The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Gertrude Himmelfarb
In Defense of
the Two Cultures
The American Scholar, Autumn 1981, 451-463
NEXT YEAR WILL BE THE CENTENARY of Charles Darwin’s
death, and the occasion will, no doubt, be properly memorialized. But it will be a very different kind of
occasion from that celebrated twenty-two years ago on the anniversary of the
Origin of Species. In these
two decades the advances in genetics, paleontology, embryology, molecular
biology, and all the other sciences that are now thought to have a bearing on
evolution - many of which did not even exist in Darwin’s time-have made the
theory of Darwinism ever more remote from anything Darwin would have recognized
by that name. And if Darwinism, as
we know it, has come a long way from its origins, the social theories derived
from Darwinism have had an even more curious evolution. It is a situation another eminent
Victorian, Lord Acton, would have appreciated. “Ideas,” Acton wrote, “have a radiation
and development, an ancestry and posterity of their own, in which men play the
part of godfathers and godmothers more than that of legitimate
parents.”
The most familiar form of Social Darwinism is that
espoused, not by Darwin, but by Herbert Spencer: the idea that natural selection
functions, or should function, the same way in society that it functions in
nature; that the struggle for existence is the precondition for the emergence of
the socially fit as for the biologically fit; and that the best society is one
that approximates a state of nature, that is least regulated, least governed,
least controlled by extraneous forces or purposes - a laissez-faire society, in
short.
This view of Social Darwinism is unsatisfactory on
several counts. In equating a
laissez-faire society with a Hobbesian state of nature, it suggests that the
laws of the marketplace are nothing more than the laws of the jungle, and that
the ethos of a commercial society is a barely veiled legitimization
(sublimation, in the more sophisticated version of this theory) of violence.
Nor is the alternative genealogy
more satisfactory - that which derives Social Darwinism, not from Hobbes, but
from Malthus. It is no accident, it
is often said, that Darwin was inspired by that classic of laissez-faire, An
Essay on The Principle of Population. But
GERTRUDE HIMMELFARB is professor of
history at the Graduate School of the City University of New York. She is the
author of several books, including On Liberty and Liberalism: The Case of
John Stuart Mill. This essay is
adapted from a lecture originally delivered at Christ’s College,
Cambridge.
451
in one sense it was an accident, and an ironic one, for
Malthus’s Essay contained an explicit denial of the theory of evolution.
Refuting Smith’s theory of progress
as well as Godwin’s theory of perfectibility, Malthus insisted that both were
belied not only by the law of population but also by that law of nature which
assured the fixity of species. Just
as no amount of artificial breeding could produce a carnation the size of a
cabbage or a sheep with a head so small as to be “evanescent,” so no amount of
social reform could alter the natural condition of man. Darwin did, to be sure, take his clue
from the Essay, but it was only by turning Malthus on his head that he
derived a theory of evolution from the Malthusian struggle for
existence.
It is also curious that Darwinism should have appeared
on the scene at precisely the time when laissez-faire had lost its original
force. Even in the supposed heyday
of laissez-faire, as Lionel Robbins and others have demonstrated, the doctrine
was never as rigid and dogmatic as it is often made out to be. Certainly by the time Darwinism
established itself as the dominant scientific theory - the new orthodoxy, as
Huxley ruefully put it - England had accommodated herself to a pragmatic,
conciliatory, reformist temper far removed from the ideological rigors of a
Malthus or a Ricardo. Only in
America, where Darwinism entered under the auspices of Herbert Spencer, did it
take a laissez-faire form; in England, by yet another irony of intellectual
history, Darwinism was invoked in support of eugenics, a system of controlled
breeding designed to promote “national efficiency” - the very antithesis of
laissez-faire.
If Darwinism, then, in England at any rate, did not
inspire any upsurge of Social Darwinism in the familiar sense, neither did it
inspire the religious crisis of faith often attributed to it. Long before Darwin, religious orthodoxy
had been subverted by one intellectual current after another: by rationalism,
naturalism, utilitarianism, biblical criticism, and a host of evolutionary
theories dating back at least to Erasmus Darwin. Indeed, theories of evolution were
becoming so commonplace in Darwin’s own time that his great fear was not that
his own theory would be attacked but that it would be anticipated by someone
else (as, indeed, it very nearly was). In this intellectual atmosphere, the
effect of the Origin of Species was not so much to produce a crisis of
religious faith as to confirm and dramatize that crisis.
