The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Harry Hillman Chartrand
April 2002
Herbert F.
Thomson
ADAM SMITH’S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE
(cont'd as Web 2)Introduction 212
I. Characteristics of Smith’s early work on scientific methodology 214
II. Motives for philosophical inquiries 215
III. The aesthetic element in Smith’s standard of judgment 219
Web 2
IV. Psychological presuppositions of Smith’s scientific method 222
IV. Psychological
Presupposition of Smith’s Scientific Method
Smith’s preoccupation with
taste as a main criterion by which to appraise a system of thought
derives in large part from his close association with David Hume (d. 1776).
Even during his student days at
Oxford, Smith bad been reprimanded for reading Hume’s Treatise of Human
Nature, 7 and at a much later period he speaks of Hume
as “by far the greatest philosopher of his age.” 8 Over a period of more than twenty
years, Smith and Hume had been accustomed to read each other’s manuscripts and
to discuss their conclusions prior to publication. Hume’s skeptical position with regard to
any certainty of knowledge about the external world is well summarized in the
following quotation: “Tis not solely in poetry and music we must follow our
taste and sentiment, but likewise in philosophy... reason is and ought only to
be the slave of the passions.” 9
Although Adam Smith’s views
of epistemology are revealed only by occasional comments, these suffice to
establish that at least in his earlier years he shared the skeptical
metaphysical views of Hume. These
include a belief that causal connections, however well substantiated they might
seem in practice, have their existence only in the imagination which attributes
external reality and necessity to certain configurations of events which
normally occur in a given sequence. Typical of Smith’s position is the
following passage from the History of
Astronomy:
Even we, while we have been
endeavouring to represent all philosophical systems as mere inventions of the
imagination, to connect together the otherwise disjointed and discordant
phaenomena of nature, have insensibly been drawn in, to make use of language
expressing the connecting principles of this one, as if they were the real
chains which Nature makes use of to bind together her several operations. Can we wonder then, that it (Newton’s
System) should have gained the general and complete approbation of mankind, and
that it should now be considered, not as an attempt to connect in the
imagination the phaenomena of the Heavens, but as the greatest discovery that
ever was made by man, the discovery of an immense chain of the most important
and sublime truths, all closely connected together, by one capital fact, of the
reality of which we have daily experience.
l
Smith’s view seems to be
that all causal relationships are metaphysical; the phenomena which they relate
are known empirically,
7. Rae, op. cit., p.
24.
8. The Wealth of
Nations, V, V, 3, p. 472.
9. David Hume, “Treatise of
Human Nature,” from Hume, Works (London: Green & Grose, 1898), II,
195-98.
1. History of Astronomy,
op. cit., pp. 189-90.
222
but any explanation of
these phenomena must make use of metaphysical concepts that reflect the outlook
of a given age and a particular school of thought. 2 Smith likens science or philosophy to the
effort of a person attending a stage play to imagine what stage effects behind
the scene might be the causes of the visible changes; or to the reasonings of
the spectator at an unfamiliar card game who undertakes to discover the rules of
the game merely by observing the cards which are played in silence. 3 This concept of a scientific system
as an imaginative construct intended to explain otherwise chaotic and discordant
phenomena bears a striking resemblance not only to the thought of David Hume,
but also to the views expressed in more recent times by Albert
Einstein:
Science is not just a
collection of laws, a catalogue of unrelated facts. It is a creation of the human mind, with
its freely invented ideas and concepts. Physical theories try to form a picture
of reality and to establish its connection with the wide world of sense
impressions. Thus the only
justification for our mental structures is whether and in what ways our theories
form such a link. 4
V. The Selected
Analogy as the Organizing Principle of a
Science
A student of the Scottish
literature of Smith’s time has stated that the definition of science then
required that “every system of science should possess, in order to be considered
scientific at all, a general principle capable of unifying and organizing the
whole mass of material. 5 Smith observes in the History of
Astronomy that such an organizing principle for a new science has generally
been selected as an analogy from some other art or science, in which a
new discovery has previously been made, and has been adapted to serve as the
“main hinge” for a related science. In this way, by a process of
cross-fertilization among the arts and sciences, each field has received new
impetus from the application of hypotheses which, on account of their
demonstrated usefulness in some other branch of knowledge, are employed
experimentally in this new science.
