The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
April 2003
Robert Skidelsky
The Mystery of Growth
Book Review
The Spirit of Capitalism: Nationalism and Economic Growth
by Liah Greenfeld,
Harvard University Press, 2003.
Lectures on Economic Growth
by Robert E. Lucas Jr., Harvard University Press,
2003
The
New York Review of Books
Vol. L, No. 4
March 13, 2001
28-31
Index
HHC – titling and index added
The question of what causes
economies to grow is theoretically interesting and practically important. If we could discover the secrets of economic
growth - what causes income per person to increase over time - we might be able
to make growth happen at will, abolishing poverty and creating a world of
universal abundance.
Until about three hundred years
ago, periods of economic growth had always been reversed, leaving long-term
income levels unchanged: the standard of living of a European agricultural
worker in the sixteenth century was little higher than it had been in Roman
times. In his Essay on Population (1798)
the Reverend T.R. Matthus explained why. Whenever food supply grew, population grew,
but even faster. This meant that income
per head - or food per person - was constantly being forced back toward
subsistence levels. But from the late
seventeenth century onward “perhaps for the first time in... history... both
the Dutch and the British economies succeeded in increasing the per capita income
of a growing population despite the continued pressure of diminishing returns
in agriculture.” [1] Malthus’s
population theory was by then explaining only past history. In the century after he wrote, emigration to
the Americas, the Industrial Revolution, and falling birth rates banished, or
at least postponed, his “problem” in the Western European countries of the
world. Wealth could be made to grow
faster than population.
Adam Smith, the founder of
scientific economics, was the inventor of growth theory. The question he asked in The Wealth of
Nations (1776) was: What laws, institutions, and public policies does a
society need to experience economic growth? Smith had no doubt that “little else is
requisite to carry a state to the highest degree of opulence from the lowest
barbarism, but peace, easy taxes, and a tolerable administration of justice;
all the rest being brought about by the natural course of things.” [2] Over fifty years later, and well into the Industrial Revolution,
John Stuart Mill listed three requirements for the “less civilized and
industrious” nations to catch up with the advanced ones: better government and
property laws; the “decay of superstition” and “growth of mental activity”; and
hospitality to “foreign arts” (technology) and foreign capital. [3]
Behind these economists’
assertions lay the thought that economic growth is natural because, except for
some monks and other ascetics, “love of gain” is universal. The main “obstacle to growth” was what Karl
Marx called “ancient and venerable prejudices.” However, these would yield to scientific
knowledge. In this view, no change in
human motives is needed to explain economic growth, merely a change in
the circumstances in which the self-interested motives are translated into
action. Prescriptively, “scientific” economics
tries to tell you what the required circumstances are.
However, the economists’
accounts left one huge question unanswered: Why has Western civilization been
so much more successful than any other in removing the obstacles to economic
growth? An equal love of gain cannot
explain the highly unequal patterns of growth we have in fact observed. Sociologists argued that for growth to happen
a prior shift of cultural values had to occur: the obstacles to growth were not
prescientific prejudices, but cultural systems that
frowned on moneymaking.
According to the sociologist
Max Weber, this cultural shift was accomplished - uniquely in
Western Europe - by
Protestantism. Protestanism
was the carrier of the “spirit of capitalism.” Protestant countries, sociologists argued,
developed a special aptitude for moneymaking. This explained their economic success; the
lack of a Protestant ethic explained the failure of others. Seeing growth as culturally disruptive,
sociologists were more sensitive to its costs.
And they were less optimistic than were economists about the benefits
growth would bring. In the sociological
tradition, it is the obsession with growth, not resistance to it, which is
irrational.
Post-1945 growth experience
has given economics the edge over sociology. The classic sociological growth theories, associated
with Max Weber, R. H. Tawney, Werner Sombart, and the Harvard scholar Alexander Gerschenkron, date from a time when Europe and its
offshoots offered the only material for growth stories. So it made sense to explain economic growth
according to Europe’s exceptional, not readily reproducible, characteristics. This conclusion was,
if anything, reinforced by early-twentieth-century attempts to force growth on
the non-Protestant world by means of centrally directed “development strategies.”
