The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Harry Hillman Chartrand
April 2002
Joseph A.
Schumpeter
Capitalism, Socialism
and Democracy
Chapter VIII: Monopolistic
Practices
3rd Edition
1950
Harper
Torchbooks, New York, 1962.
Index *
1. Myth of Monopoly Pricing & Output
2. Myth of Restrictive & Regulatory Strategies
3. Myth of
Rigid Prices
4. Myth of Conservation of Existing Capital
5. Myth of
Monopoly
6.
Myth of Perfect Competition
7. Conclusion
* index cnot in original text
WHAT has been
said so far is really sufficient to enable the reader to deal with the large
majority of the practical cases he is likely to meet and to realize the
inadequacy of most of those criticisms of the profit economy which, directly or
indirectly, rely on the absence of perfect competition. Since, however, the bearing of our
argument on some of those criticisms may not be obvious at a glance, it will be
worth our while to elaborate a little in order to make a few points more
explicit.
1. Myth of Monopoly Pricing
& Output
1. We have just seen that,
both as a fact and as a threat, the impact of new things – new technologies for
instance – on the existing structure of an industry considerably reduces the
long-run scope, and importance of practices that aim, through restricting
output, at conserving established positions and at maximizing the profits
accruing to them. We must now recognize the further
fact that restrictive practices of this kind, as far as they are effective,
acquire a new significance in the perennial gale of creative destruction, a
significance which they would not have in a stationary state or in a state of
slow and balanced growth. In either
of these cases restrictive strategy would produce no result other than an
increase in profits at the expense of buyers except that, in the case of
balanced advance, it might still prove to be the easiest and most effective way
of collecting the means by which to finance additional investment. 1 But in the process of creative
destruction, restrictive practices may do much to steady the ship and to
alleviate temporary difficulties. This is in fact a very familiar argument
which always turns up in times of depression and, as everyone knows, has become
very popular with governments and their economic advisers - witness the NRA.
While it has been so much misused
and so faultily acted upon that most economists heartily despise it,
those
1. Theorists are apt to
look upon anyone who admits this possibility as guilty of gross error, and to
prove immediately that financing by borrowing from banks or from private savers
or, in the case of public enterprise, financing from the proceeds of an income
tax is much more rational than is financing from surplus profits collected
through a restrictive policy.
For
some patterns of behavior they are quite right.
For others they are quite wrong.
I believe that both capitalism and
communism of the Russian type belong in the latter category.
But the point is that theoretical
considerations, especially theoretical considerations of the short-run kind,
cannot solve, although they contribute to the solution of, the problem which we
shall meet again in the next part.
87
same advisers who are
responsible for this 2 invariably fail to see its much more general
rationale.
Practically any investment
entails, as a necessary complement of entrepreneurial action, certain
safeguarding activities such as insuring or hedging. Long-range investing under rapidly
changing conditions, especially under conditions that change or may change at
any moment under the impact of new commodities and technologies, is like
shooting at a target that is not only indistinct but moving - and moving jerkily
at that. Hence it becomes necessary
to resort to such protecting devices as patents or temporary secrecy of
processes or, in some cases, long-period contracts secured in advance. But these protecting devices which most
economists accept as normal elements of rational management 3 are
only special cases of a larger class comprising many others which most
economists condemn although they do not differ fundamentally from the recognized
ones.
If for instance a war risk
is insurable, nobody objects to a firm’s collecting the cost of this insurance
from the buyers of its products. But that risk is no less an element in
long-run costs, if there are no facilities for insuring against it, in which
case a price strategy aiming at the same end will seem to involve unnecessary
restriction and to be productive of excess profits. Similarly, if a patent cannot be secured
or would not, if secured, effectively protect, other means may have to be used
in order to justify the investment. Among them are a price policy that will
make it possible to write off more quickly than would otherwise be rational, or
additional investment in order to provide excess capacity to be used only for
aggression or defense. Again, if
long-period contracts cannot be entered into in advance, other means may have to
be devised in order to tie prospective customers to the inveting
firm.
In analyzing such business
strategy ex visu of a given
point of time, the investigating economist or government agent sees price
policies that seem to him predatory and restrictions of output that seem to him
synonymous with loss of opportunities to produce. He does not see that restrictions of this
type are, in the conditions of the perennial gale, incidents, often unavoidable
incidents, of a long-run process of expansion which they protect rather than
impede. There is no more of paradox
in this than there is in saying that motorcars are traveling faster than they
otherwise would because they are provided with
brakes.
2.
In particular, it is easy to show
that there is no sense, and plenty of harm, in a policy that aims at preserving
“price parities.”
