The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
April 2003
Steven Shapin
Here and Everywhere: Sociology of Scientific Knowledge
Annual Review of Sociology
Volume 21, 1995, 289-321.
Index
Sociology of Scientific Knowledge and the Academic
Culture
SSK and the Forms of Cultural Inquiry
Situated Knowledge and Its Travels
Despair and Decorum: SSK Dissolved?
The sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK) is one of
the profession’s most marginal specialties, yet its objects of inquiry, its
modes of inquiry, and certain of its findings have very substantial bearing
upon the nature and scope of the sociological enterprise in general. While traditional sociology of knowledge asked
how, and to what extent, “social factors” might influence the products of the mind,
SSK sought to show that knowledge was constitutively social, and in so doing,
it raised fundamental questions about taken-for-granted divisions between
“social versus cognitive, or natural, factors.” This piece traces the historical development
of the sociology of scientific knowledge and its relations with sociology and
cultural inquiry as a whole. It
identifies dominant “localist” sensibilities in SSK
and the consequent problem it now confronts of how scientific knowledge
travels. Finally, it describes several
strands of criticism of SSK that have emerged from among its own practitioners,
noting the ways in which some criticisms can be seen as a revival of old
aspirations toward privileged meta-languages.
There is no shortage of
reviews and assessments of the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK). Most have been written by critics or by
participants meaning to put their special stamp on a contentious and splintered
field. [1] I too am a participant: My views about what the field
is, and ought to be, are strongly held; they have been canvassed elsewhere, and
they will be unavoidably evident in this survey. Yet my purpose here is less to score points
than to offer a critical survey
1. Special note should be taken of Lynch (1993:Ch
2-4), which, while it argues a vigorous case for the virtues of ethnomethodology, is a detailed critical survey of recent
trends in the social studies of science.
289
of how SSK developed, and continues to develop, in
relation to sociology, and to make the leading concerns of the field rather
more comprehensible to sociologists in general than they have been. For this specialty, such a purpose is not
banal, as neither the place of SSK in the sociological culture nor its
implications for the future of sociology - especially social theory - have been
adequately canvassed before. [2] The “here and
everywhere” of my title refers at once to the problematic place of SSK within
academic sociology and to a central problem it has generated and now confronts
- how to interpret the relationship between the local settings in which
scientific knowledge is produced and the unique efficiency with which such
knowledge seems to travel.
Sociology of Scientific Knowledge and
the Academic Culture
SSK must count as one of
sociology’s notable recent successes. Emerging
not more than 25 years ago, in the 1970s and early 1980s it was an
almost exclusively British practice (Collins 1983a:266-71). Now there are influential practitioners
throughout North America, as well as in France, Germany, the Netherlands,
Scandinavia, Israel, and Australia; and key Anglophone works have been
translated into French, Italian, Japanese, Polish, Russian, and Spanish. Programs in “Science Studies,” “Science and
Technology Studies,” or “Science, Technology and Society” - several elaborately
funded by the US National Science Foundation - employing sociologists of
scientific knowledge have sprung up at leading American universities; relevant
professional societies flourish. Journals
and academic publishers, once unaware of or uninterested in the field, now
actively seek out contributions, creating a situation in which demand outstrips
quality supply. Seminal monographs have
been reprinted and advertised as “classics” (Bloor
1991, Collins 1992); anthologies, primers, synthetic surveys, and candidate
textbooks have appeared and been superseded by new texts bidding to redefine a
fast-changing field (Barnes 1972, 1985, Mulkay
1979, Barnes & Shapin 1979, Barnes & Edge
1982, Law & Lodge 1984, Yearley 1984, Woolgar 1988a, Cozzens & Gieryn 1990, Callon & Latour 1991, Jasanoff et al
1994).
Projects have been launched
to intercalate the findings of SSK into programs of science communication and
liberal education (Collins & Pinch 1993, Chambers & Turnbull 1989) [3] and into the
analysis and formulation of science and
2. As I shall note below, many sociologists of scientific knowledge were
not professionally trained in sociology, and neither was I. (My training and much of my work belong more
to history than to sociology.) Such
amateurism often betrays itself in naiveté, far less often in insight into
fundamentals. Not coming to sociology
through a normal career-route, I find myself “unprofessionally” interested in
what it is to have a sociological understanding of science.
3. A measure of the provisional success of these suggestions is a recent
series on scientific experiment, published in The Economist (Morton
& Carr 1993), which draws heavily upon SSK research.
290
technology policy (Jasanoff 1990,
1992, Wynne 1992, Collins 1985, Fuller 1993, Cambrosio
et al 1990, Travis & Collins 1991, Epstein 1993), while the potential of
SSK (broadly construed) to recast the traditional categories of social and
cultural theory as a whole has been asserted (Latour
1993, Law 1994). [4]
Most importantly, the
general academic culture has shown great interest in what has been done in this
field. Unlike many other sociological specialties, SSK has strongly engaged the
attention of historians and philosophers (e.g. Shapin
1982, Shapin & Schaffer 1985, Rudwick 1985, Golinski
1990, Dear 1995, Fuller 1988, 1992, Rouse 1987, Toulmin
1990), and the boundary lines between what counts as historical or
philosophical and what as sociological practice in the area have been blurred
to the point of invisibility. [5] Meanwhile anthropologists, literary and feminist theoreticians,
and a loosely defined but trendy “cultural studies” community have been
attracted in significant numbers to the study of science largely through work
in SSK. The social study of science is
one of the modern academy’s most unremittingly interdisciplinary projects.
Twenty-five years ago it
was a truth almost universally acknowledged that there might be a legitimate
sociological understanding of scientific error, of “the blind alleys entered by
science,” of the state of scientific institutionalization, and, perhaps, of the
overall dynamics of scientific foci, but that there could be no such thing as a
sociology of authentically scientific knowledge (Ben-David 1971:11-13). Now, while assent to the validity of SSK is
scarcely universal, a number of central claims have quietly passed into common
academic currency, and the recent paths of the history and philosophy of
science, technology, and medicine have been fundamentally shaped by
practitioners’ appreciation of opportunities opened up or problems posed by SSK
research.
At the same time, the field
shows many signs of being in serious trouble: Some problems are of very long
standing, while others must be seen as the bitter fruits of success itself. The very achievement of SSK in establishing
the possibility, legitimacy, and interest of a thoroughly sociological (and
social historical) understanding of scientific knowledge has attracted so great
a range of scholars from other disciplines that neither the boundaries of the
field nor
4. Recent social theorists continue to comment centrally on modern
science and technology while engaging only obliquely or not at all with the SSK
literature (e.g. Bauman 1993:199-209, Giddens 1993:9-15,
Bourdieu 1990, 1991).
5. When the speciality was last reviewed in
this journal, HM Collins (1983a:272) acutely noted that the relationship
between SSK and relevant history was seamless and that a “proper description”
of the field “would treat the history of science as integral.” Yet, largely restricting his treatment to
ethnographic studies of contemporary science, Collins did not there attempt to
offer such a “proper” account. Two years
earlier (Collins 1981a), he had voiced doubts that historical work was capable
in principle of attaining the ethnographer’ s understanding of science, and
four years later (1987) he proclaimed that historical studies represented some
of the best SSK. Shifting judgments are
possibly best read as reliable reflections of shifting realities.
291
its intellectual goals and foci are any longer at all
clear. What appears to some
practitioners as an admirable “diversity of voices” seems to others lamentable incoherence
and lack of seriousness of purpose. The “social study of science,” as opposed to
SSK “proper,” has developed into one of the modern academy’s most centrifugal,
most argumentative (at times uncivil), as well as most vital terrains (e.g.
Pickering 1992). Just because what is at
stake is nothing less than the proper interpretation of our culture’s most
highly valued form of knowledge - its truth - the struggle for interpretative
rights has become fraught and bitter. Names are called and mud is slung. The weight of the world’s injustices is dumped
firmly on the shoulders of those maintaining “incorrect” methodological views. This is not a practice for the cardiovascularly challenged.
Fundamental issues of
methodological propriety are fervently debated. Choices between Durkheimian
objectivism and Weberian subjectivism, explanatory
and interpretative goals, stress on structure and agency, micro and macro foci,
theoretical and empirical methods - all are often fought out in relative
disengagement from the career of parallel debates in mainstream sociology, with
results ranging from rediscovered wheels to important respecifications
of the terms of debate (Cailon & Latour 1981, Collins 1981a, 1983b, Knorr-Cetina
1981a,b, Law 1974, 1984, Turner 1981). Metaphysical
and ontological schemes are proffered, and it is asserted that sociology of
science requires the adoption of the correct scheme, while skeptics wonder why
interpretative projects should be supposed to require a
metaphysics (Latour 1993, Shapin
1992:354-60). Leading sociologists of
science discover that the practice has contained social-theoretical entities,
such as “interests,” and announce their gleeful despair that “definitive”
descriptions or explanations of science can ever be attained, while other practitioners
express bemusement that anyone could ever think to construct accounts free of
theorizing or pretending to definitiveness (Woolgar
1981, Barnes 1981).
Relativism is attacked (far
less often than it is actually commended) as an insidious threat to the fabric
of social order, while advocates argue that methodological (not moral or
ontological) relativism is simply necessary for the naturalistic interpretation
of variation in belief. [6] Practitioners agonize over the proper posture of the analyst, as
between disinterested and committed. The
original claim that SSK was just the extension of science to the study of
itself (Bloor [1976] 1991) has been countered by the
increasingly insistent - though perhaps not yet dominant - voices of writers
meaning to “expose” science (as
6. For an analyst to say that the credibility of two different beliefs
about the world should be interpreted using the same methods is, thus,
not necessarily the same thing as saying that they are equally “true” or that
the world(s) to which they refer is (are) multiple. Almost all SSK relativists set aside
ontological questions and treat truth-judgments as topic rather than as
resource. So far as morality is
concerned, the dominant tendency here is not to celebrate moral anarchy but to
interpret how locally varying moral standards acquire their obligatory
character.
292
“hegemonic,” as “masculinist,”
as “dehumanizing,” as “mystifying”) and by those who reckon that a proper task
for scholars is to open up alternative visions of what science might be and how
its social relations ought to be constituted (Martin 1993, Restivo
1989, Lynch & Fuhrman 1991, Scott et al 1990; cf
Collins 1991, Lynch 1992b).
Quite recently, small
numbers of eminent natural scientists have become aware of SSK, and, cavalierly
neglecting crucial differences in tone and intent among practitioners, have
sought to expose them all as motivated by hostility to science, purportedly
animated by hidden political agendas (Gross & Levitt
1994, Wolpert 1992). Alleged crises in public confidence in, and
support for, science have been traced - incredible as it may seem - to the
sinister influence of SSK and fellow-traveling philosophy of science (e.g. Theocharis & Psimipoulis
1987). The political vulnerability of
one of the few sociological specialties that, so to speak, “studies up,” that
aims to interpret a culture far more powerful and prestigious than itself, and
that offers accounts at variance with that culture’s official myths, is only
now being made manifest. As the Chinese
proverb has it, he who rides on the back of the tiger may wind up inside.
The number of sociologists
working in the area continues to be very small. The rise of SSK to relative popularity coincided
with the Thatcher government’s systematic reduction in British university
funding, from which several of the original homes of this sort of work suffered
significantly, eroding or eliminating their ability to train the next
generation. A surge of interest in this
area among American institutions from the mid-1980s was also checked by
recession and a consequent retrenchment in graduate student support and
opportunity. Hard times discourage
intellectual adventurousness, on the part of both students and recruitment
committees. Time and improving economies
may heal these wounds, but endemic structural difficulties beset SSK.