Individuals with the “extensive” outlook of philosophers are occupied
with the search for fruitful analogies which may be employed
as
2. There seems to be little
foundation for the position of certain American Institutionalists who would
picture the Newtonian outlook as absolutist. Smith’s Newtonian perspective was
altogether relativistic.
3. History of Astronomy
op. cit., pp. 74, 76-77.
4. Albert Einstein and
Leopold Infield, The Evolution of Physics (New York: Simon and
Schuster, 1938), p. 310.
5. Bryson, “The Comparable
Interests of the Old Moral Philosophy and the Modern Social Sciences,” in
Social Forces, Vol. 11 (Oct. 1932), p. 20.
223
organizing principles to
impart greater simplicity and accuracy to another science. Such were the contributions of
Copernicus, Descartes, and Sir Isaac Newton.
Adam Smith explains in
detail the characteristics of the fruitful
analogy:
Aristotle observes, that
the early Pythagoreans, who first studied arithmetic, explained all things by
the properties of numbers; and
Such an analogy, in
order to serve as an organizing hypothesis for a new system of science, must
satisfy several requirements. It
must be simple; it must be familiar; and it must be capable of uniting the
otherwise disconnected and chaotic phenomena of the field in which it is to be
applied. 7 The
propensity to wonder is natural to the human mind, and a further propensity
exists to seek for a solution to the problem which gave rise to the sentiment of
wonder; even a false answer, if concurred in by others, may provide satisfaction
to a person who was seriously troubled by the excess of wonder. 8
The discovery of an apt analogy
helps to restore tranquility to the mind which was once disposed to
wonder, and this is the chief end of philosophy.
9
6. History of Astronomy,
op. cit., pp. 82-84.
7. Ibid., pp.
106-9.
8. “If a person asserts
anything about the moon, though it should not be true, he will feel a kind of
uneasiness in being contradicted, and would be very glad that the person he is
endeavouring to persuade should be of the same way of thinking with himself.”
Smith, Lectures on Justice,
Police, Revenue and Arms, or,. cit., p. 171.
9. “Nothing can more
evidently show, how much the repose and tranquility of the imagination is the
ultimate end of philosophy, than the invention of the
224
VI. Smith’s “Moral
Newtonianism” and “Historical Aristotellianism”
Having selected an
hypothesis or organizing principle for a science, the philosopher then proceeds
to explain in terms of this principle the causal relationships that exist within
his field. The composed and
orderly system that is thus constructed will be an imaginary machine,
responding with maximum elegance and efficiency to the impulse of the great
hinge or the main principle, which must control all its divergent wheels and
motions:
Systems in many respects
resemble machines. A machine is a
little system, created to perform, as well as to connect together, in reality,
those different movements and effects which the artist has occasion for. A system is an imaginary machine invented
to connect together in the fancy those different movements and effects which are
already in reality performed. The
machines that are first invented to perform any particular movement are always
the most complex, and succeeding artists generally discover that, with fewer
wheels, with fewer principles of motion, than had originally been employed, the
same effects may be more easily produced. The first systems, in the same manner,
are always the most complex, and a connecting chain, or principle, is generally
thought necessary to unite every two seemingly disjointed appearances; but it
often happens, that one great connecting principle is afterwards found to be
sufficient to bind together all the discordant phenomena that occur in a whole
species of things. l
The imaginary machine that
is thus constructed must have as its main hinge an analogy or
hypothesis which is generally familiar, and which will impart greater
simplicity to the system:
Philosophy is the science
of the connecting principles of nature.... By representing the invisible chains
which bind together all these disjointed objects, (it) endeavours to introduce
order into this chaos of jarring and discordant appearances, to allay this
tumult of the imagination, and to restore it, when it surveys the great
revolutions of the universe, to that tone of tranquility, and composure which is
both more agreeable in itself, and most suitable to its nature.... No system,
how well soever in other respects supported, has ever been able to gain any
general credit on the world, whose connecting principles were not such as were
familiar to all mankind. 2
Two analogies appear
to dominate the arrangement of the materials in the Wealth of Nations. The first of these is Newtonian in
origin, and the second is adapted from the Aristotelian concept of Natural
Teleology, or of a Purposeful Nature. Adam Smith was one of the few economists
who experienced some success in integrat-
1. Ibid,
p.116.
2. Ibid,
pp.80-82.
225
ing a systematic analysis
of economic phenomena with an additional perspective of historical
development.