3. Some economists,
however, consider that even those devices are obstructions to progress which,
though perhaps necessary in capitalist society, would be absent in a socialist one. There is some truth in this. But that does not affect the proposition
that the protection afforded by patents and so on is, in the conditions of a
profit economy, on balance a propelling and not an inhibiting
factor.
88
Index
2. Myth of Restrictive & Regulatory
Strategies
2. This stands out most
clearly in the case of those sectors of the economy which at any time happen to
embody the impact of new things and methods on the existing industrial
structure. The best way of getting
a vivid and realistic idea of industrial strategy is indeed to visualize the
behavior of new concerns or industries that introduce new commodities or
processes (such as the aluminum industry) or else reorganize a part or the whole
of an industry (such as, for instance, the old Standard Oil
Company).
As we have seen, such
concerns are aggressors by nature and wield the really effective weapon of
competition. Their intrusion can
only in the rarest of cases fail to improve total output in quantity or quality,
both through the new method itself - even if at no time used to full advantage -
and through the pressure it exerts on the preexisting firms. But these aggressors are so circumstanced
as to require, for purposes of attack and defense, also pieces of armor other
than price and quality of their product which, moreover, must be strategically
manipulated all along so that at any point of time they seem to be doing nothing
but restricting their output and keeping prices
high.
On the one hand,
largest-scale plans could in many cases not materialize at all if it were not
known from the outset that competition will be discouraged by heavy capital
requirements or lack of experience, or that means are available to discourage or
checkmate it so as to gain the time and space for further development. Even the conquest of financial control
over competing concerns in otherwise unassailable positions or the securing of
advantages that run counter to the public’s sense of fair play - railroad
rebates - move, as far as long-run effects on total output alone are envisaged,
into a different light; 4 they may be methods for removing
obstacles that the institution of private property puts in the path of progress.
In a socialist society that time
and space would be no less necessary. They would have to be secured by order of
the central authority.
On the other hand,
enterprise would in most cases be impossible if
4.
The
qualification added removes, I think, any just cause for offense that the above
proposition might conceivably cause.
In case that qualification is not
explicit enough. I beg leave to repeat that the moral aspect is in this case, as
it must be in every case, entirely unaffected by an economic argument.
For the rest, let the reader reflect that
even in dealing with indubitably criminal actions every civilized judge and
every civilized jury take account of the ulterior purpose in pursuit of which a
crime has occurred and of the difference it makes whether an action that is a
crime has or has not also effects they consider socially
desirable.
Another objection would be
more to the point.
If an enterprise
can succeed only by such means, does not that prove in itself that it cannot
spell social gain?
A very simple
argument can be framed in support of this view.
But it is subject to a severe
ceteris
paribus proviso.
That is to
say, it holds for conditions which are just about equivalent to excluding the
process of creative destruction - capitalist reality.
On reflection, it will be seen that the
analogy of the practices under discussion with patents is sufficient to show
this.
89
it were not known from the
outset that exceptionally favorable situations are likely to arise which if
exploited by price, quality and quantity manipulation will produce profits
adequate to tide over exceptionally unfavorable situations provided these are
similarly managed. Again this
requires strategy that in the short run is often restrictive. In the majority of successful cases this
strategy just manages to serve its purpose. In some cases, however, it is so
successful as to yield profits far above what is necessary in order to induce
the corresponding investment. These
cases then provide the baits that lure capital on to untried trails. Their presence explains in part how it is
possible for so large a section of the capitalist world to work for nothing: in
the midst of the prosperous twenties just about half of the business
corporations in the United States were run at a loss, at zero profits, or at
profits which, if they had been foreseen, would have been inadequate to call
forth the effort and expenditure involved.
Our argument however
extends beyond the cases of new concerns, methods and industries. Old concerns and established industries,
whether or not directly attacked, still live in the perennial gale. Situations emerge in the process of
creative destruction in which many firms may have to perish that nevertheless
would be able to live on vigorously and usefully if they could weather a
particular storm. Short of such
general crises or depressions, sectional situations arise in which the rapid
change of data that is characteristic of that process so disorganizes an
industry for the time being as to inflict functionless losses and to create
avoidable unemployment. Finally,
there is certainly no point in trying to conserve obsolescent industries
indefinitely; but there is point in trying to avoid their coming down with a
crash and in attempting to turn a rout, which may become a center of cumulative
depressive effects, into orderly retreat. Correspondingly there is, in the case of
industries that have sown their wild oats but are still gaining and not losing
ground, such a thing as orderly advance.
5
5. A good example illustrative of this point - in fact of
much of our general argument - is the postwar history of the automobile and the
rayon industry.
The first
illustrates very well the nature and value of what we might call “edited”
competition.
The bonanza time was
over by about 1916.
A host of firms
nevertheless crowded into the industry afterwards, most of which were eliminated
by 1925.
