and observe those rules that are necessary for the existence of social life”
(Simmons 1989, 225).
The part of natural law that obliged individuals to do
good things for society allowed it more and more to take on the appearance of a
basically utilitarian society. Smith’s friend, David Hume, went as far
as to remove God from his whole conception of natural law. He then offered a justification for rules
of justice and property based on convenience or utility. This could well
29
have opened the door for the Benthamites, although
Hume’s position was ultimately not compatible with theirs. It is easy to conjecture, nevertheless,
that Adam Smith, who seemed less in haste to remove God from his total view of
society, would have been disturbed by the Utilitarians’ confident replacement of
God’s will by Bentham’s will, i.e., secular salvation via the simple principle
of maximum happiness.
30
Bethell, Tom. 1998. The Noblest Triumph.
Buchanan, J. M. 1978. The Economics of Politics.
Chadwick, Edwin. 1859. Results of Different Principles
of Legislation and Administration in
Crain, Mark, and Robert Ekelund. 1976. Chadwick and
Demsetz on Competition and Regulation. Journal of Law and Economics
19(1): 149-62.
Demtsetz, Harold. 1968. Why Regulate Utilities? Journal of Law and Economics 11:
55-65.
Eatwell, John,
Frankel Paul, Ellen. 1979. Moral Revolution and Economic Science.
ed. 1994. Property Rights.
Griswold, Charles, L. 1999. Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment.
Hobbes, Thomas. [1651] 1914. Leviathan.
Hume,David. [1752] 1985. Of Commerce. In Essays Moral and Literacy, ed.
Knight, Frank H. [1924] 1997. Fallacies in the Interpretation of Social
Cost. The Ethics of Competition.
Locke, John. [1690] 1991. Two Treatises of Government, ed.
P. Laslett.
31
Macey, Jonathan. 1994. Property Rights, Innovation, And
Constitutional Structure. In
Property Rights, ed. Paul Frankel,
Malthus, Thomas R. [1836] 1951. Principles of Political Economy. 2d ed.
Marx, Karl, and Friederick Engels. 1962. Selected Works, ed. V.
Adorakskyl. Prepared by the MarxlEngels Institute,
Mill, John Stuart. [1848] 1969. Principles of Political Economy,
ed. Sir William Ashley.
Mokyr, Joel. 1983. Why
Narveson, Jan. 1991. Property Rights: Original
Acquisition and Lockean Provisos. Unpublished monograph.
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia.
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph. [1840] 1994. What Is Property? ed. and trans.
D. R. Kelley and B. G. Smith.
Pipes, Richard. 1999. Property and Freedom.
Robbins, Lionel. 1952. The Theory of Economic Policy in
English Classical Political Economy.
Rosen, Shenvin. 1999. Potato Paradoxes. Journal of Political
Economy 107(6) part 2: 294-313.
Ryan, Alan. 1989. Property. In The Invisible Hand The
New Palgrave, ed. John Eatwell,
Simmons, N. E. 1989. Natural Law. In The Invisible Hand The
New Palgrave, ed. John Eatwell,
Smith, Adam. 1896. Lectures on Policy, Justice, Revenue
and Arms, ed. E. Cannan.
32
. [1776] 1976a. An Inquiry
into the Nature and Causes of the Weath of Nations, ed. R.H.
[1759] 1976b. The Theory of Moral Sentiments,
ed. D. D. Raphael and A. L. Macfie.
[1776] 1977. Lectures on Jurisprudence. Report
of 1762-3 LJ (A), Dated 1776 LJ (B), ed. R. L. Meek, D. D. Raphael and P. G.
Stein, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Teichgraeber, III. 1986. Free Trade and Moral
Philosophy.
Valcke, Catherine. 1989. Locke on Property: A
Deontological Interpretation. Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy
12(3): 941-1008.
Viner, Jacob. 1965. Guide to John Rae’s Life of Adam Smith.
Waldron, Jeremy. 1994. The Advantages and Difficulties
of the Human Theory of Property. In
Property Rights, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul.
Woodham-Smith, Cecil. 1968. The Great Hunger
33
i - This essay is a contribution to a forthcoming
symposium on property rights sponsored by the Hoover Institution. I wish to acknowledge constructive
comments from my colleagues: Keith Acheson, Ron Bodkin, and Steve
Ferris.
ii - Modern developments of the Lockean argument are
reviewed by Dean Lueck (this volume, XXX)
iii - And neither, of course, would Adam Smith for whom
mankind has a natural propensity to “truck, barter and
exchange.’
iv - Lord Robbins (1952) expressed the contrary view that
Smith’s Wealth of Nations was instead largely in the mold of
utilitarianism (a subject reviewed below).
v - Although the issue of limited liability drew most
attention in the middle of the nineteenth century, Smith was ahead of his time
in his comments on the central principal. He discusses it thoroughly, for instance,
when comparing joint-stock companies with private partnerships (copartneries in
Smithian language). Apart from the
nontransferability of shares in a partnership, Smith explains, it differed from
the joint-stock company in that “each partner is bound for the debts contracted
by the company to the whole extent of his fortune. In a joint-stock company, on the
contrary, each partner is bound only to the extent of his share” (Smith [1776]
1976a, 740). Smith also
acknowledged the principle of limited liability in his observation that the
greater part of the proprietors of the joint-stock companies received annual
dividends and enjoyed “total exemption from trouble and from risk, beyond a
limited sum” (Smith [1776] 1976a, 741). This facility encouraged many people to
become adventurers in joint-stock companies who would not otherwise hazard their
fortunes in a private partnership.
vi - Note that Smith’s public works are not what economists
call public goods because the price system does not break down and exclusion is
possible.
vii - It is true that the results of Mill’s lengthy
deliberations were often blurred by his adherence to doctrinaire Utilitarianism.
There seems no doubt, however,
about the genuineness of his overall
34
quest for truth.
His was a wide-ranging multidisciplined approach that referred not only
to economics but also to sociology, history, and recorded
custom.
viii - The Times believed that “the Celt is less energetic, less
independent, less industrious than the Saxon” (quoted in
ix - It should be noted, however, that Marx and Proudhon
were vehemently opposed to each other (Bethell, 1998,
114).
35
The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
September
2002