First, the sociological
study of science makes demands upon initiates which all but a handful find
difficult to fulfill. Despite the
continuing scientistic bent of North American
sociology, few students come equipped with relevant competences in the natural
sciences. The genuine incapacity of many
to get to grips with the scientific technicalities involved is added to the
fear of others that such competences will be extremely hard to acquire. Despite much liberal educational rhetoric and
distribution requirements, the gap between the “Two Cultures” described by CP
Snow in 1959 has not noticeably been bridged. There is a widespread, and partly justified,
sense that SSK is “hard,” and students searching for a secure career-track are
encouraged to look elsewhere. [7]
7. Yet it has to be noted that the study of any culture
possessing esoteric knowledge - e.g. that of machinists, soldiers, nurses, or Azande magicians - demands similar dedication and similar
commitment to technical mastery. It is arguably
not the “difficulty” of science but its “prestige” and “sacredness” that beget
this heightened anxiety.
293
Nor does the poor availability of undergraduate
courses in the area do much either to inform students about what the specialty
is like or to give them even a smattering of familiarity to set against
structurally induced “technophobia.” Moreover,
scientistic North American sociological traditions
and, to a lesser extent, traditions in Britain and Europe continue actively to
disseminate a picture of scientific “method” and scientific knowledge radically
at variance with those offered by SSK. There
is an argument that the last great bastion of faith in simplistic images of
science and its “method” is not to be found in the natural but in the social
sciences.
Students thus trained often
find the body of recent SSK - when they encounter it - not just unfamiliar but
shocking. Few sociology texts prepare
them for the claim that scientific truth is amenable to a thoroughgoing
sociological scrutiny, while some of the most senior and eminent authorities
remain among the unconvinced or unapproving. Joseph Ben-David (1981:41-47, 54-55), judging
work in the area to be largely “programmatic,” pronounced SSK to be
“sociologically irrelevant” and a “failure.” Stephen Cole (1992: 81), while making irenic
gestures toward SSK, nevertheless gave his opinion that it had “failed to
generate a single example or case study” that shows that social processes
“actually influence the specific cognitive content of science.” And TS Kuhn (1992:8-9), dissociating himself
from sociological appropriation of his work, has recently proclaimed that SSK,
or, more ambiguously, what “has been widely understood” as its claims, is “an
example of deconstruction gone mad.” [8] Compared to other specialties, SSK has few senior advocates or
practitioners in the sociological profession, nor, despite its persistent
characterization as “fashionable,” is association with SSK evidently a sound
strategy of career advancement.
The founding father of the
sociology of science, Robert K Merton, worked from the late 1930s through the
1960s to constitute the study of science as a legitimate branch of
structural-functionalist sociology, while at the same time he attempted to
constitute sociology as “scientific.” What
counted as “being
8. Harriet Zuckerman’s recent full-scale survey (1988) of the sociology
of science is, by comparison, notably informed about and courteous toward
strands of SSK, while she labors to assimilate this work to the
structural-functional tradition with which it is often seen to be in conflict. I should add that, as a participant, I am, of
course, wholly satisfied that a sociology of
scientific knowledge is both possible and necessary, and that it has accumulated
a large body of outstanding empirical work. Likewise, I am satisfied that much - not all -
criticism of SSK continues to proceed from an obtuse - and possibly willful - misrepresentation
of its central methods and claims (cf Barnes 1994:22-25,
Bloor 1991:163-85). Yet my purpose here is not merely to reiterate
old arguments in defense of SSK but to try to note some features of the cultural
framework in which that misrepresentation is so deeply entrenched.
294
scientific” was overwhelmingly taken from formal and informal
philosophical models of the natural scientific “method” (e.g. Parsons 1949:Ch
1). The same sensibility that persuaded
Merton and his associates that sociological accounting had to stop at the door
of scientific method and scientific knowledge (e.g. Merton 1970:xviii-xix, 75, 199-200) also supported the claims of
sociology to be a genuine science. Accordingly,
the very idea of a sociology of scientific knowledge butted against the
self-understanding and legitimation of dominant
strands of sociology. It is this
circumstance, more than others, that makes the place
of SSK so problematic within the overall sociological culture, especially in
its North American form.
Therefore, Peter Winch’s
(1958) critique of enterprises that tried to base an understanding of social
action on the methods of natural science was decisive for several practitioners
of SSK (Collins 1975:216, 1981a:373, Knorr-Cetina
1981a:148-49, Lynch 1993:40-41, 163, 183, 228). If social science could be construed as
fundamentally different from natural science - in its objects and in its
appropriate methods - then it followed that the opening up of the natural
sciences to sociological understanding need not be seen as a threat to
sociology. The pertinence of Winch’s
views indicates the importance to SSK of intellectual resources coming from the
margins of the American sociological profession, and, indeed, from outside of
sociology proper. [9] Winch’s book significantly stimulated curiosity about the
later philosophy of Wittgenstein, especially its analysis of the indeterminacy
of “rules,” while other British practitioners disputed Winch’s distinction between
sociology and natural science (Bloor 1983). The intellectual mix that in the 1970s
inspired the early sociological studies of such British writers as Barry
Barnes, David Bloor, HM Collins, Donald MacKenzie, Michael Mulkay,
Richard Whitley, and Steve Woolgar included, to be
sure, elements of the classic sociological theory of Durkheim
and, more diffusely, of Marx, but also the historiography of TS Kuhn, the
comparative cultural anthropology of EE Evans-Pritchard, Mary Douglas, and
Robin Horton, philosophical work on the categories of sociological explanation
by Alisdair Maclntyre,
Basil Bernstein’s revisionist sociology of language and education, the
relativist philosophy of Nelson Goodman, Mary Hesse’s
neo-Bayesian philosophy of science, and, especially, a vast body of detailed
historical work on the natural sciences in their social and cultural contexts.
In the early and mid 1980s,
SSK received an infusion from practitioners trained in, or attracted by,
phenomenological and ethnomethodological traditions. Studies by Michael Lynch, Steve Woolgar, Steve Yearley, and Eric
Livingston drew significantly on work by Alfred Schutz
and Harold Garfinkel
9. Winch’s work, while influential in British sociological theorizing,
is referred to little or not at all in standard American surveys.
295
(Lynch 1988, 1993:Ch 4). [It was predominantly these writers who
imported the tag “social construction” into SSK, most immediately by way of
Berger & Luckmann (1966), though others not
primarily indebted to phenomenology soon elaborated a modified conception of
“social constructionism,” different from both its
theoretical begetters and from sociological “labeling theory.”] [10] More recently, such sociologists as Susan
Leigh Star, Adele Clarke, Joan Fujimura, and Chandra Mukerji
have effected links between SSK and “Chicago School” interactionist
sociology of work, occupations, and culture (e.g. Clarke 1990, Clarke & Montini 1993, Star 1989, Star & Griesemer
1989, Mukerji 1989, Fujimura 1987, 1988). And all through the 1980s, social studies of
science have been increasingly preoccupied by challenges to several central
descriptive and explanatory categories emerging from a Parisian circle centered
on Bruno Latour, whose work was itself fundamentally
shaped by Nietzschean and Heideggerian
philosophical traditions as well as by the techniques of semiotics and
anthropological ethnography (Latour 1987, 1988a,
1993).
Only in one respect is SSK
typical of the sociological profession:
Its practitioners disagree about the very identity of sociology, and,
therefore, about the identity of a legitimate sociological framework for the
study of their objects. In the late
1970s and early 1980s, Ben-David, meaning to be rude about SSK, observed
(1978:203-08, 1981:43-47; cf Zuckerman 1988:513) that
few of its leading practitioners were properly trained as sociologists, that
they meddled with epistemological concerns best left to philosophers, and that,
owing to their amateurism, they were unfamiliar with the history of disaster
that was said to be the career of systematic sociological attempts to account
for scientific knowledge. Ben-David’s
description was, to be sure, correct on several points. Few of the founding figures were professionally
trained as sociologists (Collins 1983a:267-68). On the other hand, a number had natural
science backgrounds that discouraged them from confusing the reality of
scientific knowledge-making with textbook idealizations. The field was also particularly receptive to
the sociological exploitation of historical and philosophical frameworks
developed by such writers as Michael Polanyi (1958)
and Thomas Kuhn (1962), who did have extensive natural scientific experience.
Moreover, as Ben-David
rightly noted, the leading concerns of “British” SSK were philosophical
and, in particular, epistemological. If
scientific judgment and the growth of knowledge could be adequately accounted
for by impersonal canons of evidence, logic, rationality, and, especially, of
“the
10. By the early to mid 1970s, phenomenologically
inclined sociologists were widely appropriating the tag, and it remains
especially fashionable in work on sexuality, deviance, and crime. So far as I can discover, the first uses of
the term in titles of studies concerned with science appear in 1976 and 1977;
evidently the term reached its height of SSK popularity in the late 1970s and early
1980s (e.g. Latour & Woolgar
1979, MacKenzie 1981a, and Collins & Pinch 1982).
296
scientific method,” then, indeed, neither a sociological nor an
historically contextual account was appropriate for the interpretation or
explanation of scientific knowledge. The
“Great Tradition” of Vienna Circle logical empiricism was concerned with
providing not a naturalistic account of scientific change and judgment but (as
Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach
said) its “rational reconstruction.” Yet
other philosophers wrote as if “method-stories” were historically adequate, and
still others continued to conceive of sociological considerations as potential
“pollutants” of authentic science, to be guarded against or relegated to the
contingent domain of “contexts of discovery.”
Accordingly, early SSK took
it as a primary task to create a legitimate space for sociology where none had
previously been permitted, in the interpretation or explanation of scientific
knowledge. In just that sense, SSK set
out to construct an “anti-epistemology,” to break down the legitimacy of the
distinction between “contexts of discovery and justification,” and to develop
an anti-individualistic and anti-empiricist framework for the sociology of
knowledge in which “social factors” counted not as contaminants but as
constitutive of the very idea of scientific knowledge (e.g. Bloor
1975, Law 1975; cf Fuchs 1992:Ch
2). SSK developed in opposition to philosophical
rationalism, foundationalism, essentialism, and, to a
lesser extent, realism. The resources of
sociology (and contextual history) were, it was said, necessary to understand
what it was for scientists to behave “logically” or “rationally,” how it was
that scientists came to recognize something as a “fact,” or as “evidence” for
or against some theory, how, indeed, the very idea of scientific knowledge was
constituted, given the diversity of the practices claiming to speak for nature
(Bloor 1984a,b, Collins
1981b). The current philosophical tag
corresponding to SSK is “social epistemology” (Fuller 1988, 1992).
Analytic philosophers of
science have not much appreciated, nor in many cases comprehended, the gesture
- a “social epistemology” seemed to some a contradiction in terms - and the
career of SSK continues to be marked by trench warfare between its
practitioners and the dominant tendencies in the philosophy of science (e.g.
Brown 1984, 1989, Bloor 1991:163-85). For these reasons, SSK developed partly
through efforts to exploit some traditional and nontraditional sociological
resources to show - both theoretically and empirically - how a
sociology of scientific knowledge was possible, and not as a
professional extension of mainstream disciplinary practices into this terrain. On the whole, mainstream sociological
practitioners did not want sociology to go in such directions or did not
believe that it could be so extended. The
over-publicized “warfare” between SSK and the “Mertonians”
was, in fact, but a brief early episode in the career of the field and was
mainly concerned with such questions of possibility (Collins 1983a:266, 271).
SSK practitioners soon
found it more satisfying to do the sociology of scientific knowledge than to
argue whether it was possible, and by the early
297
1980s, they were content to point to a body of
detailed empirical studies as strong evidence of that possibility (Shapin 1982). Indeed, early practitioners systematically
argued that scientific knowledge could be understood in just the same way as
one would go about interpreting any other area of culture - there were no special resources or methods
required to account for science (Barnes 1974). So a number of important writers, having
established that point of possibility to their satisfaction, saw no special
reason to persist with the particular study of the natural sciences and moved
on (in whole or in part) to applying the methods and resources of SSK to other
areas of culture (notably technology and economics), to debates in the
philosophy of knowledge and theories of representation, to social theory, and,
notably, to participation within such scientific practices as artificial
intelligence (e.g. Barnes 1988, Collins 1990, Ashmore
et al 1989).