There was, however, a profound crisis produced by
Darwinism, and it was one that struck at the heart of Victorian England. If the Victorians had no dogmatic social
ideology, no binding religious faith, they did have a compelling, almost
obsessive faith in morality. As
revelation, ritual, and religious authority failed them, they clung all the more
firmly to the most categorical of all imperatives: an inner law, a sense of
rectitude
452
inherent in man which was presumed to be a sufficient
guide to private and public behavior, and which could be violated only at the
risk of inviting a retribution as certain as any devised by church or state.
George Eliot invoked this law when
she spoke of a “binding belief or spiritual law, which is to lift us into
willing obedience and save us from the slavery of unregulated passion or
impulse.” Pressed about the nature
of that belief, in view of her avowed religious disbelief, she made her famous
testament of faith: God is “inconceivable,” immortality “unbelievable,” but duty
is nonetheless “peremptory and absolute.”
These eminent Victorians who no longer believed in God
believed all the more in man; they deified man, not, like Feuerbach, to
“de-alienate” him, or, like Marx, to “socialize” him, but, like Comte, to
moralize him. Their “Religion of
Humanity” had only one dogma: that man was capable, by virtue of his
distinctively human nature, of every higher impulse, every moral and spiritual
quality, which had formerly required the inspiration and sanction of religion.
This was also the function of the
“intellectual clerisy” that Coleridge, and John Stuart Mill after him, made so
much of: to propagate and transmit this secular faith to future generations for
whom the conventional religious creeds would have become so attenuated as to be,
finally, vitiated.
When George Eliot was asked to define her idea of duty,
she said that it was the “recognition of something to be lived for beyond the
mere satisfaction of self, which is to the moral life what the addition of a
great central ganglion is to animal life.” What Darwinism did was to imperil that
moral faith by making the “great central ganglion” of animal life the nerve
center of human life as well. This
was the traumatic. effect of Darwinism:it did not so much displace God by man as
displace man by nature, moral man by amoral man. Malthusianism had earlier been accused of
de-moralizing man, making him a creature of primitive biological needs, needs
for sex and food that were beyond rational or moral control. But Darwinism de-moralized him further,
by making him a creature of nature who had evolved, slowly and painfully, from
the animal world, who still bore the traces of his origins, and was still
subject to that process of evolution, the struggle for survival, which had made
him what he was.
The Origin of Species, as contemporaries
immediately recognized, contained within it the seeds of The Descent of Man
published a dozen years later; and The Descent of Man, as was also
recognized at the time, was exactly what its title said: an account of the
descent of man - not, as some commentators: would have it, the ascent
of man. The book was,
literally, reductivist, designed to demonstrate that the intellectual and
spiritual faculties of human beings differed only in degree, not in kind, from
those of animals. Thus language was
interpreted as a more sophisticated
453
form of animal cries and gestures. The moral sense (which John Stuart Mill
had characterized as a uniquely human trait) became only another form of the
“sociability” exhibited by animals. And the religious impulse, the sense of
reverence and devotion, was said to be akin to the emotion displayed by Darwin’s
dog after Darwin had returned from his travels - in confirmation of which he quoted a
German professor who had written that “a dog looks on his master as a
god.”
While some moralists rejected Darwinism out of hand, and
others (Mill, for example) chose to belittle or ignore it, a few adopted the
strategy devised earlier by Tennyson. Appalled by a nature “red in tooth and
claw,” Tennyson looked to evolution as the instrument for the redemption of man,
the means by which man would rise above nature, would, as the famous lines went,
“Move upward, working out the beast, / And let the ape and tiger die.” Still others professed to find in nature
a providential order that was as moral as the divine providence it replaced.
This was the tactic taken at first
by T. H. Huxley. In a remarkable
letter written after the death of his young son, Huxley thanked Charles Kingsley
for his expressions of condolence, but assured him that he had no need of the
consolation of immortality since he was firmly convinced that the real world was
as moral and just as the supposedly immortal world. “The wicked does not flourish, nor
is the righteous punished. . .. The absolute justice of the system of things is
as clear to me as any scientific fact. The gravitation of sin to sorrow is as
certain as that of the earth to the sun.” Huxley reaffirmed that creed a quarter of
a century later in his lecture, “Science and Morals.” “The safety of morality lies neither in
the adoption of this or that philosophical speculation, nor this or that
theological creed, but in a real and living belief in that fixed order of nature
which sends social disorganisation upon the track of immorality, as surely as it
sends physical disease after physical trespasses.”