These produced either monstrous
aberrations, as in Soviet Russia and Communist China, or monuments to
inefficiency and corruption, as in India, sub-Saharan Africa, and much of Latin
America.
However, while these growth
strategies were being tested, the Japanese economic “miracle” provided materials
for an alternative story of development, based on export-led growth in a
liberalizing world economy. Japan’s
success was the first real breach in the theory of European exceptionalism.
In the 1970s and 1980s it was closely
followed by a small cluster of East Asian “miracles” in South Korea, Taiwan,
Singapore, and Hong Kong. Since 1960, according to Robert Lucas, the “entire human race [has
been] getting rich, at historically unprecedented rates.” This seemed to vindicate the insight of the
classical economists that, if Western standards of good government prevailed,
“love of gain” would do the rest.
The two books under review,
one written by the political sociologist Liah Greenfeld, the other by Nobel Prize-winning economist
Robert Lucas, reflect the two main traditions for thinking about growth. To Liah Greenfeld, the explanation of growth belongs to the
“history of ideas and the sociology of culture.” For Lucas, growth is what happens automatically
as knowledge accumulates.
Greenfeld denies the validity of naturalistic explanations of
human behavior. Her key argument is that
the emergence of the modern economy has to be understood “as a problem in the
cultural construction of reality.” Specifically, a desire for “continuous
economic growth” is not natural for human beings, and for most of history it
has been absent. “I am asking,” Greenfeld writes, “why the historically exceptional inclination
for ever-increasing gain... became defined, on the level of the individual, as
rational self-interest... and on the level of society, as common good and
paramount collective interest.” The
harnessing of greed to efficiency and ethical goals requires an explanation - a
Factor X, as Lucas calls it.
Max Weber’s Factor X was Protestantism. The Protestant ethic was required to convert
natural, haphazardly satisfied greed into purposeful frugality. Calvinism abolished the distinction between
the sacred and profane, generalizing the ascetic ideal of the monastic orders
to secular life. Personal asceticism, in
turn, favored the accumulation of capital.
In this explanation of the origins of capitalism, Adam Smith’s engine of
accumulation – frugality - arises not from a natural desire for more wealth but
from a heightened concern for one’s immortal soul. But the rationality entailed by this concern
became in time detached from the goal of salvation it was designed to serve. Capital accumulation became an end in itself.
Greenfeld accepts the need for a Factor X. Weber was right to see that the “spirit of
capitalism” required a new morality. But
the mechanism that brought this about, she argues, was nationalism, not
Protestantism. By the seventeenth
century, nationalism had emerged in Britain as “the cognitive and ethical
framework which gave
[1] Douglass C. North and Robert Paul Thomas, The
Rise of the Western World: A New Economic History (Cambridge University
Press. 1973), p. 2.
[2] John A. Hall, Powers and
Liberties: The Causes and Consequences of the Rise of the West, (Penguin,
1985), p. 141.
3, John Stuart Mill, Principles of Political Economy, Book 1,
Chapter 13 (London, 1871), pp. 236-237.
28
meaning to reality” - that is, consciousness of being a
nation is what inspired the British to build up their wealth. Nationalism freed money from its subordination
to religion and turned the accumulation of wealth into the summum
bonum of life.
Britain’s economic success
made it a political superpower. This
stimulated “many a reactive nationalism” in other countries, their focus on
economics “greatly contributing to the formation of the modern ‘economic
civilization.” Without nationalism,
economic growth would have stopped earlier, the motives recognized by
economists being insufficient to explain the sustained hunger for wealth. Greenfeld cites
Holland as a counterexample of an economy which, after a great spurt, declined
in the seventeenth century because it lacked a national consciousness.