From a fierce life and
death struggle three concerns emerged that by now account for over 8o per cent
of total sales.
They are under
competitive pressure inasmuch as, in spite of the advantages of an established
position, an elaborate sales and service organization and so on, any failure to
keep up and improve the quality of their products or any attempt at monopolistic
combination would call in new competitors.
Among themselves, the three concerns
behave in a way which should be called corespective rather than competitive:
they refrain from certain aggressive devices (which, by the way, would also be
absent in perfect competition); they keep up with each other and in doing so
play for points at the frontiers.
This has now gone on for upwards of
fifteen years and it is not obvious that if conditions of theoretically perfect
competition had prevailed during that period, better [ * or cheaper cars would
now be offered to the public, or higher wages and more or steadier employment to
the workmen.
The rayon industry had
its bonanza time in the twenties.
It presents the features incident to introducing a commodity into fields
fully occupied before and the policies that impose themselves in such conditions
still more clearly than does the automobile industry.
And there are a number of other
differences.
But fundamentally the
case is similar.
The expansion in
quantity and quality of rayon output is common knowledge.
Yet restrictive policy presided over
this expansion at each individual point of time.]
*
bracketed section of footnote concludes on page
91
90
Index
All this is of course
nothing but the tritest common sense. But it is being overlooked with a
persistence so stubborn as sometimes to raise the question of sincerity. And it follows that, within the process
of creative destruction, all the realities of which theorists are in the habit
of relegating to books and courses on business cycles, there is another side to
industrial self-organization than that which these theorists are contemplating.
“Restraints of trade” of the cartel
type as well as those which merely consist in tacit understandings about price
competition may be effective remedies under conditions of depression. As far as they are, they may in the end
produce not only steadier but also greater expansion of total output than could
be secured by an entirely uncontrolled onward rush that cannot fail to be
studded with catastrophes. Nor can
it be argued that these catastrophes occur in any case. We know what has happened in each
historical case. We have a very
imperfect idea of what might have happened, considering the tremendous pace of
the process, if such pegs had been entirely absent.
Even as now extended
however, our argument does not cover all cases of restrictive or regulating
strategy, many of which no doubt have that injurious effect on the long-run
development of output which is uncritically attributed to all of them. And even in the cases our argument does
cover, the net effect is a question of the circumstances and of the way in which
and the degree to which industry regulates itself in each individual case. It is certainly as conceivable that an
all-pervading cartel system might sabotage all progress as it is that it might
realize, with smaller social and private costs, all that perfect competition is
supposed to realize. This is why
our argument does not amount to a case against state regulation. It does show that there is no general
case for indiscriminate “trust-busting” or for the prosecution of everything
that qualifies as a restraint of trade. Rational as distinguished from vindictive
regulation by public authority turns out to be an extremely delicate problem
which not every government agency, particularly when in full cry against big
business, can be trusted to solve. 6 But our argument, framed to refute
a preva-
6. Unfortunately, this
statement is almost as effective a bar to agreement on policy as the most
thoroughgoing denial of any case for government regulation could be.
In fact it may embitter discussion.
Politicians, public officers and
economists can stand what I may politely term the whole-hog opposition of
“economic royalists.”
Doubts about
their competence, such as crowd upon us particularly when we see the legal mind
at work, are much more difficult for them to stand.
91
lent theory and the
inferences drawn therefrom about the relation between modern capitalism and the
development of total output, only yields another theory, i.e., another
outlook on facts and another principle by which to interpret them. For our purpose that is enough. For the rest, the facts themselves have
the floor.
3. Myth of Rigid Prices
3. Next, a few words on the
subject of Rigid Prices which has been receiving so much attention of late.
It really is but a particular
aspect of the problem we have been discussing. We shall define rigidity as follows: a
price is rigid if it is less sensitive to changes in the conditions of demand
and supply than it would be if perfect competition prevailed. 7
Quantitatively, the extent
to which prices are rigid in that sense depends on the material and the method
of measurement we select and is hence a doubtful matter. But whatever the material or method, it
is certain that prices are not nearly as rigid as they seem to be. There are many reasons why what in effect
is a change in price should not show in the statistical picture; in other words,
why there should be much spurious rigidity. I shall mention only one class of them
which is closely connected with the facts stressed by our
analysis.