One suspects that by this time Huxley was desperately
reasserting a faith he no longer believed, for only two years later he reversed
himself, becoming the principal witness for the prosecution. Arguing against Spencer’s version of
Social Darwinism, the view that the struggle for existance was as essential to
progress in society as in nature, Huxley pointed out that even in nature
Darwinism did not preclude occasional regression, and that in human society even
the assurance of eventual progress did not justify the suffering and sacrifice
of one generation for the sake of another.
Having started this train of thought, Huxley could not
let it go. During the last
half-dozen years of his life he was as dogged in exposing the moral limitations
of Darwinism as he had earlier been - and, indeed, as he still was - in
defending its scientific validity. The most dramatic statement of his position
appeared in his famous Romanes Lecture of 1893,
454
“Evolution and Ethics,” which might more properly have
been called “Evolution versus Ethics.” Had Huxley had before him the text of his
earlier letter assuring Kingsley that “the wicked does not flourish, nor
is the righteous punished,” he could not now have repudiated that doctrine more
precisely and deliberately. “If
there is a generalization from the facts of life which has the assent of
thoughtful men in every age and country, it is that the violator of ethical
rules constantly escapes the punishment which he deserves; that the wicked
flourishes like a green bay tree, while the righteous begs his bread; that the
sins of the father are visited upon the children.” His conclusion was equally stark. The evolutionary or “cosmic process,” the
process of struggle and selection, which had made the world what it was, had
resulted in the survival of the “fittest” but not of the “best.” “The ethical progress of society depends,
not on imitating the cosmic process, still less in running away from it, but in
combating it.”
Under the terms of the Romanes lectureship, Huxley was
enjoined from any discussion of politics. But he could not resist one reference to
the “fanatical individualism” that sought to apply the principles of nature to
society. Nor could he be prevented,
the following year, from publishing a “Prolegomena” to his lecture in which he
made it clear that his objection was not only to the “fanatical individualist”
like Herbert Spencer, but also to the administrator, the socialist or
eugenicist, who would take it upon himself to try to create an “earthly
paradise, a true garden of Eden.” That “pigeon-fancier’s polity,” Huxley
suspected, was unattainable, but if it were attainable it would be a despotism
as ruthless as any known to man, for it would require a vigilant battle against
the instinct of self-assertion that was part of man’s animal
nature.
The effect, indeed the intention, of the “Prolegomena”
was to enhance the paradox inherent in the lecture. The ethical process was required to
counteract the evolutionary one, to restrain the combative instincts of man in
the interests of society and morality. But to the degree to which the ethical
process succeeded in that purpose, in impeding the operation of natural
selection, it was debilitating to society and a deterrent to progress. It was this tragic paradox that made
Huxley pronounce his lecture “a very orthodox discourse on the text, ‘Satan, the
Prince of this world.’
Long before Huxley had come to that Manichaean
conclusion, another kind of dualism had been advanced by the man who is often
described as the co-discoverer of the theory of natural selection, Alfred Russel
Wallace. When Huxley first read
Darwin’s theory, he said to himself, “How extremely stupid not to have thought
of that.” But one man had in fact
thought of it and had even written a brief account of it.
Wallace’s
455
place in the history of Darwinism has been a subject of
much controversy. To what extent
did he in fact anticipate Darwin’s theory? Can his brief essay claim priority over
the treatise Darwin had been working on for many years? Was there, as has recently been charged,
a conspiracy and cover-up on the part of the scientific establishment to deprive
Wallace of his just claim to fame? It is a dramatic story that all too
easily lends itself to a spurious melodrama. It has also had the unfortunate effect of
diverting us from what may be a more significant part of the story. For Wallace not only had the distinction
of being the first Darwinist; he was also the first renegade
Darwinist.