Greenfeld believes that nationalism “necessarily promotes the
type of social structure which the modern economy needs to develop.” Because it is, at least in principle,
egalitarian - membership in the nation confers equal rights on all - it
encourages social mobility, frees labor, encourages market forces, and gives
prestige to hitherto disparaged groups like merchants. Nationalism can also set up a system of
international competition, committing societies “which define themselves as
nations to a race with a relative and therefore forever receding finishing
line.” When international competition
includes the economy, this presupposes a commitment to constant growth. “In other words, the sustained growth
characteristic of modern economy is not self-sustained; it is stimulated and
sustained by nationalism.”
Greenfeld’s book can be read both as an attack on economists and
as a debate within sociology. Against
the economists, she makes the good, though scarcely original, point that economic
behavior is shaped by cultural values, and that
growth-resistant cultures cannot simply be explained as products of ignorance
and superstition. Within sociology, the
question is whether nationalism offers a better explanation for economic growth
than does Weber’s Protestant ethic. I
think not, for three reasons.
First, it is far from clear
how nationalism is supposed to produce the individual behavior necessary
for economic growth. Weber’s theory of
the Protestant ethic postulates a functional relationship between frugality
(self-denial) and capital accumulation (though it was Keynes who famously
remarked that “mere abstinence is not enough by itself to build cities or drain
fens.” [4]) Why should nationalism make people more systematically
frugal or, for that matter, enterprising - as opposed to more systematically
warlike? Greenfeld
herself admits it does not have to. Military
conscription is as much a product of nationalism as is universal suffrage.
Secondly, the Protestant
ethic, being transnational, at least explains why growth happened in some
countries, whereas nationalism doesn’t. Greenfeld treats the emergence of nationalism in one
country after another as “an unconnected series of historical accidents.” It is therefore incapable of explaining
economic growth in any country but that in which the nationalism occurs. Apart from the vague musings I have mentioned
on “reactive nationalism” (itself not original) no plausible mechanism is
offered by which growth is transmitted from one “nation” to another.
Thirdly, nationalism hardly
explains the origins of British capitalism. As a political doctrine, it dates from the
French Revolution; but England had developed the core institutions of a
capitalist market economy long before this. To save her argument, Greenfeld
has to say that nationalism was “the preponderant vision” of British society by
1600. But this is nonsense, since, far from
being egalitarian and democratic, England in 1600 was a hierarchical society,
ruled by a hereditary monarch who held down the non-English parts of his
dominion by force. What is true is that
by 1600, the English had developed a strong sense of national identity (not
nationalism). This was embodied in the
“patriotic” Tudor monarchy, and underpinned by the sense of being a Protestant
nation locked into semipermanent war with the
Catholic powers of Spain and (later) France.
Greenfeld is right to see a link between national feeling and
economic growth, but the connection has to be made in a historical context, and
this she fails to provide. Historically
minded sociologists have located the political foundations of capitalism in the
failure of Europe to develop a single center of power after the collapse of the
Roman Empire. [5] From the ruins
of the Roman imperium emerged feudalism, a
fragmented, overlapping system of jurisdictions and states held together by
Christianity; parts of that system had by the early sixteenth century coalesced
into intensely competitive national monarchies. Feudalism checked arbitrary rule, leaving
space for the growth of free cities, pan-European markets, and private property
rights; military competition between states stimulated national feeling and
turned the attention of rulers to augmenting the stock of national wealth,
because of the close connection between wealth and power. Thus national identity and the growth-minded
“spirit of capitalism” can be seen as joint products of European rivalry among
states. In economic jargon, nationalism
is a dependent, not an independent, variable. It is connected to growth through the
competition of states. Even so, we are
left with no explanation of why some nationalistic states, like Russia, failed
to develop the “spirit of capitalism.”
Weber’s Protestant ethic hypothesis remains superior for explaining why
the growth experience of parts of Europe diverged from elsewhere.