Sir Isaac Newton had
suggested, some decades before Smith, that his own mechanical perspective be
adapted to the social sciences, stating in the first edition of the
Principia:
I wish we could derive the
rest of the phenomena of Nature by the same kind of reasoning from mechanical
principles, for I am induced by many reasons to suspect that they may all depend
upon certain forces by which the particles of bodies, by some causes hitherto
unknown, are either mutually impelled toward one another, and cohere in regular
figures, or are repelled and recede from one another.
3
And at the end of the
Opticks,
Smith, in his two most
important works, appears to have taken his main hypothesis, or his analogy,
from the Newtonian principle of attraction. In both the Theory of Moral Sentiments
and the Wealth of Nations, the structure of the system is constituted
by an equilibrium between the individual and society. In the Theory of Moral Sentiments,
sympathy serves as the regulating force which sustains the divergent motions
of individuals and directs their courses within the harmonious pattern
established by nature. 5 This is noted by Hume, who, shortly
after the completion of this work, wrote to Smith: “I wish you had more
particularly and fully proved that all kinds of sympathy are agreeable. This is the hinge of your system,
and yet you only mention the matter cursorily.”
6
In the Wealth of
Nations, Smith’s ruling principle is “the desire of bettering our condition,
a desire which, though generally calm and dispassionate, comes with us from the
womb, and never leaves us until we go into the grave.” 7 Smith had explained in the
Theory
3. Isaac Newton,
Principia (Motte’s Translation), Preface.
4. Isaac Newton, Opticks, III, 1, qu.
3.
5. Various suggestions have
been made to explain the origin of Smith’s concept of sympathy, or of its use as
the organizing principle for his system of ethics. Smith himself acknowledges that he
employs the term sympathy in an unusual sense, more akin to the Greek
root-word than to the word in its modern usage. “Pity and compassion are words
appropriated to signify our fellow-feeling with the sorrow of others. Sympathy, though its meaning was,
perhaps, originally the same may now, however, without much impropriety, be made
use of to denote our fellow-feeling with any passion whatever.” Theory of Moral Sentiments, op. cit.,
I, I, i, p. 5. One can scarcely
fail to notice the mechanical aspect of Smith’s use of sympathy, as the force
relating the individual to society. The interaction between the main
characters and the chorus in Greek drama has also been pointed to as an
important source for Smith’s distinctive employment of the concept of
sympathy.
6. Rae, op. cit. p.
145.
7. Wealth of Nations,
op. cit., II, iii, p. 324.
226
of Moral Sentiments
that this desire, or any success in
“bettering our condition,” can do nothing to increase our happiness, because
“between one permanent situation and others, there was, with regard to real
happiness, no essential difference.” 8 Yet the desire for betterment is a
propensity or an instinct that is part of human nature, having been implanted
within man as an artifice of Nature and as part of the beneficent process of
illusion. Under the impulse
of this inescapable propensity, man is driven to creative activity and becomes
an agent of nature in her effort to keep society in motion and in a gradual
state of advance. 9 Self-interest imparts the
motion to society, and sympathy directs the motion within wholesome restraints.
The goal of this process appeared
to Smith to be greater refinement; that is, an increase in the variety,
the beauty, and the purposeful activity of human life. Man is thus led “to cultivate the ground,
to build houses, to found cities and commonwealths, and to invent and improve
all the sciences and arts which ennoble and embellish human life.”
1
This picture differs in two
important respects from the popular impression of the Wealth of Nations.
Self-interest is not extolled
for its own sake, but is considered as powerful human sentiment which might be
more effectively harnessed as an instrument of economic progress. And the goal of the economic system is
regarded more as progress in refinement and in creative activity than as
maximizing utility in a material sense.
The second of the two
analogies which dominate Smith’s works is adapted from the Aristotelian
concept of natural teleology, or of a purposeful nature. The distinction between final
causes and efficient causes, which was elaborated theoretically by
Aristotle, is employed in a more ambitious manner by Smith, as he distinguishes
between the purpose of nature in history, and the intentions of
individuals who are unaware of the true source or purpose of their instincts.
This Aristotelian distinction is
expanded by Smith into a deception, or illusion
theory.
Self-preservation, and the
propagation of the species, are the great ends which Nature seems to have
proposed in the formation of all animals.... Nature has directed us to the
greater part of these by original and immediate instincts. Hunger, thirst, and the passion which
unites the two sexes, the love of pleasure, and the dread of pain, prompt us to
apply those means for their
8. Theory of Moral
Sentiments, op. cit., III, iii,
p.