Even before Darwin had published his Descent of Man,
Wallace was controverting that book by arguing that evolution could not
account for the physical development of man’s brain, still less for his moral
capacity. In these respects man was
unique, not part of the animal kingdom, not a product of the struggle for
existence and natural selection. Wallace cited physiological and
anthropological evidence in support of his contention, but he also had good
political reasons to take the position he did. Long before he had become a scientist, he
had been a socialist, and he remained that while he pursued his other passions:
entomology chiefly, but also phrenology, spiritualism, and mesmerism. Where Huxley was initially attracted to
the theory of evolution because it placed man firmly in the world of nature and
made of him an “anthropoid ape,” Wallace was attracted to it because it gave
promise of elevating man above the world of nature and establishing his
uniqueness and his superiority over the ape. Eventually both felt obliged to separate
man from the evolutionary process: Huxley because he became convinced that man,
in spite of his animal nature, had the ethical duty to suppress that nature, at
least in part; Wallace because he was convinced that man’s nature was
qualitatively different from that of the animal, that man was naturally social,
moral, cooperative, pacific - a natural socialist, in fact. From quite different perspectives, then,
and for quite different reasons, Huxley and Wallace arrived at much the, same
point, a radical disjunction between nature and man, science and
morality.
For Huxley, and for Wallace too, that disjunction was a
measure of desperation, a strenuous attempt to keep Darwinism from being tainted
by Social Darwinism, to preserve the scientific integrity of the theory without
permitting it to encroach upon the domains of ethics and society. But there were other Victorians who had
no need of such strategies: those like Herbert Spencer who found no moral
dilemma in Social Darwinism, and those like Matthew Arnold who were so firmly
ensconced in a pre-Darwinian universe that the problem never
arose.
Arnold, one suspects - and I say this not derisively -
had a mind so
456
fine that no idea so gross as Darwinism could violate
it. Long before the Origin,
in a poem ironically entitled “In Harmony with Nature,” he had disposed of
the illusion that there could be any such harmony.
… Man hath all which Nature hath, but
more
And in that more lie all his
hopes of good.
Nature is cruel; man is sick of
blood:
Nature is stubborn; man would fain
adore:
Nature is fickle; man hath need of
rest:
… Man must begin, know this, where
Nature ends;
Nature and man can never be fast friends.
In 1882, delivering the Rede Lecture at Cambridge,
Arnold made it the occasion for an impassioned defense of humanistic education
against those, like his good friend Huxley, who had been urging a predominantly
scientific curriculum. Against
Huxley’s argument that “natural knowledge,” scientific knowledge, was the basis
of modern life and therefore essential for the mass of the people, Arnold
insisted that it was precisely the masses who urgently required a humanistic
education, an education which was not utilitarian in any vulgar sense but did
serve the practical purpose of elevating the spirit above the mundane
circumstances of life, enlarging the mind and life itself by putting us “into
relation with our sense for conduct, our sense for beauty.” The greatest of scientists might not
require that stimulus; Darwin, he recalled, had confessed that he had no feeling
for religion or poetry, that science and the domestic affections sufficed for
him. But the Darwins of the world,
Arnold suspected, were few. Most
people needed art and poetry, religion and philosophy” - the best that has been
thought and uttered in the world” - for the realization of their “true human
perfection.”
That Rede Lecture was in 1882, the year, as it happened,
of Darwin’s death. In 1959, at the
time of another Darwinian anniversary, Lord Snow delivered another Rede Lecture
to quite the opposite effect. This
was, of course, the famous lecture on “The Two Cultures.” Had Snow known of Arnold’s lecture-he
gave no indication that he did - he could not have controverted it more boldly.
Decrying what he took to be the
gulf separating the scientific and humanistic cultures, he made no secret of the
fact that he held the “literary intellectuals” responsible for it. Parochial in their interests and
complacent in their ignorance, they guilty of an “intellectual Luddism” that was
stultifying and disastrous for it prevented any serious attempt to solve the
most critical problem the time: the growing disparity between the rich countries
and the poor. That disparity could
only be reduced by a new industrial
457
which would do for the poor nations what the old
industrial revolution had done for the poor people of England. But a new industrial revolution required
a commitment to the new scientific revolution that was taking place, unbeknownst
to the literary intellectuals.