Greenfeld tries to demonstrate her key claim, that economic
rationality on its own is incapable of generating a commitment to “continuous”
growth without the support of nationalism, by
4. John Maynard Keynes, A Treatise on Money, Vol.
2 (Macmillan, 1930). Reprinted in The
Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, Vol. 6 (Royal Economic
Society, 1971), p. 132.
5. See for example Jean Baechler, The Origins
of Capitalism, translated by Barry Cooper (St. Martins, 1976), and
Hall, Powers and Liberties.
29
reference to Holland. Holland
had a hundred-year “golden age,” roughly between 1580 and 1680, then declined. Greenfeld writes: “The Dutch of the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries did not choose to become modern. They did not make a fetish of ever-continued
growth... They remained economically rational... In other words, they were not
a nation.” There is a simpler
explanation for Dutch “retardation”: Britain struck at the heart of Dutch
prosperity with the Navigation Act of
1651, which excluded Dutch ships from carrying any goods that went through
British ports. “What we want is more of
the trade the Dutch now have,” said the Duke of Albemarle. In any case, the Dutch did not do so badly
even after their “decline” started. They
were overtaken by the British, but the Dutch population continued to rise at an
increased income per capita - that is, the Malthusian population cycle was
broken. In 1820, Holland was just behind
England as the richest country in Europe in per capita terms - not a bad record
for a country lacking an “orientation” to sustained growth.
To turn from Greenfeld to Lucas is like emerging from an old curiosity
shop into a modern office. There is no
clutter. Lucas is an economist’s
economist. Much of his work is mathematical
- inaccessible to the nonspecialist reader. His method is to construct “a mechanical, artificial
world, populated by... interacting robots..., that is capable of exhibiting
behavior the gross features of which resemble those of the actual world…” This is not a sales pitch for a wide readership.
However, with great effort, even a nonspecialist reader can get some benefit from his spare
volume of lectures, since Lucas provides a lucid introduction and nontechnical summaries of his main ideas. And such a reader may even come to feel the
excitement of Lucas’s passionate quest for the solution to the mystery of
growth. “If we know what an economic
miracle is,” Lucas writes, “we ought to be able to make one.”
The first tour chapters of
the book are made up of lectures given in the years between 1985 and 1997,
beginning with the Marshall Lectures, “On The
Mechanics of Economic Development,” delivered at Cambridge, England. These
introduce the main theme: Lucas’s dissatisfaction with conventional growth
theory and his search for an alternative capable of giving a more satisfactory
explanation of economic growth - one not just able to explain the actual growth
experience of the modern world, but to do so by showing how it is based on
rational individual behavior.
In the traditional (i.e.,
post-1940s) growth models, economic growth was associated with the accumulation
of physical capital - plant and equipment. The more capital a given population had, the
higher its standard of living would be. But
physical capital (like land) is subject to diminishing returns: the more
capital there is, the less each additional unit of it adds to output. This suggested that all countries would
converge on the same growth path: countries with less capital per person would
grow faster, those with more would grow slower, and, once they had the same
ratio of capital to labor, they would all end up growing at the same rate. What this rate would be depends on what happens
to population and technology.
Lucas rejected this theory
on two grounds. First, it failed to
explain the actual divergence of growth across countries, with the richest
countries now having twenty-five times more income per person than the poorest
ones. Secondly, it made long-run growth
depend on two “exogenous,” i.e., unexplained, factors: population and
technology. Economists are always
uncomfortable with variables that their models cannot explain.
Lucas’s alternative is
known to economists as “endogenous growth theory” - in which growth is
explained within the theory and does not depend on something happening outside
it. Endogenous growth theory distinguishes
between physical and human capital. Human
capital is the skill and knowledge embodied in the labor force. A person’s human capital is measured by the
present market value of the increase in productivity conferred on that person
by the acquisition of skills or qualifications. (For example, the higher’ lifelong earnings
accruing to a college graduate as compared to a blue-collar high school dropout
are a measure of the increase in human capital associated with a college
education.) Unlike physical capital,
however, the accumulation of human capital for the whole society is not subject
to diminishing returns, but leads to increasing returns. This is because human capital formation is a “social
activity, involving groups of people in a way that has no counterpart
in the accumulation of physical capital.” (Italics in the original.)