I have adverted to the
importance, for the capitalist process in general and for its competitive
mechanism in particular, of the intrusion of new commodities. Now a new commodity may effectively bring
down the preexisting structure and satisfy a given want at much lower prices per
unit of service (transportation service for instance), and yet not a single
recorded price need change in the process; flexibility in the relevant sense may
be accompanied by rigidity in a formal sense. There are other cases, not of this type,
in which price reduction is the sole motive for bringing out a new brand while
the old one is left at the previous quotation - again a price reduction that
does not show. Moreover, the great
majority of new consumers’ goods - particularly all the gadgets of modern life -
are at first introduced in an experimental and unsatisfactory form in which they
could never conquer their potential markets. Improvement in the quality of products is
hence a practically universal feature of the development of individual concerns
and of industries. Whether or not
this improvement involves additional costs, a constant price per unit of an
improving commodity should not be called rigid without further
investigation.
Of course, plenty of cases
of genuine price rigidity remain - of
7. This definition suffices
for our purposes but would not be satisfactory for others.
See D. D. Humphrey’s article in the
Journal of Political Economy, October 1937, and E. S. Mason’s article in
the
Review of Economic Statistics, May 1938.
Professor Mason has shown, among other
things, that contrary to a widespread belief price rigidity is not increasing
or, at all events, that it is no greater than it was forty years ago, a result
which in itself suffices to invalidate some of the implications of the current
doctrine of rigidity.
92
prices which are being kept
constant as a matter of business policy or which remain unchanged because it is
difficult to change, say, a price set by a cartel after laborious negotiations.
In order to appraise the influence
of this fact on the long-run development of output, it is first of all necessary
to realize that this rigidity is essentially a short-run phenomenon. There are no major instances of long-run
rigidity of prices. Whichever
manufacturing industry or group of manufactured articles of any importance we
choose to investigate over a period of time, we practically always find that in
the long run prices do not fail to adapt themselves to technological progress -
frequently they fall spectacularly in response to it 8 - unless
prevented from doing so by monetary events and policies or, in some cases, by
autonomous changes in wage rates which of course should be taken into account by
appropriate corrections exactly as should changes in quality of products. And our previous analysis shows
sufficiently why in the process of capitalist evolution this must be
so.
What the business strategy
in question really aims at - all, in any case, that it can achieve - is to avoid
seasonal, random and cyclical fluctuations in prices and to move only in
response to the more fundamental changes in the conditions that underlie those
fluctuations. Since these more
fundamental changes take time in declaring themselves, this involves moving
slowly by discrete steps - keeping to a price until new relatively durable
contours have emerged into view. In
technical language, this strategy aims at moving along a step function that will
approximate trends. And that is
what genuine and voluntary price rigidity in most cases amounts to. In fact, most economists do admit this,
at least by implication. For though
some of their arguments about rigidity would hold true only if the phenomenon
were a long-run one - for instance most of the arguments averring that price
rigidity keeps the fruits of technological progress from consumers - in practice
they measure and discuss primarily cyclical rigidity and especially the fact
that many prices do not, or do not promptly, fall in recessions and
depressions. The real question is
there-
8. They do not as a rule
fall as they would under conditions of perfect competition.
But this is true only
ceteris paribus,
and this proviso robs the proposition of all practical importance.
I have adverted to this point before and
shall return to it below (
§5).
9. From a welfare
standpoint, it is proper to adopt a definition different from ours, and to
measure price changes in terms of the hours of labor that are currently
necessary to earn the dollars which will buy given quantities of manufactured
consumers’ goods, taking account of changes of quality.
We have already done this in the course
of a previous argument.
A long-run
downward flexibility is then revealed that is truly impressive.
Changes in price level raise another
problem.
So far as they reflect
monetary influences they should be eliminated for most of the purposes of an
investigation into rigidity.
But so
far as they reflect the combined effect of increasing efficiencies in all lines
of production they should not.
93
fore how this short-run
rigidity 10 may affect the long-run development of total output.
Within this question, the only really important issue is this: prices that stay
up in recession or depression no doubt influence the business situation in
those phases of the cycles; if that influence is strongly injurious—making
matters- much worse than they would be with perfect flexibility all round—the
destruction wrought each time might also affect output in the subsequent
recoveries and prosperities and thus permanently reduce the rate of
increase in total output below what it would be in the absence of those
rigidities. Two arguments have been put forth in favor of this
view.
In order to put the first
into the strongest possible light, let us assume that an industry which refuses
to reduce prices in recession goes on selling exactly the same quantity of
product which it would sell if it had reduced them. Buyers are therefore out of pocket by the
amount to which the industry profits from the rigidity. If these buyers are the kind of people
who spend all they can and if the industry or those to whom its net returns go
does not spend the increment it gets but either keeps it idle or repays bank
loans, then total expenditure in the economy may be reduced thereby. If this happens, other industries or
firms may suffer and if thereupon they restrict in turn, we may get a cumulation
of depressive effects. In other
words, rigidity may so influence the amount and distribution of national income
as to decrease balances or to increase idle balances or, if we adopt a popular
misnomer, savings. Such a case is
conceivable. But the reader should
have little difficulty in satisfying himself 11 that its practical
importance, if any, is very small.