However deplorable the tone of the ensuing controversy
(which, it must be said, was not Snow’s doing), one cannot but be impressed by
the passion generated by it, in America as well as in England, suggesting that
Snow had hit a deep and sensitive nerve. Everything that could be said about that
lecture has assuredly been said - except perhaps to comment on what Snow did
not say. In all his talk
about scientific revolutions he never mentioned that earlier and at least as
momentous a revolution, Darwinism. This was all the more remarkable because
he delivered his lecture at the very time the centenary of the Origin of
Species was being celebrated. When Snow wanted to illustrate the
ignorance of science on the part of the literary intellectuals, he cited their
inability to define the second law of thermodynamics - the equivalent in
literary terms, he said, of never having read a play by Shakespeare. He later regretted that example. He thought it sounded comic, was too
easily parodied; he would have done better to have taken as his example
molecular biology. But even then,
Snow did not choose the theory of evolution as his example-perhaps because he
realized that literary intellectuals knew something of that theory, knew enough
to be skeptical of its application to social and political affairs, knew not
only something of the difficulty of applying it, but of the ambiguous, even
dangerous, effects of its application.
If Snow paid no heed either to Darwin or to Arnold, it
was perhaps because his own intellectual universe was curiously pre-Victorian.
Whatever else one may say about the
intellectual habits of the Victorians-their penchant for large categories and
bold antitheses: man and nature, morality and science, reason and faith - one
cannot charge them (although they have, of course, been so charged) with
complacency or undue optimism. On
the contrary, some of the most eminent, and certainly the most interesting, of
them came to their affirmations by way of doubt and fear; in this respect they
were the very model of the modern existentialist. Snow was rather in the tradition of the
Enlightenment, which took a more benign view of nature and reason, and which
conceived of progress in linear rather than dialectical terms, proceeding not by
conflict and negation but by the steady, cumulative advance of knowledge and the
steady, cumulative application of knowledge. Unlike Huxley, who was always fighting a
battle on two fronts-against those who denied the truths of science as well as
against those who denied all other truths, against the “fanatical
individualists” who brooked no interference in the free market of society and
the administrators who were all too ea
458
ger to refashion society according to their own designs
- Snow had a monolithic view both of the social problem and of the solution to
that problem.
The recent emergence of a new form of Social Darwinism
has brought with it a renewal of the Two Cultures debate, the latest version
being even more ill-natured than the earlier ones. Again one is reminded of the Victorians,
who were no mean polemicists, the disputes between Freeman and Froude, Kingsley
and Newman, presaging some of the more notorious academic feuds of our time.
But considering the momentousness
of the issue, the original Darwinian debate was far less acrimonious than might
have been expected, certainly less so than the current controversy over
Sociobiology. The highlight of that
earlier debate was the famous meeting of the British Association at Oxford in
1860, when Bishop Wilberforce asked whether it was from his grandfather or
grandmother that Huxley traced his descent from an ape, and Huxley retorted that
there was nothing shameful about having an ape for a grandfather; what was
shameful was a man who stooped to such cheap rhetoric. At that point, we are told, students
leapt from their seats and shouted, and one lady fainted and had to be carried
out. One wonders what those
Victorians would have made of a meeting a few years ago of the American
Association for the Advancement of Science, when Edward Wilson, professor at
Harvard and the leading proponent of Sociobiology, was greeted with shouts of
“Fascist,” “Nazi,” “Racist,” “Sexist,” and with a bucket of water thrown over
his head.
By now even the most benighted of Snow’s “literary
intellectuals” must be familiar with the basic tenets of Sociobiology: human
emotions and ethical ideas and practices have been programmed to a substantial
degree by natural selection over thousands of generations. These emotions, ideas, and practices have
evolved and been incorporated into our genetic constitution; and those traits -
altruism, for example - which seem to contradict the self-serving,
self-preserving function of natural selection, can be understood as a kind of
higher selfishness, a form of kin selection only once removed from the more
familiar kind of natural selection.
Because Sociobiology is so firmly rooted both in natural
selection and in genetics - because, as the very term suggests, it purports to
describe social behavior in terms of biology - it is obviously open to the
charge of being materialistic and deterministic. Indeed Wilson himself speaks of it as a
form of “scientific materialism.” Yet it is ironic to find this charge so
heatedly made by those who proudly subscribe to other forms of materialism and
determinism: historical materialism and environmental determinism. It is also ironic that those who accuse
the Sociobiologists of
459
being politically inspired are themselves frankly
political, a group of them, including some eminent professors at Harvard and
their graduate students, having formed an organization called the Sociobiology
Study Group of Science for the People, which issues the kind of manifestos and
collective letters appropriate to a political sect. One of those public letters accused the
Sociobiologists of providing a “genetic justification of the status quo,” and of
reviving the doctrine that had led to sterilization laws in the United States
and to the gas chambers of Nazi Germany.