SSK and the Forms of Cultural Inquiry
If intellectual influences
on SSK and its diverse disciplinary affiliations make the field marginal to the
profession of sociology, its preoccupations, circumstances, and several of its
findings ought to make it central to the sociological enterprise, and, indeed,
to cultural inquiry as a whole. On the
one hand, SSK, like any descriptive or explanatory practice, inevitably deploys
our current stock of knowledge about what the world, natural and social, is
like. However much practitioners in this
area may mean to show that such items as “neutrinos,” “neurofibrillary
tangles,” or “social class” are theorized and socially constructed, the realist
mode of speech is ineliminable in practice, and the
“phenomenological bracketing” that allows analysts to be curious about how such
items are constructed is dependent upon a robust realist idiom in speaking
about other items. Skepticism, as
Wittgenstein said, takes place on the margins of trusting systems, and radical
skepticism is radically disruptive of communicative order (Douglas 1986, Shapin 1994:Ch 1). This is no more than to say that sociologists
of scientific knowledge “know” the world that science has depicted as securely
as any other competent members of the culture, and that they use this knowledge
in producing their accounts.
On the other hand, the
practice that seeks to understand science as an historical and social enterprise
also demands that analysts be curious about its findings, including the
findings about the natural and social worlds that have to be used to implement
that curiosity. The realist mode of
speech itself becomes an object of curiosity. In this sense, SSK is prone to tension between
how it speaks and what it says, and its practice is irremediably embedded in
the objects of its inquiry (Barnes 1981:484, 493). While many philosophical and everyday forms of
inquiry seek to justify our intuitions about science - its correspondence, its
objectivity, its efficacy, and its progressiveness - SSK takes those intuitions
as matters to be interpreted and explained (Collins
298
1981b). That makes SSK at times uncomfortable -
to both practitioners and readers of their work - but also fundamental to our
culture’s self-understanding. Uneasiness
in inquiry is often - not invariably - a sign that the inquiry is nearing the
heart of the matter, and the claimed hyper-awareness
of “post-modernity” is played out in SSK in one of its most acute forms.
The second reason SSK may
arguably be central to the sociological enterprise and to cultural inquiry as a
whole flows from the categories that traditionally comprised the sociology of
knowledge and the changes wrought on these categories by work over the past
quarter-century. As Merton surveyed the
field in 1945, the sociology of knowledge was the practice that sought to show
the influence of social (or “existential”) factors upon “mental productions”
(Merton 1973; cf Parsons 1949:14). How did social
factors condition the form, content, and dynamics of cognitive products? There was social stuff and there was
intellectual stuff, and there were (varying) narratives concerned to bridge the
Cartesian gulf. That dualism, and that
resulting problematic, were accepted by all theorists, no matter what scheme
they proposed for doing the connecting (causal, functional, or symbolic), and
no matter what exemptions (typically the mental productions of logic, mathematics,
and the natural sciences) they stipulated. [11]
The dualism that provided
traditional sociology of knowledge with its frame of reference was inherited
from ancient lay and philosophical discourse. From the Greek philosophical tradition to
early Christianity and on into the culture of seventeenth-century English
empiricism and nineteenth-century high romanticism, knowledge was considered to
be properly philosophical, sacred, or genuine insofar as the circumstances of
its attainment were removed from the domains of the practical and the political
(Shapin 1991a,b). Disengagement and disembodiment were ancient
tropes of value: Removing knowledge-making from the polis was seen as a
technique of transcendence. Accordingly,
to say that knowledge was produced in and through mundane interactions between
people, as well as between people and reality, was
taken just to say that its truth, objectivity, universality, and power were
compromised. So far as genuine
philosophical knowledge was concerned, the polity was a pollutant. In this way, interpretative and explanatory
tasks were embedded - largely unwittingly - in traditional tropes of
evaluation. Bacon’s idols of the theatre
and the marketplace marked the social contamination of knowledge no less
11. It has often been insisted that Merton himself (1973) was the father
of that “Copernican revolution” in the sociology of science which took true as
well as false belief for its legitimate subject, from which it follows, in Bourdieu’s opinion (1990:297-98), that writers like Barnes
and Bloor were merely “crashing through an open
door.” It is, for all that, remarkable
that Merton never purported to produce a sociological account of what has been
called “the technical content” of scientific knowledge, while some of his
followers continue to insist very vigorously on the impossibility of any such
account.
299
than the presentation of Greek and early Christian
thinkers as withdrawn and disengaged. From the late 1930s through the 1960s and
beyond, the discourse of “internalism” and
“externalism” that so fundamentally structured the practice of history and
sociology of science took the dualistic juxtaposition of “social” versus
“rational,” “intellectual,” and “evidential” for granted. “The social” was taken as that which was
“external” to science, and it was persistently debated by what means authentic
science kept “the social” at bay, how and to what extent “social influences”
infiltrated science without deleterious effects, or how what seemed to be
properly scientific knowledge was “in fact” socially marked ideology (Shapin 1992).
Some strands of early SSK
and related social historical work did indeed deploy the same society-mind
vocabulary as traditional sociology of knowledge. Here the task was taken to be the showing of
“social influences” on properly scientific knowledge where such “influences”
had previously been reckoned not to act. The taken-for-granted equation between the
social autonomy and the truth of knowledge was challenged, and a series of
empirical studies sought to establish - without a tone of exposé - that even
the “hard cases” of claims within the physical and mathematical sciences,
taxonomic sciences, and observation-reports were so “influenced”: Society, and
its concerns, nevertheless “got in” (Shapin 1979, MacKenzie 1978, 1981a). To a number of critics, that sums up the case
that SSK argued: Its bearing upon the truth and objectivity of science was
taken over from traditional schemes that conceived the social as a
“contaminant” (Brown 1989). Where there
was “social influence,” there the roles of natural reality and rationality were
regarded as compromised.
However, this sensibility
in fact grossly misrepresents SSK’s case for “the
social.” Rather, the claim was that “the
social dimension” of knowledge needed to be attended to in order to understand
what counts as a fact or a discovery, what inferences are made from facts, what
is regarded as rational or proper conduct, how objectivity is recognized, and
how the credibility of claims is assessed. The target here was not at all the legitimacy
of scientific knowledge but the legitimacy of individualist frameworks for
interpreting scientific knowledge. Attention was drawn to “the social dimension,”
accordingly, not as a pollutant but as a necessary condition for making, holding,
extending, and changing knowledge. In
just that sense, the language of “the social” as a “dimension,” an “influence,”
or a “factor” to be juxtaposed with the “factors” of evidence and rationality
was rendered problematic (Lynch 1991b). And
here, arguably, SSK was the primary field in which that challenge to the traditional
dualism was laid down.
The challenge was expressed
in varying idioms. From 1979 Bruno Latour repeatedly pointed out that there was undeniably as
much (and arguably more) “politics” within the walls of scientific workplaces
as there was outside, and
300
that the securing of credibility for scientific claims was
a thoroughly social and political process. Thus he highlighted as a potential topic of
inquiry the cultural scheme that simply assumed otherwise (Latour
1987: 30, 62). At the same time, the
performance of modern political action fundamentally implicated scientific
knowledge of what sorts of things existed in the world and how these things
acted upon humans. The “missing masses”
in existing social and political theory were the “nonhumans” predicated by
science and technology. A defensible
sociology of science and technology, therefore, had the potential to recast the
terms of social theory generally. Signaling
the sensibility that sought to remove “the social” from its status as “factor,”
the second (1986) edition of Latour & Woolgar’ s
Laboratory Life deleted the word “social” from its original (1979)
subtitle: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts. To remove “the social” from the idea of
scientific knowledge was said to remove its status as knowledge.
In a more familiar
(anti-)epistemological idiom, Mulkay, Barnes, and Bloor sought, from the early 1970s, to establish the
inadequacies of individualism for interpreting scientific, or any other form
of, knowledge. Here the Kuhnian framework assumes central significance, not least
for appreciating the place of SSK vis-à-vis existing sociological traditions. If, for Merton, the answer to the
Hobbes/Parsons social-order problem was supplied, in the case of science, by a
set of allegedly unique social norms making up the “ethos of science,” for
Kuhn-inspired SSK, the regulative principles of social order in science were
furnished by scientific knowledge itself. Within traditions of “normal science,”
authoritative socializing institutions schooled practitioners in exemplars
(“paradigms”) of what it was to do good science in particular domains. For early modern chemists, Robert Boyle’s
J-tube experiment defined a model problem and its model solution, including the
embodied representation of what it meant for evidence to confirm or disconfirm
a theoretical hypothesis; for late twentieth-century molecular biologists, the
“central dogma” (by which DNA produces RNA produces protein) similarly
structures practitioners’ sensibilities about relevant domains of inquiry, about
the directionality of molecular cause, and about the locus of biological
meaning.
From a sociological point
of view, Kuhnian SSK is at once conservative and
radical. On the one hand, it seeks inter alia to
answer traditional questions about the grounds of a communal order, and it does
so by pointing to the regulative role of norms. While the regulatory relevance of social
maxims (“Be skeptical,” “Be disinterested”) is doubted, the significance of
norms for ensuring order and for marking the boundaries of communities is
vigorously respecified and reaffirmed in a new idiom.
The solidarity of specialist communities
- or such solidarity as is found to exist - is coordinated through their
specialist knowledge. Good and bad,
proper and improper, interesting and banal scientific behavior is recognized
and sanctioned by members’ knowledge
301
of the natural world. On the other hand, by arguing that the
relevant norms are made of the same stuff as the community’s technical
knowledge, the Kuhnian move overturns the existing
sociology-of-knowledge scheme that asks how “society might influence
knowledge.”
Just because the sway of an
evaluative individualism in interpreting our society’s most esteemed knowledge
has been so strong, SSK’s insistence upon a quite
elementary feature of the sociological sensibility has seemed to acquire a
shockingly radical, even subversive, character. If sociology is the study of the collective aspects
of human conduct, then a basic role for the sociological study of scientific
knowledge is showing in what ways that knowledge has to be understood as a
collective good and its application as a collective process. If there is a fundamental and irreducibly
sociological point to be made about scientific knowledge, it is this one.
Society - including the specialist societies of scientists - might properly be
regarded as a distribution of knowledge, just as the very idea of knowledge
depended upon the social relations of knowers (Barnes
1988, Shapin & Schaffer 1985).