The second argument turns
on the dislocating effects price rigidity may exert if, in the individual
industry itself or elsewhere, it leads to an additional restriction of output,
i.e., to a restriction greater than that which must in any case occur during
depression. Since the most
important conductor of those effects is the incident increase in unemployment -
unstabilization of employment is in fact the
indict-
10. It should, however, be
observed that this short run may last longer than the term “short run” usually
implies - sometimes ten years and even longer.
There is not one cycle, but there are
many simultaneous ones of varying duration.
One of the most important ones lasts on
the average about nine years and a half.
Structural changes requiring price
adjustments do in important cases occur in periods of about that length.
The full extent of the spectacular
changes reveals itself only in periods much longer than this.
To do justice to aluminum, rayon, or
motorcar prices one must survey a period of about forty-five
years.
11. The best method of
doing this is to work out carefully
all the assumptions involved, not
only in the strong case imagined but also in the weaker cases that are less
unlikely to occur in practice.
Moreover, it should not be forgotten that
the profit due to keeping prices up may be the means of avoiding bankruptcy or
at least the necessity of discontinuing operations, both of which might be much
more effective in starting a downward “vicious spiral” than is a possible
reduction in total expenditure.
See
the comments on the second argument.
94
ment most commonly directed
against price rigidity - and the consequent decrease in total expenditure, this
argument then follows in the tracks of the first one. Its practical weight is considerably
reduced, although economists greatly differ as to the extent, by the
consideration that in the most conspicuous cases price rigidity is motivated
precisely by the low sensitiveness of demand to short-run price changes within
the practicable range. People who
in depression worry about their future are not likely to buy a new car even if
the price were reduced by 25 per cent, especially if the purchase is easily
postponable and if the reduction induces expectations of further
reductions.
Quite irrespective of this
however, the argument is inconclusive because it is again vitiated by a
ceteris paribus clause that is inadmissible in dealing with our process
of creative destruction. From the
fact, so far as it is a fact, that at more flexible prices greater quantities
could ceteris paribus be sold, it does not follow that either the output
of the commodities in question, or total output and hence employment, would
actually be greater. For inasmuch as we may assume that the refusal to lower
prices strengthens the position of the industries which adopt that policy either
by increasing their revenue or simply by avoiding chaos in their market – that
is to say, so far as this policy is something more than a mistake on their part
– it may make fortresses out of what otherwise might be centers of
devastation. As we have seen
before, from a more general standpoint, total output and employment may well
keep on a higher level with the restrictions incident to that policy than they
would if depression were allowed to play havoc with the price structure.
12 In other
words, under the conditions created by capitalist evolution, perfect and
universal flexibility of prices might in depression further unstabilize the
system, instead of stabilizing it as it no doubt would under the conditions
envisaged by general theory. Again
this is to a large extent recognized in those cases in which the economist is in
sympathy with the interests immediately concerned, for instance in the case of
labor and of agriculture; in those cases he admits readily enough that what
looks like rigidity may be no more than regulated
adaptation.
Perhaps the reader feels
some surprise that so little remains of a doctrine of which so much has been
made in the last few years. The
rigidity of prices has become, with some people, the outstanding defect of the
capitalist engine and – almost - the fundamental factor in the explanation of
depressions. But there is nothing
to wonder at in this. Individuals
and groups snatch at anything that will qualify as a discovery lending support
to the political tendencies of the hour. The
12. The theorist’s way to
put the point is that in depression demand curves might shift downwards much
more violently if all pegs were withdrawn from under all
prices.
95
doctrine of price rigidity, with a modicum of truth to its credit, is not the
worst case of this kind by a long way.
4. Myth of
Conservation of Existing Capital
4. Another doctrine has
crystallized into a slogan, viz., that in the era of big business the
maintenance of the value of existing investment - conservation of capital
-becomes the chief aim of entrepreneurial activity and bids fair to put a stop
to all cost-reducing improvement. Hence the capitalist order becomes
incompatible with progress.
Progress entails, as we
have seen, destruction of capital values in the strata with which the new
commodity or method of production competes. I n perfect competition the old
investments must be adapted at a sacrifice or abandoned; but when there is no
perfect competition and when each industrial field is controlled by a few big
concerns, these can in various ways fight the threatening attack on their
capital structure and try to avoid losses on their capital accounts; that is to
say, they can and will fight progress itself.
So far as this doctrine
merely formulates a particular aspect of restrictive business strategy, there is
no need to add anything to the argument already sketched in this chapter. Both as to the limits of that strategy
and as to its functions in the process of creative destruction, we should only
be repeating what has been said before. This becomes still more obvious if we
observe that conserving capital values is the same thing as conserving profits.