209.
9. Ibid., IV, I, p.
263. “it is well that Nature imposes upon us in this manner. It is this deception which rouses and
keeps in motion the industry of mankind.”
1. Ibid., IV, II,
pp. 263-64.
227
own sakes, and without any
consideration of their tendency to those beneficent ends which the great
Director of Nature intended to produce by them.
2
This analogy, taken
from the most commonplace observations in biology, is applied by both Smith and
Montesquieu to the field of history, where it is used to justify or to explain
their confidence that a progressive force exists in nature, apart from any
conscious human planning. 3 Whereas Grotius and Locke had
regarded nature in a static sense as a source of law, Smith’s view was that
nature operated as an active force. Smith’s typical reference is to “the
natural course of things,” or “the natural order of things.” Even when Smith refers to nature
as a source of law, he refers merely to the limitations which a constant
human nature or an established trend of history would impose upon the
legislator. 4 Nature
determines laws only by imposing limits, not by specifying detailed
enactments. Laws might be enacted
contrary to human nature or in opposition to the course of history, but the
enforcement of such laws will be difficult and will involve great social and
economic waste.
Both in his outlook on
historical change, and in his method of reasoning on historical subjects, Smith
resembles Darwin. In a famous passage in the Wealth of Nations, Smith
pictures the harmony and progress that are in evidence when the natural
human propensities are allowed to operate without artificial
restraints:
Every individual
necessarily labours to render the annual revenue of the society as great as be
can. He generally, indeed, neither
intends to promote the public interest, nor knows how much he is promoting
it.... He intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many other cases,
led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part, of his
intention.... By pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that of the
society more effectually than when he really intends to promote it.
5
2. Ibid., II, I, p.
109.
3. James Bonar,
Philosophy and Political Economy (New York: Macmillan, 1893) p.163. “There is no reason, on Adam Smith’s
philosophical principles, why human society should have been deliberately
contrived by its members any more than the planetary system consciously framed
by its own parts.”
4. Dugaid Stewart,
Account..., op. cit. liii. Mr. Hume adds that “the policy of ancient
times was VIOLENT, and contrary to the NATURAL course of things” — by which, I
presume, he means that it aimed too much at modifying, by the force of positive
institutions, the order of society, according to some preconceived idea of
expediency; without trusting sufficiently to those principles of the human
constitution, which, wherever they are allowed free scope, not only conduct
mankind to happiness, but lay the foundation of a progressive improvement in
their condition and in their character. The advantages which modern policy
possesses over the ancient, arose principally from its conformity, in some of
the most important articles of political economy to an order of things
recommended by nature.
5. Wealth of Nations, op. cit., IV,
II, p. 423.
228
The inclusion within his
system of a concept of a purposeful nature is a feature which distinguishes
Smith from the more mechanistic French economists, such as the Physiocrats - or,
in a later century, Leon Walras. Quesnay’s neglect of this dimension of
nature calls for a sharp criticism from Smith:
He (Quesnay) seems not to
have considered that in the political body, the natural effort which every man
is continually making to better his own condition is a principle of preservation
capable of preserving and correcting, in many respects, the bad effects of a
political economy, in some degrees both partial and oppressive.... If a nation
could not prosper without the enjoyment of perfect liberty and perfect justice,
there is not in the world a nation which could ever have prospered. In the political body, however, the
wisdom of nature has fortunately made ample provision for remedying many of the
bad effects of the folly and injustice of man; in the same manner as it has done
in the natural body, for remedying those of his sloth and intemperance.
6
VII. Adam Smith’s Purpose in the Wealth of
Nations
Most readers of the
Wealth of Nations experience some surprise at the discovery that Adam
Smith should have adhered, at least during his earlier years, to an aesthetic or
to a purely analytic ideal of science. The goals of the Wealth of Nations
seem utilitarian, and a rather materialistic concept of utility
appears to replace the stoic ethic which underlies the Theory of Moral
Sentiments. The transition in
Smith’s thought has led some scholars to conclude that Smith the analyst
had given way to Smith the reformer.