Following such writers as Simmel (1950: 313) and Polanyi (1958), it has been noted that
modern systems of scientific and technical knowledge are highly differentiated
and distributed: No one individual keeps the whole of a discipline’s knowledge
in his or her head, and even the technical knowledge involved in the conduct of
a single experiment in modern physics or biology is typically distributed
across a range of specialist actors. In
a symbolic interactionist idiom, actors in different
“social worlds” are invariably involved in the making of scientific goods (Star
& Griesemer 1989). And, while this distributed character is very
evident in modern scientific practice, in principle it is arguably just as
pertinent as a description of the “simpler” scientific cultures of past
centuries. The director of a large-scale
experiment in high-energy physics does not have direct knowledge of every
aspect of that experiment, just as an individual seventeenth-century English
natural philosopher would typically not have direct evidential warrant for his
knowledge of icebergs, comets, or the flora of the Americas. As a general matter, practitioners rely
massively upon others for their knowledge. For there to be solutions to the problem of
knowledge there have to be practical solutions to problems of trust, authority,
and moral order (Barnes 1985:49-58, 82-83). Individualist philosophies of knowledge at
least since Locke have persistently argued that knowledge is genuine and secure
when its warrants are direct, experiential, and individual (Shapin
1994:Ch 5). If that is the case, then the
sociological sensibility would suggest that there is perishingly
little genuine and secure scientific knowledge in the world. Yet that is not what sociologists of
scientific knowledge have argued: Scientific knowledge is as secure as it is
taken to be, and it is held massively on trust. The recognition of trustworthy persons is a
necessary component in building and maintaining systems of knowledge, while
302
the bases of that trustworthiness are historically and
contextually variable. This core
sociological insight into the collective nature of knowledge has enormous
potential to generate detailed comparative studies of the moral economies of
science, but, perhaps owing to the largely philosophical concerns of many
sociologists of scientific knowledge, the point has as yet been made, for the
most part, at a programmatic level. [12]
A fundamental sociological
collectivism applies not just to describing the conditions in which it can
rightly be said that individuals have knowledge but also to the means by which
knowledge is acquired, applied, and changed. Scientists’ knowledge of specialist domains of
the natural world, like that of children, is for the most part initially
acquired via trusted sources. The proper
applications of terms like “chicken,” “dog,” “electron,” and “ideal gas” are
not logically fixed; rather, how such terms are used, whether by scientists or
laity, is adapted to a range of contingent circumstances, including the weight
of custom and convention and the purposes people may have in representing the
world. This is the sense in which it is
said, following Durkheim and Mauss,
that the classification of things reproduces that of people (Bloor 1982). When
people confront the experience of their senses, they do so within an already
existing structure of knowledge given them by their community and within a
structure of purposes sustained by their community. Nor, when new experience is confronted, is it
logically determined how such experience is to be sorted out with respect to
existing schemes: whether it is to be counted as evidence confirming or
disconfirming some theory, whether it is to be bracketed, subjected to taboo,
or filed away, to be dealt with another time. It is people’s goal-orientation - the
pragmatic structure of the community to which they belong - that judges among
possible courses of action. Much of the
theoretical development of SSK through the 1970s and early 1980s concentrated
upon elaborating a fully general sociological framework for interpreting
knowledge-acquisition and concept-application (Barnes 1982a,b,c,
1983). And, despite the fact that this
work developed without evident specifiable intellectual “influence” from
American pragmatist philosophy, it is wholly compatible with pragmatism, and,
by extension, with strands of academic sociology - those of Mead, Blumer, and their progeny - that drew inspiration from
James and Dewey.
In this way, SSK opposed
philosophical rationalism - the view that scientific judgment is sufficiently
determined by unambiguous criteria of method - by asserting the contingency and
the locality of judgment. Rules did not suffi-
12. An insistence that SSK should be concretely operationalized
in such ways has informed some criticism that it “has not developed a
fully-fledged sociological account of science” (Fuchs 1992:Ch
2, Hagendijk
1994:135). Once more, an accusing finger
is pointed at excessively philosophical concerns.
303
ciently explain scientific judgment; the way in which rules
were identified and used was itself a topic for contextual inquiry. Why is it that, since one can “rationally”
continue the series 2, 4, 6, 8... in any number of
ways, the “right way” of going on in an arithmetic class is “10” whereas at an
American sporting event it is more likely to be “who do we appreciate?” (Collins 1992:12-16). [13] Right conduct is tied to place and purpose. The in-principle “interpretative flexibility”
of rules is securely settled in practice by local notions of decorum.
By contrast with
rationalism, such SSK writers as Barnes and Bloor
explicitly endorse a robust realism and, indeed, have noted that the idiom of
sociological realism presupposes a corresponding natural realism: “No
consistent sociology could ever present knowledge as a fantasy unconnected with
our experience of the material world around us” (Bloor
1991:33) or “[T]here is indeed one world, one reality, ‘out there,’ the source
of all our perceptions…” (Barnes 1977:25-26, cf 1992, Barnes & Bloor
1982). [14] What one cannot do if one proposes disinterestedly to
interpret varying beliefs about nature, is to use one particular account - usually
that of modern science - to gauge the validity of others. That would be to include the answer in the
premises (Barnes 1992). All
institutionalized beliefs about nature are causally connected to reality, and
all are on a par with respect for the manner in which their credibility is to
be interpreted. Judgments of what is the
case, like judgments of what is rational, are locally accomplished.
Situated Knowledge and Its Travels
Indeed, the best way of
summing up the thrust of a great deal of work in SSK, and in related history
and philosophy, produced from the mid-1970s to the present, is to see it as
concerned to show in concrete detail the ways in which the making, maintaining,
and modification of scientific knowledge is a local and a mundane affair. Here the case-study method - occasionally
belittled as piling on more “proof’ of “the same sociological theory” - is
beautifully suited to the business at hand, since its “theory” of science is
more “shown” than “said, and since its practitioners are rightly skeptical of
narratives that purport to distill the “essence” of practices as varied as
those that are, and have been,
13. The sociological locus classicus for
treatment of Wittgenstein on rule-following is Winch (1958), and in SSK,
Collins (l992:Ch 1), Bloor
(1983, 1992), Lynch (l992a, 1993:Ch 5).
14. The puzzle of why, despite these insistences, critics of SSK make it
out as a recommendation of “social variables” versus the “data from the
empirical world” (e.g. Cole 1992:2, 12,229) can best be resolved by noting the
hold of individualistic empiricism that makes such dualistic language
seem natural. Even Collins’s famous
dictum (198lc:54, cf Collins & Cox 1977:373,
Collins l98lb:2l6, 1992:16, 174) that “the natural world in no way constrains
what is believed to be” is repeatedly specified not as an epistemological or
ontological judgment but as a “methodological prescription” - how analysts
should proceed if they are genuinely curious about the bases of varying
beliefs.
304
called “scientific.” [5] Quite unlike past traditions in the
sociology of science, SSK case studies are typically tightly focused upon
specific passages of scientific practice. Their detailed ethnographic or historical
character is geared to breaking down the “enchantment” produced by distance
(Collins 1992:144-45) - and hence the appeal of idealized “method-stories” -and
to displaying the contingency, informality, and situatedness
of scientific knowledge-making.
These “localist”
arguments have proceeded along a number of lines. First, science-making is identified as a
mundane matter. Exploiting work by such
writers as TS Kuhn (1970), Peter McHugh (1970), Jeff Coulter (1975), Harvey
Sacks (1984), and Melvin Poilner (1987), much
empirical and theoretical research has been devoted to showing that the making
of scientific knowledge can be sufficiently accounted for by ordinary human
cognitive capacities and ordinary forms of social interaction (Barnes 1976, Feyerabend 1978, Lynch 1985, Collins 1992, Shapin
1994). Once the grand narratives of
unique scientific “norms” and unique scientific “method” lost their compulsion,
curiosity was unleashed about how scientists used “secular” ways of thinking
and acting to build up their exceptionally authoritative systems of knowledge
(Barnes 1974, Lynch 1985, Latour 1987, 1988a, Latour & Woolgar 1986, Turner
1989). Almost needless to say, mundane
means can produce widely differing products - just as stone, mortar, and rules
of thumb can produce results as varying as a worker’s cottage and Durham
Cathedral - and saying that science ought to be understood as a typical form of
culture is, of course, not the same thing as saying that it is no different
from other forms of culture. Arguably,
sociologists and historians are only now in a fit position naturalistically to
address relevant questions about the character and bases of cultural
difference.
Second, since it is argued
that no scientific claim “shines with its own light” - carries its credibility
with it - sociologists and historians have become intensely interested in the
specific processes of argumentation and political action whereby claims come to
be accepted as true or rejected as false. The gap between individual experience and
public knowledge must always be filled by persuasion, and the resources
available to make claims persuasive can include any tools the local culture
makes available and is responsive to. The
“rhetorical turn” in SSK has now yielded a large body of empirical work on the
techniques of scientific exposition - the textual and informal means by which
scientists labor to persuade others, to extend experience from private to
public domains, to assure others of their disinterestedness, to assert the
significance of their claims, to argue that their body of knowledge is indeed
“scientific” (Woolgar 1976, 1989, Yearley
1981, Gilbert & Mulkay 1984, Shapin
15. The link between the case-study method in science studies and the attempted
revival of the casuistical tradition in ethics is
worth pursuing. Both
instantiate doubt about the regulatory role of abstract theories (see e.g. Jonsen & Toulmin 1988, Bauman
1993).
305
1984a, Pinch 1985, Latour 1987, Bazerman 1988, Myers
1990, Dear 1991, Gieryn 1992).
Third, stress has been put
upon the embodied character of scientific knowledge. It is noted that scientific competences are
not effectively transferred from one individual to another,
and from one place to another, solely by recipes, algorithms, or formal rules
of proceeding. Much empirical work has
addressed the embodied nature of scientific know-how and the embodied vectors
by which it travels, whether that embodiment is reposed in skilled people, in
scientific instruments, or in the transactions between people and
knowledge-making devices. Collins’s
now-classic study (Collins & Harrison 1975) of the transfer of
laser-building skills as embodied tacit knowledge built upon an appreciation of
science as craftwork, and that work has in turn been extended by ethnomethodological and symbolic interactionist
studies of modern biology (Lynch 1985, Jordan & Lynch 1992, Clarke &
Fujimura 1992, Cambrosio & Keating 1988) and
mathematics (Livingston 1986), and by historical work on physics (Shapin & Schaffer 1985:Ch 6, Moms 1988, Schaffer 1989,
1992a,b, Warwick 1992-1993), astronomy (Schaffer 1988, Van Helden
1994), chemistry (Roberts 1991, Golinski 1994),
genetics (Kohler 1994), and medicine (Lawrence 1985).
Finally, empirical and
theoretical work has addressed the physical situatedness
of scientific knowledge-making (Ophir & Shapin 1991). The
grand narrative of inherent scientific universality deflected attention away
from place: Situatedness was the mark of lower
cultural forms, and science, as Durkheim announced
(1972:88), was “independent of any local context.” Again, structures of evaluation weighed
against localist perspectives on science. Yet, from the point of view of naturalistic
inquiry, science is undeniably made in specific sites, and it discernibly
carries the marks of those sites of production, whether sites be conceived as
the personal cognitive space of creativity, the relatively private space of the
research laboratory, the physical constraints posed by natural or built
geography for conditions of visibility and access, the local social spaces of
municipality, region, or nation, or the “topical contextures” of practice,
equipment, and phenomenal fields (Lynch 1991a, Gooding 1985, Shapin 1988). Here
SSK has not merely attempted a resuscitation of interest in the “contexts of
discovery” abandoned by philosophers, it has also opened up new curiosity about
structures of “justification” and the translation of knowledge from place to
place.
It is impossible to treat localist sentiments in the study of science without
engaging with the contribution of feminist writers, and it is equally
impossible briefly to summarize one of the modern academy’s most heterogeneous
and politically charged genres. (Feminist views of science, and their vexed
relations with SSK and social theory, merit systematic survey on their own by
someone competent in this contested domain.) One strand of feminist writing on sci-
306
ence - that which views the whole of
post-seventeenth-century science as “essentially masculinist”
- is not, indeed, compatible with post-Kuhnian sociological
localism: Grand narratives about what science “essentially is” or about its
“essential preoccupations” were just what the contextual and naturalistic turns
were meant to reject. To say that
science, across a broad sweep of history and cultures, was “essentially”
informed by gender preoccupations, or, with the “standpoint” theorists, that women-as-victims
are “epistemologically privileged,” represents much the same kind of
sensibility as those that announced that science was “essentially” about class
relations, or about the abstraction from common sense, or that a class of
free-floating intellectuals existed and enjoyed epistemological privilege. Yet other versions of feminist science studies
are perhaps best seen as tributaries of SSK and related streams feeding the
river of embodied localism. In
criticizing individualist, rationalist, and disembodied views of science, such
feminists as Dorothy Smith and Lorraine Code urge perspectives similar to those
of phenomenologically informed SSK, while Donna Haraway’s flamboyant antimodernism
tackles the great Enlightenment dualisms - nature/culture, human/nonhuman, etc.