Modern theory tends in fact to use
the concept Present Net Value of Assets (= capital values) in place of the
concept of Profits. Both asset
values and profits are of course not being simply conserved but
maximized.
But the point about the
sabotage of cost-reducing improvement still calls for comment in passing. As a little reflection will show, it is
sufficient to consider the case of a concern that controls a technological
device - some patent, say -the use of which would involve scrapping some or all
of its plant and equipment. Will
it, in order to conserve its capital values, refrain from using this device when
a management not fettered by capitalist interests such as a socialist management
could and would use it to the advantage of all?
Again it is tempting to
raise the question of fact. The
first thing a modern concern does as soon as it feels that it can afford it is
to establish a research department every member of which knows that his bread
and butter depends on his success in devising improvements. This practice does not obviously suggest
aversion to technological progress.
Nor can we in reply be referred to the cases in which patents acquired by
business concerns have not been used promptly or not used at all. For there may be perfectly good reasons
for this; for example, the patented process may turn out to be no good or at
least not to be in shape to warrant application on a commercial basis. Neither the inventors themselves nor the
investigating economists
96
Index
or government officials are
unbiased judges of this, and from their remonstrances or reports we may easily
get a very distorted picture. 13
But we are concerned with a
question of theory. Everyone agrees
that private and socialist managements will introduce improvements if, with the
new method of production, the total cost per unit of production, is expected to
be smaller than the prime cost per unit of product with the method actually in
use. If this condition is not
fulfilled, then it is
held that private management will not adopt a cost-reducing method
until the existing plant and equipment is entirely written off, whereas
socialist management would, to the social advantage, replace the old by any new
cost-reducing method as soon as such a method becomes available, i.e., without
regard to capital values. This
however is not so. 14
Private management, if
actuated by the profit motive, cannot be interested in maintaining the values of
any given building or machine any more than a socialist management would be.
All that private management tries
to do is to maximize the present net value of total assets which is equal to the
discounted value of expected net returns.
This amounts to saying that it will always adopt a new method of
production which it believes will yield a larger stream of future income per
unit of the corresponding stream of future outlay, both discounted to the
present, than does the method actually in use. The value of past investment, whether or
not paralleled by a bonded debt that has to be amortized, does not enter at all
except in the sense and to the extent that it would also have to enter into the
calculation underlying the decisions of a socialist management. So far as the use of the old machines
saves future costs as compared with the immediate introduction of the new
methods, the remainder of their service value is of course an element of the
decision for both the capitalist and the socialist manager; otherwise bygones
are bygones for both of them and any attempt to conserve the value of past
investment would conflict as much with the rules following from the profit
motive as it would conflict with the rules set for the behavior of the
socialist
13.
Incidentally, it should be noticed that
the kind of restrictive practice under discussion, granted that it exists to a
significant extent, would not be without compensatory effects on social welfare.
In fact, the same critics who talk
about sabotage of progress at the same time emphasize the
social losses
incident to the pace of capitalist progress, particularly the unemployment which
that pace entails and which slower advance might mitigate to some extent.
Well, is technological progress too quick
or too slow for them?
They had
better make up their minds.
14. It should be observed
that even if the argument were correct, it would still be inadequate to support
the thesis that capitalism is, under the conditions envisaged, “incompatible
with technological progress.”
All
that it would prove is, for some cases, the presence of a lag of ordinarily
moderate length in the introduction of new methods.
97
It is however not true that
private firms owning equipment the value of which is endangered by a new method
which they also control - if they do not control it, there is no problem and no
indictment - will adopt the new method only if total unit cost with it is
smaller than prime unit cost with the old one, or if the old investment has been
completely written off according to the schedule decided on before the new
method presented itself. For if
the new machines when installed are expected to outlive the rest of the period
previously set for the use of the old machines, their discounted remainder value
as of that date is another- asset to be taken account of. Nor is it true, for analogous reasons,
that a socialist management, if acting rationally, would always and immediately
adopt any new method which promises to produce at smaller total unit costs or
that this would be to the social advantage.