Leo Rogin, an outspoken
representative of the school of thought which would characterize the Wealth
of Nations as primarily normative or polemical, argues that Smith’s model
has been “quite frankly employed as (an argument) for specific programs of
reform. Obviously, however, the
validity of an argument must be appraised with reference to the issue to which
it is addressed.” 7 Rogin supports this contention by citing
a passage from a letter by Smith, representing the Wealth of Nations as
“a very violent attack… upon the whole commercial system of
6. Ibid.,
IV, IX p.
638.
7. Rogin, The Meaning
and Validity of Economic Theory (New York: Harper, 1956), p.61. Cf. Harlan McCracken, Keynesian
Economics (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1961),
p.48.
8. Scott, op. cit.,
p. 283.
229
In presenting this thesis,
Rogin maintains that to be genuinely scientific, a system must deal with “what
is” rather than with “what ought to be”; and that the “questions posed... should
be susceptible of solutions in which adequately trained people will ultimately
acquiesce.” The system that is
presented “must conform to the necessities imposed by persistently effective
matters of fact.” 9 Measured by these criteria, Rogin
concludes that the Wealth of Nations fails to qualify as an “objective”
or a “scientific” work, and must therefore be classified as “normative economic
theory.”
This characterization of
the Wealth of Nations is one which cannot be refuted completely or
easily, but which calls for some important qualifications. The first of these is that the
fundamental value judgment found in this work is the very broad proposition that
“consumption is the sole end and purpose of all production.”1 A misconception which must be dispelled
is that some other principle, such as laissez faire or competition
is Smith’s implicit norm or goal. These are, in fact, only subordinate or
instrumental elements in Smith’s system. His espousal of the material well-being
of the common people is the revolutionary normative judgment that distinguishes
the Wealth of Nations from the History of
Astronomy.
A more important
misconception regarding Smith’s purpose is that his adherence to a simple and
elegant system is an expression of contempt for the facts pertaining to
the subject. Actually, Smith’s own
account of his reasons for employing a simple system seem adequate and
convincing. To have incorporated
all observed facts within this field of study would have complicated the system
needlessly and would have been a methodological regression in terms of Smith’s
philosophy of science. Smith
therefore seemed willing to abstract from the random elements of history so as
to construct a system that would provide a simple representation of its
essential features. So decisive was
the impact of the Newtonian methodology, that Dugald Stewart remarks with
reference to Smith’s procedure: “It is of more importance to ascertain the
progress that is most simple, than the progress that is most agreeable to fact.”
2
Two other aspects of
Smith’s thought should also be taken into consideration as explanations of the
apparently ideal or metaphysical element in the Wealth of
Nations. Stewart makes special
mention of Smith’s curiosity regarding “the principles of human nature” and the
“circumstances of society.” Although Smith was
9. Rogin, op. cit.,
p.6.
1. Wealth of Nations,
op. cit., IV viii, 625.
2. Stewart, Account
..., op. cit., xxxviii.
230
not unwilling to abstract
from many of the features of society, he was insistent on giving more than the
usual emphasis to the logic of historical change and to the propensities of
human nature. He was not willing to
restrict his speculations to economic statics or to the purely mechanical
relationships of economic phenomena.
Thus we can see that the
statements of Smith’s early biographers fail to bear out Rogin’s claim that
Smith intended that his work be primarily normative in character. The apparently normative aspects of the
Wealth of Nations reflect Smith’s efforts to account for the trend of
historical development and to do justice to the fundamental principles of
psychology, 8 as well as to present a coherent system. Though it cannot be denied that Smith’s
“obvious and simple system of liberty” was thought of by certain statesmen of a
later age as a pattern or a blueprint, it must be recognized that Smith thought
of his own system as deducible from the realities of history, psychology, and
logic. The word inquiry,
which is used in the title of Smith’s work, suggests likewise that its
purpose was largely analytic. The
following quotation from the Account by Stewart traces more closely the
relationship of the Wealth of Nations to Smith’s earlier theory of
science.
In Mr. Smith’s writings,
whatever be the nature of his subject, he seldom misses an opportunity of
indulging his curiosity, in tracing from the principles of human nature, or from
the circumstances of society, the origin of the opinions and the institutions
which he describes. I formerly
mentioned a fragment concerning the History of Astronomy which he has left for
publication; and I have heard him say more than once, that he had projected, in
the earlier part of his life, a history of the other sciences on the same plan.