- in order to display their historical specificity and thereby to reject them. Such feminist work often has its own
intellectual and frankly political agenda, but it is, nevertheless, intelligible
to see it as proceeding from sensibilities similar to SSK localism. It is another idiom for identifying and
interpreting “situated knowledges” (Haraway 1991: Ch 9).16
The localist
thrust of recent SSK has generated one of the central problems for future work.
If, as empirical research securely
establishes, science is a local product, how does it travel with what seems to
be unique efficiency? One appeal of the
modernist grand narratives of reason, reality, and method was the
table-thumping response they offered to questions about the travel of science. If, however, universality can no longer be
accepted as an assumption flowing from the very nature of the knowledge or the
“method” for making it, then what are the mundane means that so powerfully
effect the circulation of science? And
is that travel, indeed, to be treated as real, or is what circulates yet
another illusory grand narrative?
In this connection, SSK has
thrown up one particularly well-developed framework for engaging with the
problem of travel. Bruno Latour and his associates have offered what is best taken
as a descriptive vocabulary for construing scientific success and power (Callon et al 1986, Latour 1987,
1988a). “Technoscientific”
knowledge - both propositional claims and the
16. An entry to the contest between “standpoint,” “empiricist,” and
“postmodern” feminist writing on science can be secured via Bordo
(1987), Harding (1986), Code (1991), Haraway (1991),
Keller (1983, 1986, 1988), Longino (1990), Merchant
(1980), Noble (1992), Richards & Schuster (1989), Schiebinger
(1989), and Smith (1990).
307
knowledge embodied in technology - are held stable and treated
as true, insofar as they are constituted as obligatory passage points for many
actors’ work. Think, for example, of the
physical knowledge embodied in a thermometer. To contest that knowledge would be to fight on
many fronts against many institutionalized activities that depend upon treating
the thermometer as a “black box.” Intercalating
science or technology into larger and larger networks of action is what makes
them durable. When all the elements in a
network act together to protect an item of knowledge, then that knowledge is
strong and we come to call it scientific. The central modern scientific phenomenon to
which attention is directed is thus metrology - the development of standards
and their circulation around the world (Schaffer 1992b, O’Connell 1993, Barry
1993, Shapin & Schaffer l985:Ch
6). The suggestion is that the wide
distribution of scientific knowledge flows from the success of certain cultures
in creating and spreading standardized contexts for making and applying that
knowledge. Phrased in this way, Latour is offering a new, but sociologically recognizable,
vocabulary for describing institutionalization. [17]
The resources available to
effect this intercalation include a range of discursive and technical means. Artfully deployed rhetorical maneuvers delete
the grammatical modalities that qualify claims: The move from “Bloggs says,” to “It is the case,” to the submergence of a claim
in taken-for-granted background assumptions in yet another claim is a way of
describing the ascent to truth. Scientific
rhetoric induces readers to go in only one direction, that
pointed out by the author. Theatres of
persuasion can be mounted: The dramatic staging of such field trials as those
laid on by Louis Pasteur at Pouilly-le-Fort were at
once spectacles of confidence and of efficacy. Husbandmen who wanted their livestock
protected from anthrax were shown that, to achieve their ends, they had to go
through Pasteur’s Parisian laboratory and that Pasteur had to be treated as a
transparent spokesman for natural reality. Interests can be generated and translated. Potential consumers of technoscientific
goods can be told that they really need these goods in order to attain their
existing goals, or that their goals should be modified so as to achieve even
more benefits than they had envisaged. Allies
have to be enrolled by such persuasive acts and then controlled so that they do
not fall out of alignment. Technical
means can be found that make the exercise of power over a distance effective. The “immutable mobiles” represented by print
and graphic technologies can cir-
[17] Here and elsewhere I knowingly “make a mistake” - common to
Anglophone readers - of assimilating Latour’s work to
existing currents of sociological theorizing. This is to set aside the radical recasting of
the terms of theorizing sought by Latour’s “amodernist” metaphysics and its bearing on a proper
ontological vocabulary for referring to human and nonhuman actors. Ironically, however, this very
“misunderstanding” is proving to be the major vehicle for absorbing his work
outside of the French cultural context. In
Latourian vocabulary, therefore, “enrollment” is
proceeding apace while the “control” of allies is notably slack.
308
culate with minimum modification and represent a
world-to-be-controlled on the convenient scale of a tabletop (Latour 1987, 1988a).
Latour’ s
inventory of the means by which technoscientific
knowledge is extended amounts to a descriptive vocabulary of power as well as
of institutionalization. Pasteur grows
great and powerful, his knowledge is extended and made durable, insofar as
these effects are achieved. And, while Latour repeatedly disavows both
psychological theorizing and explanatory intent (Latour
1988b), the agent deploying these resources is recognizable from Machiavellian
and Hobbesian accounts of human nature: Pasteur is
displayed as animated by a will to power and domination, and his readers’
decisions to acquiesce or submit are treated as those of pragmatic maximizers-of-marginal-advantage. The language of militarism and imperialism is
natural to this account, and its suitability is explicitly asserted.
Indeed, one way of
situating the Latourian framework within sociological
traditions would be to see it as unwinding the solution of a social-order
problem which Parsons proffered. The
“dog that doesn’t bark” in Latour’s sociology is,
indeed, a conception of normative order. All these effects of order and its extension
are to be achieved by constant practices of enrolling, controlling, and
invigilating. Latourian
social order appears all natural fact and no moral fact. Therefore, the onus on those who suspect the
adequacy of Hobbesian accounts of order would be to
produce a post-Mertonian picture of the moral
economies of science - the locally distributed conceptions of legitimacy, authority,
and trust by which scientific knowledge comes to be a collective good, the
moral-pragmatic preconditions for intersubjectivity,
and the mundane means by which moral orders of scientific knowledge-making come
to be distributed around the world.
Despair and Decorum: SSK Dissolved?
No sooner had the dust
settled on the first claims of SSK “success” than a number of leading
practitioners announced that SSK was a failure and required replacement by more
“radical” next-things. The grounds of
this despair were several. The program
of “discourse analysis” launched in the early 1980s by Michael Mulkay and his students criticized SSK as a form of
overenthusiastic sociologizing (Gilbert & Mulkay 1984, Mulkay et al 1983). Rightly observing that scientists’ accounting
procedures were heterogeneous - sometimes they talked as if work were governed
by evidence and method and sometimes as if it were shaped by contingent
personal and social factors - Mulkay announced that
sociologists could never produce “definitive” descriptions or explanations of
science, dependent as they were on the jumble of scientists’ talk. At most and at best, sociologists should
document and classify scientists’ accounts. Definitive description could presumably still
be attained, but only
309
by shifting down a referential level, from accounts of
what science is to accounts of scientists’ accounts of what it is.
In an allied move some of Mulkay’s students cast a skeptical eye on the particular
form of “interest-explanations” produced by writers in the “Edinburgh School.” These too were condemned as instances of
sociological over-optimism. How could
one use “social interests” as explanations of scientists’ judgments when those
“interests” ought properly to be seen as objects of negotiation, constructed in
the course of interaction (Woolgar 1981, Yearley 1982)? Interests
were said to be inadequately established on empirical foundations. They were circularly inferred from the effects
they were meant to explain, and they were, for these reasons, illegitimately
smuggled into sociological explanations. Here too the “radical next move” out of SSK
was, by another description, the recommendation of judicious retreat from a
methodological impasse.
Discourse analysis and
closely related critiques of SSK have now largely been abandoned. SSK writers embraced the theoretical character
of their explanatory notions and wondered what other status “interests” could
have. Nor were they content to reduce
“interests” to “interest-talk.” As Barnes sourly put it, “With cream-cakes there is a chance of
satisfying hunger - with accounts of cream-cakes there is not” (Barnes 1981:492-93;
cf MacKenzie 1981b, Shapin l984b, Collins & Yearley
1992:303-04). If proponents of
SSK and many philosophers of science claimed that scientific theorizing can
never be fully justified - uniquely determined by the evidence - then, of
course, the same condition applied to social science theorizing. Nor were the foundational claims made for
“discourse” any less vulnerable than explanatory items: The forms of talk
discerned by discourse analysts went “beyond the evidence” no less than any
other sort of theoretical construct. The
“radical” program of discourse analysis was identified as a form of that
not-very-radical doctrine, positivism.
Emerging together with the
discourse analytic critique was a “reflexive” program. Proponents noted that the discursive forms in
which much SSK work was embedded shared with science a realist mode of speech
in which authority-claiming authors referred “disinterestedly” to real states
of affairs in the social world. This was
said to be an unsatisfactory situation, protecting from inquiry that which
ought properly to be the object of inquiry. Here the proposed “radical next move” was the
purposeful subversion of realist and referential modes of speech. “New literary forms” shattering these univocal
and referential modes were to be put in place of descriptions and explanations
of scientific conduct, and the objects of inquiry were to be shifted away from
“science” and “society” to the “referring self’ which had traditionally
reported upon “science” and “society.” Such questions were asserted to be deeper and
more fundamental, and the overarching problem to which reflexivity addressed itself
310
was no less than that of how we know anything at all
(e.g. Ashmore 1989, Woolgar
1988b, Mulkay 199 1:xvii). SSK was to be not exploded but imploded. To the objection that such practices were
getting nowhere, it was robustly replied that “getting nowhere should be seen
as an accomplishment” and that the “somewhere” purportedly reached by SSK was
in fact nowhere at all (Collins & Yearley 1992: 305).
“Next-step” radicalism
again appeared to those defending SSK as yet another counsel of despair (Pinch
1993, Pinch & Pinch 1988, Collins & Yearley
1992:305-9). “New literary forms”
arguably have the claimed capacity to break up authority only in the case of
quite dim readers. Either no specifiable
arguments or claims about science are being advanced through these forms (in
which case no note need be taken of them by those concerned with describing or
explaining science) or some definite proposition is being advanced (in which
case readers would attempt to discern it in the mélange of voices). As with discourse analysis, reflexive writers,
for all their trying, could not wholly avoid the realist mode of speech, and
one could scarcely imagine that their claims would be in any way comprehensible
if they had.
Discourse analysts and reflexivists were partly inspired by ethnomethodology,
and, indeed, the specifically ethnomethodological
critique of SSK [18] shares their suspicion of allegedly over-confident sociologizing and their attempt to shift attention from
“why-questions” to “how-questions.” [19] Just as ethnomethodologists
condemn the formalism, the reductionism, and the scientism of academic
sociology, so they consider the social explanations of science proffered by SSK
to be impoverished. Like the stylized
accounts of social behavior produced by mainstream sociologists, SSK is
considered to be insufficiently curious about the methods by which both
scientists and those who study them produce accounts. Ethnomethodologists
also reject asocial philosophical rationalism as a response to questions about
the grounds of social order in science: The production of social order in
scientific disciplines is said to be, in Lynch’s
formulation, “inseparable from the dense texture of understandings and
concerted practices that make up disciplinary specific language games.” The traditional concepts and methodological
stances of sociology are “simply overwhelmed by the heterogeneity and technical
density of the language, equipment, and skills through which [scientists] make
their affairs accountable” (Lynch 1993:298-99).
18. It is notoriously difficult to pin down ethnomethodological
doctrine. Here I broadly follow the
leading ethnomethodological analyst of science,
Michael Lynch (1993:Chs 1,4-7).
19. Here it is unclear whether the position is (i)
that “how-questions” are more fundamental and should precede posing
“why-questions”; (ii) that existing responses to “why-questions” are
inadequate; or (iii) that “why-questions” are illegitimate in principle and
ought to be given up. In the event, it
remains uncertain how, in any strong sense, “how-questions” could be thought to
replace “why-questions.”