There is however another
element 15 which profoundly affects behavior in this matter and which
is being invariably overlooked. This is what might be called ex ante
conservation of capital in expectation of further improvement. Frequently, if not in most cases, a
going concern does not simply face the question whether or not to adopt a
definite new method of production that is the best thing out and in the form
immediately available, can be expected to retain that position for some length
of time. A new type of machine is
in general but a link in a chain of improvements and may presently become
obsolete. In a case like this it
would obviously not be rational to follow the chain link by link regardless of
the capital loss to be suffered each time. The real question then is at which link
the concern should take action. The
answer must be in the nature of a compromise between considerations that rest
largely on guesses. But it will as
a rule involve some waiting in order to see how the chain behaves. And to the outsider this may well look
like trying to stifle improvement in order to conserve existing capital values. Yet even the most patient of comrades
would revolt if a socialist management were so foolish as to follow the advice
of the theorist and to keep on scrapping plant and equipment every year
5. Myth of Monopoly
5. I have entitled this
chapter as I did because most of it deals with the facts and problems that
common parlance associates with monopoly or monopolistic practice. So far I have as much as possible
refrained from using those terms in order to reserve for a separate section some
comments on a few topics specifically connected with them. Nothing will be said however that we have
not already met in one form or another.
(a) To begin with, there is
the term itself. Monopolist means
Single
15. There are of course
many other elements.
The reader
will please understand that in dealing with a few questions of principles it is
impossible to do full justice to any of the topics touched
upon.
98
Seller. Literally therefore anyone is a
monopolist who sells anything that is not in every respect, wrapping and
location and service included, exactly like what other people sell: every
grocer, or every haberdasher, or every seller of “Good Humors” on a road that is
not simply lined with sellers of the same brand of ice cream. This however is not what we mean when
talking about monopolies. We mean
only those simgle sellers whose markets are not open to the intrusion of
would-be producers of the same commodity and of actual producers of similar ones
or, speaking slightly more technically, only those single sellers who face a
given demand schedule that is severely independent of their own action as well
as of any reactions to their actions by other sellers. The traditional Cournot-Marshall theory
of monopoly as extended and amended by later authors holds only if we define it
in this way and there is, so it seems, no point in calling anything a monopoly
to which that theory does not apply.
But if accordingly we do
define it like this, then it becomes evident immediately that pure cases of
long-run monopoly must be of the rarest occurrence and that even tolerable
approximations to the requirements of the concept must be still rarer than are
cases of perfect competition. The
power to exploit at pleasure a given pattern of demand - or one that changes
independently of the monopolist’s action and of the reactions it provokes - can
under the conditions of intact capitalism hardly persist for a period long
enough to matter for the analysis of total output, unless buttressed by public
authority, for instance, in the case of fiscal monopolies. A modern business concern not so
protected - i.e., even if protected by import duties or import prohibitions
- and yet wielding that power (except temporarily) is not easy to find or even
to imagine. Even railroads and
power and light concerns had first to create the demand for their services and,
when they had done so, to defend their market against competition. Outside the field of public utilities,
the position of a single seller can in general be conquered - and retained for
decades-only on the condition that he does not behave like a monopolist. Short-run monopoly will be touched upon
presently.
Why then all this talk
about monopoly? The answer is not
without interest for the student of the psychology of political discussion.
Of course, the concept of monopoly
is being loosely used just like any other.
People speak of a country’s having a monopoly of something or other
16 even if the industry in question is highly competitive and so
16. These so-called
monopolies have of late come to the fore in connection with the proposal to
withhold certain materials from aggressor nations.
The lessons of this discussion have some
bearing upon our problem by way of analogy.
At first, much was thought of the
possibilities of that weapon.
Then,
on looking more closely at it, people found their lists of such materials to be
shrinking, because it became increasingly clear that there are very few things
that cannot be either produced or substituted for in the areas in question.
And finally a suspicion began [*to
dawn to the effect that even though some pressure can be exerted on them in the
short run, long-run developments might eventually destroy practically all that
was left on the lists.]
* bracketed
section of footnote concludes on page
100
99
on. But this is not all. Economists, government agents,
journalists and politicians in this country obviously love the word because it
has come to be a term of opprobrium which is sure to rouse the public’s
hostility against any interest so labeled. In the Anglo-American world monopoly has
been cursed and associated with functionless exploitation ever since, in the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, it was English administrative practice to
create monopoly positions in large numbers which, on the one hand, answered
fairly well to the theoretical pattern of monopolist behavior and, on the other
hand, fully justified the wave of indignation that impressed even the great
Elizabeth.
Nothing is so retentive as
a nation’s memory. Our time offers
other and more important instances of a -nation’s reaction to what happened
centuries ago. That practice made
the English-speaking public so monopoly-conscious that it acquired a habit of
attributing to that sinister power practically everything it disliked about
business. To the typical liberal
bourgeois in particular, monopoly became the father of almost all abuses - in
fact, it became his pet bogey. Adam
Smith, 17 thinking primarily of monopolies of the Tudor and Stuart
type, frowned on them in awful dignity. Sir Robert Peel - who like most
conservatives occasionally knew how to borrow from the arsenal of the demagogue
- in his famous epilogue to his last period of office that gave so much offense
to his associates, spoke of a monopoly of bread or wheat, though English grain
production was of course perfectly competitive in spite of protection. 18
And in this country monopoly
is being made practically synonymous with any large-scale
business.