Protesting against these “vigilante” tactics, as he
calls them, Wilson insists that it is not he but his critics who are
reductivist, that his theory does not equate the genetic is with the
ethical ought, if only because the two are presumed to be constantly
evolving in response to changing conditions. So far from licensing the old kind of
Social Darwinism, he has gone to great pains to establish a biological basis for
altruism and ethical behavior. At
times he seems to suggest that Sociobiology is not meant to provide a biological
basis for behavior but only to establish its biological limits -
limits within which individuals, groups, and societies have a large range of
freedom for ethical choices, but beyond which they cannot go without violating
their basic natures and ultimately destroying themselves. If this modest interpretation is
accepted, Sociobiology becomes, not an assertion of biological or genetic
determinism, but rather a refutation of social or environmental determinism, a
denial that human beings are infinitely malleable and can be totally refashioned
by changes in the environment, education, or social
system.
This modest reading of Sociobiology may be taken as a
defense of the individual not only against any systematic attempt to reprogram
him but against the more insidious pressures of society and culture. Wilson quotes Lionel Trilling’s memorable
defense of Freud, in which the biological basis of Freud’s thought, the idea of
a biological “given,” so far from being repressive, as is commonly supposed, was
represented by Trilling as a liberating idea - liberating because it prevented
man from being overwhelmed by an otherwise pervasive and omnipotent culture.
“Somewhere in the child,” Trilling
wrote, “somewhere in the adult, there is a hard, irreducible, stubborn core of
biological urgency, and biological necessity, and biological reason, that
culture cannot reach, and that reserves the right, which sooner or later it will
exercise, to judge the culture and resist and revise it.”
But just as Freud, it may be argued, pushed his
biological given beyond that limited and limiting role, so that it was not
simply a deterrent to the usurpations of society and culture but was a usurper
in its own right, a determinism as powerful as any other, so Wilson has larger
designs than he sometimes suggests. When he says that Sociobiology has
finally reconciled the Two Cultures in the “blending of biology and
the
460
social sciences,” he is obviously misstating the issue.
It is not science and social
science that are the antagonists of the Two Cultures debate, but science and the
humanities. The social sciences are
all too easily “scientized.” The
great source of resistance to science, as Snow recognized, is the humanistic
culture, which will hardly be reassured by some of Wilson’s assertions, such as
that “ethical philosophy must not be left in the hands of the merely wise,” or
that “the time has come for ethics to be removed temporarily from the hands of
the philosophers and biologicized.” The fact is that Wilson, like Snow before
him, does not want to reconcile science and ethics; he wants to subordinate
ethics to science, to put ethics into the “hands,” as he says, of the
biologists.
Wilson and Snow are on the same side of the great
divide, both champions of science against what they take to be the illusions,
obfuscations, or plain ignorance of nonscientists. But politically, programmatically, they
are on opposite sides. Snow assumed
that if only scientists were given their head, if only they occupied their
rightful place in the culture, the urgent social problems of the world could be
solved. When he later said that he
should have used, as an example of the egregious ignorance of humanists,
molecular biology rather than the second law of thermodynamics, he could not
have known that within a dozen years it would be molecular biology that would
inspire Sociobiology, and that the Sociobiologist would prove to be a far more
formidable opponent to his program of reform than the old-fashioned
humanist.
Snow had assumed that science, by virtue of its sheer
intellectual energy and creativity, would unleash an enormous force for good in
the world. What Wilson did was to
make of science itself a decisive check upon that force. Like the Malthusian checks on population,
or the “iron laws” of Ricardian economics, so Wilson’s genetics sets limits to
social change. “The genes,” he
writes, “hold culture on a leash.”
Where Snow’s image of the scientist recalls the classical conquistador
- audacious,
fearless, seeking new worlds to conquer - Wilson’s is reminiscent of
the bourgeois gentilhomme -
grateful to civilization (and evolution) for the goods it has bestowed on him,
cautiously adding to his estate but never jeopardizing it by any rash
speculation. This is hardly the
fascist the “People’s” scientists have made him out to be, but still far from
the brave adventurer Snow would have liked him to be.
Wilson’s is only one of many signals sent out recently
by scientists suggesting a retreat from the brave new world Snow had envisaged.