311
Consequently, ethnomethodology, like strands of SSK, has commended ever
more finely grained studies of day-to-day scientific practice. It has been a major inspiration to work
displaying the mundane and everyday character of knowledge-making, while, on a
programmatic level, it has expressed doubt that sociologists currently possess
the conceptual resources to explain or even schematically to describe
scientific order. To that extent, the ethnomethodological posture is a form of asceticism. Yet that same unremitting asceticism has made ethnomethodologists reluctant to advance some of the more
expansive methodological claims staked out by other critics of SSK. Ethnomethodology,
at least in Lynch’s form, does not assert a
privileged stance for any form of sociological accounting; it does not see
foundations or Archimedean points available anywhere; and it recognizes no
reason to be troubled by or to abandon a realist mode of speech. What makes critics of ethnomethodology
despair is just the scope of its ascetic modesty.
Finally, for the past ten
years or so, Bruno Latour and his associates have
publicized their view that sociological explanations of scientific judgment are
outmoded, fundamentally flawed, and due for replacement. The traditional vocabulary of the sociology of
knowledge, which asked how “social factors” influenced scientific knowledge,
needed to be replaced with studies of how nature and society were
“co-produced.” SSK was to be applauded
for its devastating critique of philosophical rationalism, while its residual
ambition to explain nature by reference to society was to be definitively
rejected. Just as philosophers were
wrong to use natural reality to explain scientists’ beliefs, so sociologists
were wrong to use social reality toward that end. Analysts were told to be as curious about how
society was constructed as they were about the construction of natural
knowledge. What was wrong with SSK was
that it was, after all, a form of sociology, using the categories and seeking
the goals of the sociological realist: “[T]he social
sciences are part of the problem, not of the solution” (Latour
1988b:161).
The notion of the agent - taken
as the volitional human actor - is central to the sociologist’s vocabulary, and
it is in connection with Latour’s attempted reconceptualization of actors that his work has generated
the greatest excitement, bafflement, and exasperation. Agency, like “interests” and “nature,” is to
be regarded as the outcome of controversies, and we must not use such outcomes
to explain the career of controversies. Accordingly,
Latour means to develop a mode of talking about
science and society that does not prejudge the location of agency, in
particular as between humans and nonhumans: “[I]t is very important... not to
impose any clear distinction between ‘things’ and ‘people’ in advance” (Latour 1987:72). In
present-day science studies, confusion reigns about whether what is being
offered is a scheme identifying the semiotic equivalence of human and nonhuman
“actants” - which, while exotic to Anglophone
cultural inquiry, does not necessarily impinge upon ordinary
312
realist speech - or whether genuine ontological claims are
being made, with attendant prescriptions for proper speech in science studies
and in the wider culture.
It is this aspect of Latour’s work that is currently proving most attractive to
analysts of science with “posthumanist”
sensibilities. So Andrew Pickering -
formerly a leading exponent of SSK - now advocates a “drastic overhaul of some
of our most basic intuitions... about the world, human and nonhuman”; “[o]ne very distinctive feature of modern technoscience
is... its capacity to unleash upon the world new and nonhuman actors...
“(Pickering 1993a: 104, 112; also l993b, Law l986a,b).
Latour’s
“actor-networks” and Haraway’s “cyborgs”
- part human, part nonhuman - transcend the “discredited” humanist and
modernist dualisms and are the appropriate units of analysis for writers who
wish to talk about making society and making science in the same idiom and
without commitment to a putatively modernist ontology. Anyone who wishes to understand modern science
and modern society must supply themselves with a new way of talking that
reflects the new realities. [20] Like the
seventeenth-century “moderns,” some postmoderns
evidently still yearn for a privileged language whose recommendation over
alternatives is that it mirrors the order of existence.
These critiques of SSK are
a heterogeneous lot, and it would be wrong to assimilate them too confidently
to a common source or sentiment. There
are, nevertheless, some family resemblances. First, the critiques proceed largely through
identifying SSK as a form of sociology. Its
sins are said to consist in its genetic relationship with the parent that
commonly denies the offspring as its own. That this irony has largely escaped
practitioners presumably stems from the circumstance that so few of them have
substantial commitments to the parental discipline. Almost needless to say, there is no reason
automatically to deprecate that circumstance or these criticisms. Neither commitment to fundamental sociological
resources nor the capacity to contribute to sociological inquiry necessarily
depends upon the forms of professional membership. Nor is it a prudent course for an academic
discipline to ignore or seek to ban fundamental criticism. Indeed, the baroque reflectiveness
of the science studies community throws into relief major features of the
sociological enterprise which more complacent and peaceable specialities
are less commonly obliged to confront.
Second, these critiques of
SSK, and, by extension, of sociology, have a
20. It is not at all clear whether such claims are indeed specifically
tied to nineteenth- or twentieth-century realities, or whether they are meant
to have wider temporal scope.
313
skeptical character. Typically, they are skeptical about the
claimed capacity of sociological categories to explain or reliably describe the
scientific objects of inquiry. Skepticism
has an ancient pedigree; it corrodes complacency and convention, and for that
reason alone the skeptic who makes life so awkward for the securely
institutionalized practitioner should be cherished like the most maddening of
mad uncles in a well-knit family. As
Collins (1992:6) puts it, skepticism has the virtue of being a “safe, legal and
inexpensive [way] to loosen the trammels of commonsense perception.” In this case, the skeptic’s voice has
challenged the legitimacy with which sociological descriptive, interpretative,
and explanatory categories have been applied, and they have challenged the
validity of the categories themselves. Versions
of this skepticism target not only the categories of academic sociology but,
importantly, those of realist modes of speech entrenched in our own culture. [21] SSK itself is, after all, a form of skepticism - for
example, with respect to the traditional vocabulary of “social versus cognitive
factors.” The effect
of this skepticism - both that of SSK and of its critics - has been, in my
view, overwhelmingly constructive. If, indeed, there was any taken-for-grantedness about what it was to give a sociological
description, interpretation, or explanation of science, it has now been buried
under an avalanche of methodological self-consciousness.
Third, and arguably in
tension with the skeptical posture, these critiques - with versions of ethnomethodology probably excepted - have also typically
betrayed a millenarian optimism. Existing
sociology is said to be insecurely founded. Yet if only we could get our concepts or
discourse right, if only we could take one more reflexive turn, if only we
could go down one more analytic level, if only the right, theoretically neutral
metalanguage could be devised, then at last we would
reach intellectual terra firma and
all would be well. However, far from
being a “radical next move,” there are no intellectual aspirations more
traditional than the quest for foundations: a pure and uncompromised place
beneath, above, beyond, or apart from the compromised categories of the culture
to which intellectuals mundanely belong. In other moods, critics of SSK have themselves
made major contributions to discrediting foundationalism.
Yet in their struggle to escape the
constraints of sociology, they have fallen into the oldest temptation ever to
afflict intellectuals. If the move from
traditional sociology of knowledge to SSK was the abandonment of pretensions to
privilege and of “the Archimedean point,” then the unwitting thrust of these
critics of SSK is that such a point can, after all, be found.
21. And here the break between interpretative
sociological goals and strands of postmodern science studies and Latourian practice is most apparent, since, to my
knowledge, no past or present-day scientific community trades in “stronger or
weaker heterogeneous networks of actants” while all
consequentially mark out domains of the human versus the nonhuman.
314
If there is an authentic
sociological voice to be set against individualism, empiricism, and positivism,
then that voice says “It cannot be done” - not in science and not in the study
of science. The “cage” from which the
critics evidently seek escape is not just sociology, but the realist mode of
speech which sociology shares with everyday talk. That robust realism is said to be the problem
to which there must be a remedy. To be
sure, the categories of mainstream sociology are not immune from important
criticism just because they are a version of the realist mode of speech, but
neither can criticism intelligibly suppose that the realist mode can be
replaced. The “cage” from which “escape”
is sought is, in fact, a condition of such liberty as we enjoy. Intellectuals are not obliged to leap free
from their culture in order to subject their culture to questioning, nor must
the great, and allegedly “modernist” or “humanist” dualisms be replaced in
order to be skeptical of them. Notice,
for example, that Latour’s idea of “heterogeneous
networks” is wholly intelligible, and that the condition of its intelligibility
is reference to entities plucked from the culture’s existing realist
repertoires: human, nonhuman, science, society. And if “modernist” dualisms were a “trap,”
then it would follow that late twentieth-century culture could contain no such
thing as a “materialist theory of the mind.” The fact that there is such a theory indicates
that we are not, evidently, ensnared by the categories of realist language at
all.
There are, however, limits
to skepticism about the categories of the common culture, and those limits are
posed by the boundaries of communication. We can develop and put in place arcane
languages, but we cannot ensure that others will hear us. Communicative orders are grounded in local
natural attitudes and local realist idioms. [22] If we wish effectively to speak to a specified community, we are obliged
to share its realist idiom. And if we
want to communicate at all then we are obliged to employ some version of the
realist mode of speech. That obligation is, properly speaking, a constraint. It
means, in the present case, that intellectua1s’ intelligible communication
about modern scientific culture will always be compromised by the cultural
categories shared between ourselves, the laity, and the scientists we talk
about. And if that speech is not so
compromised, then it will not be intelligible. Discontent with that formulation would,
indeed, be a measure of the extent to which sociology has been rejected or
ignored.
22. See Collins’s argument (versus Latour) in
favor of “sociological realism” as sociological decorum (Collins & Yearley 1992). No
one realist mode is privileged, but we can and should, Collins says, seek to
“alternate” between realisms. We suspend
irony about our local realist presumptions as a “methodological convenience.”
315
I thank Michael Lynch and Charis Cussins for enlightening
conversation and David Bloor
and Steven Epstein for critical comments on a previous draft of this piece.
Ashmore M.
1989. The Reflexive Thesis: Wrighting the
Sociology of Scientific Knowledge. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Ashmore M, Mulkay M, Pinch T. 1989. Health and Efficiency: A Sociology of Health Economics. Milton Keynes: Open
Univ. Press
Barnes B, ed. 1972. Sociology of Science.
Harmondsworth: Penguin
Barnes B. 1974. Scientific Knowledge and Sociological
Theory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
Barnes B. 1976. Natural rationality: a neglected concept in the social
sciences. Philos. Soc. Sci.
6:115-26
Barnes B. 1977. Interests and the Growth of
Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
Barnes B. 1981. On the ‘hows’
and ‘whys’ of cultural change. Soc. Stud. Sci.
11:48 1-98
Barnes B. 1982a. T. S. Kuhn and Social Science.
London: Macmillan
Barnes B. 1982b. On the implications of a body of
knowledge. Knowledge 4: 95-110
Barnes B. 1982c. On the extensions of concepts and the
growth of knowledge. Sociol. Rev.
30:23-44
Barnes B. 1983. Social life as bootstrapped induction.
Sociology 17:524-45
Barnes B. 1985. About Science. Oxford:
Black-well
Barnes B. 1988. The Nature of Power. Cambridge:
Polity
Barnes B. 1992. Realism, relativism and finitism. In Cognitive
Relativism and Social Science, ed. D Raven, L van Vucht
Tijssen, J de Wolf, pp. 131-47.
New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction
Barnes B. 1994. How not to do the sociology of
knowledge. In Rethinking
Objectivity, ed. A Mcgill,
pp. 21-35. Durham, NC: Duke Univ. Press
Barnes B, Bloor D. 1982. Relativism,
rationalism and the sociology of knowledge. In Rationality and Relativism, ed. M
Hollis, S Lukes, pp. 21-47. Oxford: Blackwell
Barnes B, Edge D, eds. 1982. Science in Context: Readings in the
Sociology of Science. Milton Keynes: Open Univ. Press
Barnes B, Shapin S, eds. 1979. Natural
Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture. London/Beverly
Hills, CA: Sage
Barry A. 1993. The history of measurement and the
engineers of space. Br. I. Hist. Sci. 26: 459-68
Bauman Z. 1993. Postmodern Ethics. Oxford:
Blackwell
Bazerman C.