That is, it has external, or spillover,
effects. We learn from each other: in
acquiring a skill each member of a group raises not just his own productivity
but the skill level, and thus average productivity, of the whole group, whether
in a factory or in an office.
This approach allows Lucas
to offset the diminishing private returns resulting from the accumulation of
physical (and human) capital with increasing social returns resulting from the
improvement of human capital. There is
no need for diminishing returns to total capital formation, both physical and
human. If this is so, initial inequalities
between countries in income levels can persist. Endogenous growth theory improves on
traditional theory in two ways. It
explains the divergence of growth experience over long periods of time, and it
“endogenizes” technological progress - explains how
it happens within the growth model.
What this kind of model
cannot explain, however, is the phenomenon of “catch-up,” particularly the East
Asian economic “miracle” (although it is now looking rather tarnished). How was it that a group of countries in East
Asia managed to achieve Western income levels, starting with much lower human
capital? Lucas wrestles with this
question for three chapters of his book. He makes some progress. In his 1991 lecture “Making a Miracle,” he
assumes that some of the spillover effects of human capital accumulation in any
one country are worldwide: “Productivity-related knowledge is pictured as
though it floated across national boundaries, like acid rain or volcanic ash.” Unfortunately it does not float to all places.
Accordingly economic growth rates can
still diverge greatly between nations. Those
nations lucky enough to be watered by the rain of productivity-related knowledge
grow more quickly. Others, unaffected by
this “volcanic ash,” remain stagnant. Why
this uneven spread?
In his chapter “The
Industrial Revolution: Past and Future,” Lucas turns to population as the clue
to the riddle. Today’s growth theories
assume that technological change expands only incomes; Ricardo and Malthus assumed that its main effect was to increase
population. To understand why some
countries and not others have joined the modern world we have to combine both
theories: “That is, we need to discover a more general theory of which the two
we now have can be seen as special cases…”
This general theory follows
Nobel Prize winner Gary Becker in treating decisions about how many children a
family should have as economic decisions. A family that wants to take advantage of an
increased return to investment in knowledge does so by reducing its number of
chi1dren so as to devote more resources to each child. For individual family decisions to affect the
growth of a nation enough families must change their views about the possibilities
for the future to “reduce fertility across economic classes.” The historical catalyst for this “change of
view” was the Industrial Revolution. As
factory work replaced agricultural labor, it made more sense for households to
invest in quality rather than quantity of labor. Fertility declined and voluntary mass
education started.
Lucas cites that “great
novel of economic development,” V. S. Naipaul’s A
House for Mr. Biswas, to illustrate
30
his theme. Born in
rural Trinidad, the grandson of immigrants who came to Trinidad as indentured
servants, Mo-hun Biswas
becomes a journalist in Port-of-Spain. By
the time he dies, his oldest son, Anand, is a
scholarship student at Oxford. “Between Anand and Mohun Biswas’s parents is the entire 25-1 difference between
living standards in India and living standards in Western Europe and the United
States.” By incorporating population as
well as technology into his model, Lucas has generalized his theory of economic
development. All that is needed for it
to happen is that “people must experience changes in the possible lives they
imagine for themselves and their children.”