Almost every literary season
produces another book and another thesis citing new scientific (or
pseudoscientific) reasons for retrenchment and constraint: zero population
growth, zero economic growth, zero energy growth - the last, ironically, a
presumed consequence of that law of ther
461
modynamics which Snow had made a symbol of the
scientific imagination. But the
most ominous of the new scientific pessimisms is the retreat from science itself
- what might be called “zero scientific growth.”
One scientist commented on the Sociobiology controversy:
“The real question, the question that gives the debate its emotional power, is:
do we really want to know?” The “we” in that quotation refers not
to humanists but to scientists themselves. And that question has been raised not
only in connection with Sociobiology but with other subjects of scientific
inquiry touching upon race, sex, intelligence, even class. One recalls earlier qualms about atomic
research. But then it was nothing
less than the destruction of the world that was feared; now it is knowledge
about the world we have long inhabited and have long sought to
understand.
If some scientists are fearful of what they might learn
from science, if they are no longer certain they want to know what they
can know, the reason may be that they are burdened with too heavy a
responsibility. They no longer
think it their duty to know all they can know. They now feel called upon to anticipate
and judge the social and ethical consequences of their knowledge. It is as if they alone were the
repositors of practical knowledge; as if there were no philosophers to speak to
questions of ethics, or political philosophers (and, indeed, politicians) to
politics; as if there were no historians, economists, theologians, poets, and
artists to address other human and social concerns.
“Do we really want to know?”
Snow - and Huxley, and Arnold too - would have regarded that question as the ultimate trahison des clercs, an unforgivable failure of nerve, a know-nothingness far worse than anything with which the humanist could ever be charged. This failure of nerve comes not from the hubris of humanists or their refusal to accredit the culture of science, but from the unwitting hubris of scientists, from their assumption that the salvation of the world - or its damnation - rests upon themselves alone, that, as Snow remarked not once but twice in the course of his lecture, “the scientists have the future in their bones.” That remark must have sent a chill down the spines of those of his own generation who recalled other occasions when intrepid voyagers into the new worlds of fascism and communism discovered there the “wave of the future,” the “future that works.”The final irony is that just at this time, when the
scientific culture seems to be torn by dissension and self-doubt, when the
humanists might be forgiven some small expression of Schadenfreude, they
themselves-or at least the most articulate of them, who pride themselves on
being at the “cutting edge” of their disciplines-have chosen to capitulate.
That capitulation started a long
time ago, when modernism first afflicted the
462
arts, and when philosophy, the “mother of all the arts,”
modernized and “scientized” itself. Since then we have witnessed the attempt
of political philosophy to transform itself into political science, history into
social science, literary criticism into semiotics, and, most recently, theology
into semantics. In each case the
effect has been to “de-construct” those disciplines, to desocialize, dehumanize,
demoralize them by stripping them of any recognizable social and human reality.
It is as if some humanists have
decided that they too do not “really want to know” those truths about reality
which they once thought it their most important mission to
know.
This is the latest, most aggressive - and, one might
argue, regressive - phase in this history. It is an effort to unite the Two Cultures
analytically and linguistically, to create a language of discourse so recondite
and internal, so concerned with the mode of discourse itself, that other modes
of experience - history and politics, conduct and sensibility - are but dimly
perceived as through a glass darkly. If the history of this controversy
teaches us anything at all, it is that this strategy, too, will fail, that
reality will reassert itself, and that the culture - or two cultures - will once
again assume the task, however imperfectly and inconclusively, of interpreting
reality.
Reviewing this checkered history, even the most
unregenerate modernist might find himself looking back, with something more than
nostalgia, to those Victorians who addressed themselves so forthrightly to their
condition, who tried to salvage a sense of duty - a “peremptory and absolute
Duty” at that - from a world deprived of the traditional supports for duty, who
tried to create an ethic that trod a fine line between defying nature and
acquiescing in the imperatives of nature. They were as sensible as we are of the
unsatisfactory dualism of two cultures representing different modes of
experience and knowledge. But they
took refuge in that dualism, suspecting that the alternative was nothing less
than nihilism - the “abolition of man,” in C. S. Lewis’s memorable
phrase.
The Victorian ethos which managed to sustain that
precarious balance is, to be sure, irrecoverable, largely because the
evangelical impulse from which it derived is irrevocably lost. But the memory of it, the history of it,
is not lost. And that memory, of a
culture living on sheer nerve and will, the nerve to know the worst and to will
the best, may fortify us as we persist in our quest for some new synthesis that
will herald some brave - or not so brave-new world.
463