1988. Shaping Written Knowledge: The Genre and Activity of
the Experimental Article in Science. Madison: Univ. Wisc. Press
Ben-David J. 1971. The Scientist’s Role in Society: A Comparative
Study. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Ben-David J. 1978. Emergence of national traditions in the sociology of
science: the United States and Great Britain. In Sociology
of Science, ed. J Gaston, pp. 197-218. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass
Ben-David J. 1981. Sociology of scientific knowledge.
In The State of Sociology: Problems
and Prospects, ed. JF Short, pp. 40-59. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage
Berger P. Luckmann T. 1966. The Social Construction
of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Doubleday
Bloor D. 1975. Psychology or epistemology? Stud.
Hist. Philos. Sci. 6:382-95
Bloor D. 1982. Durkheim and Mauss revisited:classification
and the sociology of knowledge. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 13:267-97
Bloor D. 1983. Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge. London:
Macmillan
Bloor D. 1984a. A sociological theory of objectivity.
In Objectivity and Cultural Divergence, ed. SC Brown, pp. 229-45. Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press
Bloor D. 1984b. The sociology of reasons: Or why ‘epistemic factors’
are really ‘social factors.’ See Brown 1984, pp. 295-324
Bloor D. [1976] 1991. Knowledge and Social Imagery.
Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press. 2nd ed.
316
Bloor D. 1992. Left and right Wittgensteinians.
See Pickering 1992, pp. 266-82
Bordo S.
1987. The Cartesian masculinization
of thought. In Sex and
Scientific Inquiry, ed. S Harding, J O’Barr, pp.
247-64. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Bourdieu P. 1990. Animadversiones in Mertonem. In Robert K
Merton: Consensus and Controversy, ed. J Clark, C Modgil,
S Mod-gil, pp. 297-301. London: Falmer
Bourdieu P. 1991. The peculiar history of scientific
reason. Sociol. Forum 6:3-26
Brown JR, ed. 1984. Scientific Rationality: The Sociological Turn. Dordrecht: Reidel
Brown JR. 1989. The Rational and the Social.
London: Routledge
Callon M, Latour B. 1981. Unscrewing the big Leviathan: how actors
macro-structure reality and how sociologists help them to do so. In Advances in Social Theory and Methodology:
Toward an Integration of Micro- and Macro-Sociologies, ed. KD Knorr-Cetina, AV Cicourel, pp.
277-303. London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul
Callon M, Latour B, eds. 1991. La science telle
qu’elle se fait. Paris: Editions La Découverte
Callon M,
Law J, Rip A, eds. 1986. Mapping the Dynamics of Science
and Technology: Sociology of Science in the Real World. London:
Macmillan
Cambrosio
A, Keating P. 1988. ‘Going monoclonal’: art, science, and
magic in the day-to-day use of hybridoma technology.
Soc. Probl. 35:244-60
Cambrosio A, Limoges
C, Pronovost D. 1990. Representing biotechnology: an ethnography of Quebec science
policy. Soc. Stud. Sci. 20: 195-227
Chambers D, Turnbull D. 1989. Science worlds: an integrated approach to social
studies of science teaching. Soc. Stud. Sci. 19:
155-79
Chubin D, Chu E,
eds. 1989. Science Off the Pedestal. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth
Clarke AE. 1990. A social worlds research adventure:
the case of reproductive science. See Cozzens & Gieryn 1990, pp. 15-42
Clarke AE, Fujimura JH, eds. 1992. The Right Tools for the Job: At
Work in Twentieth-Century Life Sciences. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ.
Press
Clarke AE, Montini T. 1993. The many faces of
RU486: tales of situated knowledges and technological
contestations. Sci. Technol.
Hum. Values 18:42-78
Code L. 1991. What Can She Know? Feminist Theory
and the Construction of Knowledge. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univ. Press
Cole S. 1992. Making Science: Between Nature and Society. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard Univ. Press
Collins HM. 1975. The seven sexes: a study in the sociology of a
phenomenon, or the replication of an experiment in physics. Sociology 9:205-24
Collins HM. 1981a. Understanding science. Fund. Sci. 2:367-80
Collins HM. 1981b. What is TRASP? The radical programme as a methodological imperative. Philos. Soc. Sci. 11:215-24
Collins HM. 1981c. Son of seven sexes: the social destruction of a
physical phenomenon. Soc. Stud. Sci. 11:33-62
Collins HM. 1983a. The sociology of scientific knowledge: studies of
contemporary science. Annu. Rev. Sociol. 9:265-85
Collins HM. 1983b. The meaning of lies: accounts of action and
participatory research. In Accounts and Action, ed. GN Gilbert, P Abell, pp. 69-76. Aldershot:
Gower
Collins HM. 1985. The possibilities of science policy.
Soc. Stud. Sci. 15:554-58
Collins HM. 1987. Pumps, rock and reality. Sociol.
Rev. 35:819-28
Collins HM. 1990. Artificial Experts: Social Knowledge and
Intelligent Machines. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Collins HM. 1991. Captives and victims: comment on Scott, Richards, and
Martin. Sci Technol.
Hum. Values 16:249-51
Collins HM. [1985] 1992. Changing Order: Replication and
Induction in Scientific Practice. Chicago: Univ. Chicago
Press. 2nd ed.
Collins HM, Cox G. 1977. Relativity revisited: Mrs
Keech - a suitable case for special treatment? Soc.
Stud. Sci. 7: 372-80
Collins HM, Harrison RG. 1975. Building a TEA laser: the caprices of
communication. Soc. Stud. Sci. 5:441-50
Collins HM, Pinch Ti. 1982. Frames of Meaning: The Social
Construction of Extraordinary Science. London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul
Collins HM, Pinch TJ. 1993. The Golem: What Everyone Should Know
about Science. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press
Collins, HM, Yearley S. 1992. Epistemological chicken. See Pickering 1992, pp. 301-26
Coulter J. 1975. Perceptual accounts and interpretive asymmetries.
Sociology 17:385-96
Cozzens 5, Gieryn T, eds. 1990. Theories of
Science in Society. Bloomington: Indiana Univ. Press
Dear P. ed. 1991. The Literary Structure of Scientific Argument:
Historical Studies. Philadelphia, PA: Univ. Penn. Press
Dear P. 1995. Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the
Scientific Revolution. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Douglas M. 1986. The social preconditions of radical scepticism. See Law 1986a, pp. 68-87
Durkheim E. [1899] 1972. Selected Writings. (Ed. and transl. A Giddens.) Cambridge: Cambridge
Univ. Press
317
Epstein S. 1993. Impure science: AIDS, activism, and the politics of
knowledge. PhD thesis. Univ. Calif., Berkeley
Feyerabend P. [1975] 1978. Against Method: Outlines of an Anarchistic Theory
of Knowledge. London: Verso
Fuchs S. 1992. The Professional Quest for Truth: A Social Theory of
Knowledge and Science. Albany: State Univ. New York Press
Fujimura J. 1987. Constructing ‘do-able’ problems in
cancer research: articulating alignment. Soc. Stud. Sci. 17:257-93
Fujimura J. 1988. The molecular biological bandwagon in cancer research:
where social worlds meet. Soc. Probl. 35:261-83
Fuller S. 1988. Social Epistemology. Bloomington:
Indiana Univ. Press
Fuller S. 1992. Social epistemology and the research agenda of
science studies. See Pickering 1992, pp. 390-428
Fuller S. 1993. A strategy for making science studies policy relevant. In Controversial Science: From Content to
Contention, ed. T Brante, S Fuller, W Lynch, pp.
107-25. Albany: State Univ. New York
Press
Giddens A. [1976] 1993. New Rules of Sociological Method: A Positive
Critique of Interpretative Sociologies. Stanford, CA: Stanford Univ. Press.
2nd ed.
Gieryn T.
1992. The ballad of Pons and Fleischmann: experiment
and narrative in the (un)making of cold fusion. In The Social Dimensions
of Science, ed. E McMullin, pp. 217-43. Notre
Dame, IN: Univ. Notre Dame Press
Gilbert GN, Mulkay M. 1984. Opening
Pandora’s Box: A Sociological Analysis of Scientists’ Discourse. Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press
Golinski JV.
1990. The theory of practice and the practice of theory: sociological approaches
in the history of science. Isis 81:
492—505
Golinski
JV. 1994. Precision instruments and the demonstrative order of proof in Lavoisier’s chemistry. Osiris
9:30-47
Gooding D. 1985. ‘In nature’s school’: Faraday as an experimentalist. In Faraday
Rediscovered: Essays on the Life and Work of Michael Faraday, 1797-1867, ed.
D Gooding, FAIL James, pp. 106-35. London: Macmillan
Gross P, Levitt N. 1994. Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and Its
Quarrels with Science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press
Hagendijk
R. 1994. Towards a sociology of science. Soc. Stud.
Sci. 24:135-39
Haraway DJ.
1991. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention
of Nature. New York: Routledge
Harding S. 1986. The Science Question in Feminism.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univ. Press
Jasanoff S.
1990. The Fifth Branch: Science Advisers as Policymakers. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard Univ. Press
Jasanoff S.
1992. Science, politics, and the renegotiation of expertise
at EPA. Osiris 7: 195-217
Jasanoff 5,
Markle O, Petersen I, Pinch T, eds. 1994. Handbook of Science and Technology Studies. Beverly
Hills, CA: Sage
Jonsen A, Toulmin S. 1988. The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of
Moral Reasoning. Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press
Jordan K, Lynch M. 1992. The sociology of a genetic engineering
technique: ritual and rationality in the performance of the ‘plasmid prep.’ See
Clarke & Fujimura 1992, pp. 77-114
Keller EF. 1983. A Feeling for the Organism: The Life and Work of
Barbara McClintock. New Haven, Conn.: Yale Univ. Press
Keller EF. 1986. Reflections on Gender and Sjience.
New Haven: CT: Yale Univ. Press
Keller EF. 1988. Feminist perspectives on science studies. Sci. Technol. Hum.
Values 13: 235-49
Knorr-Cetina
KD. 1981a. The Manufacture of Knowledge: An
Essay on the Constructivist and Contextual Nature of Science. Oxford: Pergamon
Knorr-Cetina
KD. 1981b. Social or scientific method or what do we make of the distinction
between the natural and social sciences? Philos.
Soc. Sci. 11:335-59
Kohler RE.
1994. Lords of the Fly: Drosophila Genetics and the Experimental Life. Chicago:
Univ. Chicago Press
Kuhn TS. [1962] 1970. The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions. Chicago: Univ. Chicago / Press. 2nd ed.
Kuhn TS.
1992. The Trouble with the Historical Philosophy of Science. Cambridge,
MA: ept. Hist. Sci., Harvard Univ.
Latour B.
1987. Science in Action: How to Fllow Scientists
and Engineers through Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press
Latour B.
1988a. The Pasteurization of France. (Trans.
A Sheridan, J Law.) Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press
Latour B.
1988b. The politics of explanation: an alternative. See Woolgar
1988b, pp. 155-76
Latour B.
1993. We Have Never Been Modern. (Trans. C Porter.)
Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press
Latour B, Woolgar 5. [1979] 1986. Laboratory
Life: The (Social] Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton Univ. Press. 2nd ed.