Lucas’s conclusion, as we
can see, is diametrically opposed to Greenfeld’s. Greenfeld explains
economic growth by European (and Japanese) exceptionalism,
in particular the rise of nationalism. Because
it is historically contingent, the search for the “universally applicable
formula of economic growth is a wild goose chase; it can never be found.” Lucas disagrees. By abstracting from historical contingency he
can focus all his attention on the universal, long-run consequences of the
Industrial Revolution - which, unexplained, is his own Factor X. “Full participation in the economic benefits
of the industrial revolution,” Lucas writes, “is open to countries of all races
and cultural backgrounds.” He believes
that the enormous inequality of the postwar period is at its all-time peak, and
will decline in the future until something like the more egalitarian relative
incomes of 1800 are restored. Nothing
but “unstable domestic politics and mercantilist trade policies” - surely a
major qualification - can keep the rest of the world from “follow[ing] Japan.” And all
this is an immense boon. “The legacy of
economic growth that we have inherited from the industrial revolution is an
irreversible gain to humanity, of a magnitude that is still unknown.... The
legacy of inequality, the concomitant of this gain, is a historical transient.”
Lucas’s book is an
outstanding intellectual achievement. But its propositions are likely to be fully
persuasive only to those who already inhabit his mental universe. These people will applaud his heroic attempt
to derive the history and prospects of growth solely from attempts by
households to maximize their well-being. Others will object to the use of
overambitious, oversimplified generalizations to explain the complex behavior
of the real world. The central question
is: How long does Lucas expect his universal “catch-up” to take? There has been very little change in the ranking
of nations in the last two hundred years - just an enormous increase in inequality.
And Mr. Biswas’s
case is hardly typical. Members of his
family moved from India to Trinidad to England in three generations. Most families remain stuck where they
started. In view of this, the question
posed by Max Weber is not so easily disposed of. Suppose one succeeds in implanting Western
institutions in traditional societies. How
long before the implants take?
Lucas avoids any discussion
of public policies that will quicken growth or reduce poverty, beyond the need
for governments to dispense birth control information and to finance education.
His conception of human capital also
seems excessively narrow. If we take
what people used to call “character” as an important aspect of human capital
and “trust” as an external effect of “character,” what are we to conclude about
the size of these external effects today? Human capital can’t just be measured by
“skills.”
Occupying different
intellectual terrains, both Greenfeld and Lucas help
our thinking about economic growth. Greenfeld raises the question of whether an obsession with
growth is rational. The problem is not
to explain the desire of people to improve their lot, but the organization of
modern societies for continuous growth. It
is easy enough to understand why people in poor countries should wish to get
richer. They have the examples of rich
and powerful countries before them. It
is not so clear why the already rich should want to go on getting richer.
An
earlier generation of economists assumed that
as people became more efficient at satisfying their wants, they would - and
should as rational agents - work
less and enjoy life more. This view
seems to have been replaced by the view that human wants are insatiable. We are constantly being urged to work harder,
and save more, in order to satisfy wants continuously being created by
advertising, whose main effect is to enlarge the human capacity for envy. The evidence, moreover, suggests that
increasing real income fails to make citizens of rich countries happier. In other words, Western societies remain
organized around an objectless disposition to continuous wealth-creation - something
that did not exist in earlier times, and that remains, in some sense, peculiar
to them.
Lucas’s discussion raises the question of what kind of public policies are
needed for countries to break out of poverty. He himself seems to believe that little in the
way of government intervention is required to carry us all to Nirvana. But this is not an inescapable conclusion of
endogenous growth theory. The
possibility of countries escaping poverty depends heavily on government
policies with respect to taxation, law and order, education, health care,
transport and other infrastructure, public services, intellectual property,
regulation of international trade and financial markets, and so on. The Harvard economist Robert Barro acknowledges that “government therefore has great
potential for, good or ill through its influence upon the long-term rate of
growth.” [6] The problem is that the governments of many poor
countries lack the social capacity to implement appropriate policies. For those not prepared to wait as long as
Lucas is, endogenous growth theory prepares the intellectual ground for a new
form of interventionism, in which Western countries take over some part of the
development of “human capital” in the poorest countries. The current language of “failed” states is the
embryonic language of the new imperialism.
6. Robert J. Barro, Determinants of Economic
Growth: A Cross-Country Empirical Study (MIT Press, 1997), p. 6.
31
The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
April 2003