In his Wealth of Nations, various
disquisitions are introduced which have a like object in view, particularly the
theoretical delineation he has given of the natural progress of opulence in a
country; and his investigation of the causes which have inverted this order in
the different countries of modern Europe. His lectures on jurisprudence seem, from
the account of them formerly given, to have abounded in such inquiries.
4
It seems to have been
Stewart’s view that, while the subject matter of Smith’s Wealth of Nations
required some modification of the methods appropriate to astronomy, the
general concept of science presented in his early writings remained
substantially unchanged. 5
3. Ibid., liv. “The
great and leading object in his (Smith’s] speculations is, to illustrate the
provisions made by nature in the principles of the human mind, and the
circumstances of man’s external situation, for a gradual and progressive
augmentation in the means of national wealth.”
4. Ibid.,
xxxvi-xxxvii.
5. Stewart obviously does
not accept Rogin’s criterion of the agreement of scholars as a necessary
condition for scientific proof. Both Dugald Stewart and Adam Smith
believed that the collaboration of scholars was necessary for [the furtherance
of knowledge, but they thought of knowledge as a dynamic process where any
general consensus of scholars could not long persist. Ibid., xxxviii.]
bracketed section on p.232 of original
article.
231
Smith’s own statements in
the Wealth of Nations indicate likewise that he had not abandoned the
philosophical ideals of his earlier years. 6 These passages imply that he still
considered it the main task of philosophy to seek for the invisible chains which
unite and direct the visible phenomena of nature. Positivist scientists and philosophers
have been of the opinion that the phenomena are almost self-explanatory, and
that little more than a record of observations is necessary. Smith’s view, which is expressed in his
earliest writings, is that a science must explain causal relationships that are
exceedingly complex, and where more than one explanation may be offered that is
consistent with the observed facts. 7
That the subject of
political economy possessed a structure of its own, and that its investigation
required analytic methods distinct from those used in astronomy, Smith would be
the first to concede. The finding
which is of greatest interest, however, is that Smith himself saw a close
affinity between the method pursued by Newton in the study of astronomy, and the
method which would be the most fruitful in political economy or moral
philosophy. It was his intention to
select an analogy from the Newtonian astronomy, which might be applied as
an hypothesis in the fields of moral philosophy and political economy.
According to Smith’s own outline of
his material, the Wealth of Nations was to be a study in expediency,
while the Theory of Moral Sentiments was to be a study in propriety.
Differences may be observed in
Smith’s procedure in each of his works, attributable mainly to the great variety
of subject matter; yet each of these attempts to explain a complex mass of
phenomena by a few simple and familiar principles.
The features which stand
out in Smith’s early delineation of the philosophy of science, and which he
intended to apply in the Theory of Moral Sentiments and the Wealth of
Nations, are the following:
(1) A science must be a
unity. A science or an art must
grasp the essential features of its subject, and must present all parts
of
6. Wealth of Nations,
op. cit., V, I, p. 724.
7. Stewart, Account
. . ., op. cit., xxxviii. “When different theoretical histories are
proposed by different writers, of the progress of the human mind in any one line
of exertion, these theories are not always to be understood as standing in
opposition to each other. If the
progress delineated in all of them be plausible, it is possible at least, that
they may all have been realized; but whether they have been realized or not is
of little consequence. In most
cases it is of more importance to ascertain the progress that is most simple,
than the progress that is most agreeable to fact.”
232
this subject as a unity
that is at once elegant and harmonious. Adam Smith gives the main credit to
Descartes and to
(2) The formulation of a system of science occurs through a
social and historical process. Any
system of science takes shape gradually, through the common efforts of a
community of scholars, but it is never complete. Montesquieu may be regarded as the one
who emphasized this evolutionary principle most effectively, while the
Encyclopaedists did most to exemplify it.
(3) A science must be
understood in relation to the human mind and its constitution. It is a product both of the human mind
and of the phenomena that are studied, neither of which can be regarded as
passive or neutral in the creation of a science. Any recommendations that are made through
the procedures of political economy must also take account of the human mind and
its natural propensities. This is
the Humean thesis.
(4) A science, like a work
of art, is a means of communicating. It will necessarily be related to the
artistic taste of its creator, and it should be adapted to the understanding of
the public who accept it and respond to it. Smith seems particularly indebted to
D’Alembert and Rousseau, as well as to Shaftesbury and Hutcheson, for his
recognition of the aesthetic and rhetorical aspects of a system of
science.
233