Law J. 1974. Theories and methods in the sociology of science: an
interpretative approach. Soc. Sci. Inform. 13:163-72
318
Law J. 1975. Is epistemology redundant? A sociological
view. Philos. Soc. Sci. 5: 317-37
Law J. 1984. How much of society can the sociologist digest at one
sitting? The ‘macro’ and the ‘micro’ revisited for the case of fast food. Stud
Symbol. Interact. 5: 171-96
Law J, ed. 1986a. Power, Action and Belief: A New Sociology of
Knowledge?, Sociol. Rev. Monogr., Vol 32. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
Law J. 1986b. Editor’s introduction: Power/ knowledge and the
dissolution of the sociology of knowledge. See Law 1986a, pp. 1-19
Law J. 1994. Organizing Modernity. Oxford:
Blackwell
Law J, Lodge P. 1984. Science for Social Scientists.
London: Macmillan
Lawrence CJ.
1985. Incommunicable knowledge: science, technology and the clinical art in
Britain 1850-1914. J. Contemp. Hist.
20: 503-20
Livingston E. 1986. The Ethnomethodological
Foundations of Mathematics. London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul
Longino H.
1990. Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific
Inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press
Lynch M. 1985. Art and Artifact in Laboratory Science: A Study of
Shop Work and Shop Talk in a Research Laboratory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
Lynch M. 1988. Alfred Schutz
and the sociology of science. In Worldly
Phenomenology: The Continuing Influence ofAlfred Schutz on North American Human Science, ed. L. Embree, pp. 71-100. Washington DC: Cent. Adv. Res. Phenomenol., and Univ. Press Am.
Lynch M. 1991a. Laboratory space and the technological complex: an
investigation of topical contextures. Sci.
Context 4:51-78
Lynch M. 1991b. Pictures of nothing? Visual construals in social theory.
Sociol. Theory 9:1-21
Lynch M. 1992a. Extending Wittgenstein: The pivotal
move from epistemology to the sociology of science. See Pickering 1992, 215-65
Lynch M. 1992b. Going full circle in the sociology of
knowledge: comment on Lynch and Fuhrman. Sci.
Technol. Hum. Values 17: 228-33
Lynch M. 1993. Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action: Ethnomethodological and Social Studies of Science. Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press
Lynch WT, Fuhrman ER. 1991. Recovering and expanding the normative: Marx
and the new sociology of scientific knowledge. Sci.
Technol. Hum. Values 16:233-48
MacKenzie
D. 1978. Statistical theory and social interests: a case study. Soc. Stud. Sci. 8:35-83
MacKenzie
D. 1981a. Statistics in Britain, 1865-1930: The Social Construction of Scientific
Knowledge. Edinburgh: Edinburgh Univ. Press
MacKenzie
D. 1981b. Interests, positivism and history. Soc.
Stud. Sci. 11:498-504
Martin B. 1993. The critique of science becomes academic. Sc!. Technol. Hum. Values 18:247-59
McHugh P. 1970. On the failure of positivism. In Understanding
Everyday Life: Toward the Reconstruction of
Sociological Knowledge, ed. JD Douglas, pp.320-35. Chicago: Aldine
Merchant C. 1980. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution. New
York: Harper & Row
Merton RK. [1938] 1970. Science,
Technology, and Society in Seventeenth-Century England. New
York: Harper & Row. 2nd ed.
Merton RK. [1945] 1973. Paradigm
for the sociology of knowledge. In
The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, ed.
NW Storer, pp. 7-40. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Morton O, Carr G, eds. 1993. Tests of the Truth: The Experiment in
Modern Science. London: The Economist
Morus I. 1988. The sociology of sparks: an episode in the history and
meaning of electricity. Soc. Stud. Sci. 18:387-417
Mukerji C.
1989. A Fragile Power: Scientists and the State. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton Univ. Press
Mulkay M.
1979. Science and the Sociology of Knowledge.
London: George Allen & Unwin
Mulkay M.
1991. Sociology of Science: A Sociological Pilgrimage. Milton Keynes:
Open Univ. Press/Bloomington: Indiana Univ. Press
Mulkay M,
Potter J, Yearley S. 1983. Why an analysis of
scientific discourse is needed. In Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social
Study of Science, ed. KD Knorr-Cetina, M Mulkay, pp. 171-203. London: Sage
Myers G. 1990. Writing Biology: Texts in the Social
Construction of Scientific Knowledge. Madison: Univ. Wisc. Press
Noble D. 1992. A World Without Women: The Christian Clerical
Culture of Western Science. New York: Knopf
O’Connell I. 1993. Metrology: the creation of universality by the
circulation of particulars. Soc. Stud. Sci. 23:129-73
Ophir A, Shapin S. 1991. The place of knowledge: a methodological
survey. Sci. Context 4:3-21
Parsons T. [1937] 1949. The Structure of Social Action.
New York: Free Press. 2nd ed.
Pickering A, ed. 1992. Science as Practice and Culture.
Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Pickering A. 1993a. The mangle of practice: agency and emergence in the
sociology of science. Am. J. Social. 99:559-89
319
Pickering A. 1993b. Anti-discipline or narratives of
illusion. In Knowledges: Historical
and Critical Studies in Disciplinarity, ed. E
Messer-Davidow, D Shumway,
D Sylvan, pp. 103-22. Charlottesville: Univ. Virginia Press
Pinch TJ. 1985. Towards an analysis of scientific
observation: the externality and evidential significance of observational
reports in physics. Soc. Stud. Sci. 15:3-36
Pinch Ti. 1993. Turn, turn, and turn again: the Woolgar
formula. Sci. Technol.
Hum. Values 18:511-22
Pinch Ti, Pinch Ti. 1988. Reservations about reflexivity and new
literary forms or why let the devil have all the good tunes. See Woolgar 1988b, pp. 178-97
Polanyi M. 1958. Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical
Philosophy. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Pollner M.
1987. Mundane Reason: Reality in Everyday and Sociological Discourse. Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press
Restivo S.
1989. Critical sociology of science. See Chubin & Chu 1989, pp. 57-70
Richards E, Schuster I. 1989. The feminine method as myth and accounting
resource: a challenge to gender studies and the social studies of science. Soc.
Stud. Sci. 19:697-720
Roberts L. 1991. A word and the world: the significance of naming the
calorimeter. Isis 82: 198-222
Rouse J. 1987. Knowledge and Power: Toward a Political Philosophy of
Power. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univ. Press
Rudwick MJS. 1985. The Great Devonian Controversy: The Shaping
of Scientific Knowledge among Gentlemanly Specialists. Chicago: Univ.
Chicago Press
Sacks H. 1984. On doing ‘being ordinary.’ In Structures
of Social Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis, ed. JM Atkinson, J Heritage,
pp. 413-29. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press
Schaffer S. 1988. Astronomers mark time: discipline and the personal
equation. Sci. Context 2:115-45
Schaffer S. 1989. Glass works: Newton’s prisms and the uses of
experiment. In The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences, ed.
D Gooding, Ti Pinch, S Schaffer, pp. 67-104. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press
Schaffer S. 1992a. Self-evidence. Crit. Inquiry 18:327-62
Schaffer S. 1992b. Late Victorian metrology and its instrumentation: a
manufactory of ohms. In Invisible Connections: Instruments, Institutions,
and Science, ed. R Bud, S Cozzens, pp. 23-56.
Bellingham, Wash.: SPIE Optical Engin.
Schiebinger
L. 1989. The Mind Has No Sex? Women in the Origins of
Modern Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press
Scott P, Richards E, Martin B. 1990. Captives of controversy: the myth
of the neutral social researcher in contemporary scientific controversies. Sci. Technol Hum. Values 15:474-94
Shapin S.
1979. The politics of observation: cerebral anatomy and social interests in the
Edinburgh phrenology disputes. In On the Margins of Science: The Social
Construction of Rejected Knowledge, ed. R Wallis, pp. 139-78. Keele: Keele Univ. Press
Shapin S.
1982. History of science and its sociological
reconstructions. Hist. Sci. 20:157-211
Shapin S.
1984a. Pump and circumstance: Robert Boyle’s literary technology. Soc. Stud.
Sci.
14:481-520
Shapin S.
1984b. Talking history: reflections on discourse analysis.
Isis 75:125-30
Shapin S.
1988. The house of experiment in seventeenth-century England.
Isis 79:373-404
Shapin S.
1991a. “The mind is its own place”: science and solitude in seventeenth-century
England. Sci. Context 4:191-218
Shapin S.
1991b. “A scholar and a gentleman”: the problematic identity of the scientific
practitioner in early modern England. Hist.
Sci. 29:279-327
Shapin S.
1992. Discipline and bounding: the history and sociology of science as seen
through the externalism-internalism debate. Hist. Sci. 30:333-69
Shapin S.
1994. A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-Century
England. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Shapin S, Schaffer S. 1985. Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the
Experimental Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press
Simmel G.
1950. The Lie. In The Sociology
of Georg Simniel, ed.
and trans. KH Wolff, pp. 312-16. New York: Free Press
Smith D. 1990. The Conceptual Practices of Power: A Feminist Sociology of Knowledge.
Boston: Northeastern Univ. Press
Star SL. 1989. Regions of the Mind: Brain Research and the Quest for Scientific
Certainty. Stanford, CA: Stanford Univ. Press
Star SL, Griesemer JR. 1989. “Translations”
and boundary objects: amateurs and professionals in Berkeley’s Museum of
Vertebrate Zoology, 1907-39. Soc. Stud. Sci. 19:387-420
Theocharis
T, Psimipoulis M. 1987. Where
science has gone wrong. Nature 329:595-98
Toulmin 5. 1990. Cosmopolis:
The Hidden Agenda of Modernity. New York: Free Press
Travis GDL, Collins HM. 1991. New light on old boys: cognitive and
institutional particu-
320
larism in the peer review system. Sci.
Technol. Hum. Values 16:322-41
Turner SP. 1981. Interpretive charity, Durkheim, and the “strong programme”
in the sociology of science. Philos.
Soc. Sci. 11:231-43
Turner SP. 1989. Truth and decision. See Chubin & Chu 1989, pp. 175-88
Van Helden A. 1994. Telescopes
and authority from Galileo to Cassini. Osiris 9:8-29
Warwick A. 1992-1993. Cambridge mathematics and Cavendish physics: Cunningham,
Campbell and Einstein’s relativity 1905-1911. Stud. Hist.
Philos. Sci. 23:625-56;
24: 1-25
Winch P. 1958. The Idea of a Social Science and Its
Relation to Philosophy. London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul
Wolpert L.
1992. The Unnatural Nature of Science: Why Science Does Not Make (Common)
Sense. London: Faber & Faber
Woolgar S.
1976. Writing an intellectual history of discovery accounts.
Soc. Stud. Sci. 6:395-422
Woolgar S.
1981. Interests and explanation in the social study of
science. Soc. Stud. Sci. 11:365-94
Woolgar S.
1988a. Science: The Very Idea. Chichester: Ellis
Horwood/London & New York: Tavistock
Woolgar S,
ed. 1988b. Knowledge and Reflexivity: New Frontiers in the Sociology of
Knowledge. London: Sage
Woolgar S.
1989. What is the analysis of scientific rhetoric for? A comment on the possible
convergence between rhetorical analysis and social studies of science. Sci. Technol. Hum.
Values 14:47-49
Wynne B. 1992. Carving out science (and politics) in
the regulatory jungle. Soc. Stud. Sci. 22:745-58
Yearley S.
1981. Textual persuasion: the role of social accounting in the construction of scientific
arguments. Philos. Soc. Sci.
11: 409-35
Yearley S.
1982. The relationship between epistemological and sociological cognitive
interests: some ambiguities underlying the use of interest theory in the study
of scientific knowledge. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 13:353-88
Yearley S.
1984. Science and Sociological Practice. Milton
Keynes: Open Univ. Press
Zuckerman H. 1988. The sociology of science. In Handbook of Sociology, ed. N Smelser,
pp. 511-74. Newbury Park, CA: Sage
321
The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
April 2003