(b) The theory of simple
and discriminating monopoly teaches that, excepting a limiting case, monopoly
price is higher and monopoly output smaller than competitive price and
competitive output. This is true
provided that the method and organization of production - and everything else -
are exactly the same in both cases. Actually
how-
17.
There was more excuse for that uncritical
attitude in the case of Adam Smith and the classics in general than there is in
the case of their successors because big business in our sense had not then
emerged.
But even so they went too
far.
In part this was due to the
fact that they had no satisfactory theory of monopoly which induced them not
only to apply the term rather promiscuously (Adam Smith and even Senior
interpreted for instance the rent of land as a monopoly gain) but also to look
upon the monopolists’ power of exploitation as practically unlimited which is of
course wrong even for the most extreme cases.
18. This instance
illustrates the way in which the term keeps on creeping into illegitimate uses.
Protection of agriculture and a
monopoly of agrarian products are entirely different things.
The struggle was over protection and not
over a non-existent cartel of either landowners or farmers.
But in fighting protection it was just as
well to beat up for applause.
And
there was evidently no simpler means of doing so than by calling protectionists
monopolists.
100
Index
ever, there are superior
methods available to the monopolists which either are not available at all to a
crowd of competitors or are not available to them so readily: for there are
advantages which, though not strictly unattainable on the competitive level of
enterprise, are as a matter of fact secured only on the monopoly level, for
instance, because monopolization may increase the sphere of influence of the
better, and decrease the sphere of influence of the inferior, brains
19 or because the monopoly enjoys a disproportionately higher
financial standing. Whenever this
is so, then that proposition is no longer true. In other words, this element of
the case for competition may fail completely because monopoly process are not
necessarily higher or monopoly outputs smaller than competitive prices and
outputs would be, at the levels of productive and organizational efficiency that
are within the reach of the type of firm compatible with the competitive
hypothesis.
There cannot be any
reasonable doubt that under the conditions of our epoch such superiority is as a
matter of fact the outstanding feature of the typical large-scale unit of
control, though mere size is neither necessary nor sufficient for it. The units not only arise in the process
of creative destruction and function in a way entirely different from the static
schema, but in many cases of decisive importance they provide the necessary form
for the achievement. They largely
create what they exploit. Hence the
usual conclusion about their influence on long-run output would be invalid even
if they were genuine monopolies in the technical sense of the term.
Motivation is quite
immaterial. Even if the opportunity
to set monopolist prices were the sole object, the pressure of the improved
methods or of a huge apparatus would in general tend to shift the point of the
monopolist’s optimum toward or beyond the competitive cost price in the above
sense, thus doing the work - partly, wholly, or more than wholly - of the
competitive mechanism, 20
even if
19. The reader should
observe that while, as a broad rule, that particular type of superiority is
simply indisputable, the inferior brains, especially if their owners are
entirely eliminated, are not likely to admit it and that the public’s and the
recording economists’ hearts go out to them and not to the others.
This may have something to do with a
tendency to discount the cost or quality advantages of quasi-monopolist
combination that is at present as pronounced as was the exaggeration of them in
the typical prospectus or announcement of sponsors of such
combinations.
20. The Aluminum Company of
America is not a monopoly in the technical sense as defined
above, among other reasons because it had to build up its demand schedule, which
fact suffices to exclude a behavior conforming to the Cournot-Marshall schema.
But most economists call it so and
in the dearth of genuine cases we will for the purposes of this note do the
same.
From 1890 to 1929 the price
of the basic product of this single seller fell to about
12
per cent or, correcting for the change in price level (B.L.S.
index of wholesale prices), to about 8.8 per cent.
Output rose from
30 metric tons to 103,400. .
Protection by patent ceased in 1909.
Argument from costs and profits in
criticism of this “monopoly” must [* take it for granted that a multitude of
competing firms would have been about equally successful in cost-reducing
research, in the economic development of the productive apparatus, in teaching
new uses for the product and in avoiding wasteful breakdown.
This is, in fact, being assumed by
criticism of this kind; i.e., the propelling factor of modern capitalism is
being assumed away.] *
bracketed
section of footnote concludes on page
102
101
striction is practiced
and excess capacity is in evidence all along. Of course if the methods of production, organization and
so on are not improved by or in connection with monopolization as is the case
with an ordinary cartel, the classical theorem about monopoly price and output
comes into its own again. 21 So does another popular idea, viz.,
that monopolization has a soporific effect. For this, too, it is not difficult to
find examples. But no general
theory should be built upon it. For, especially in manufacturing
industry, a monopoly position is in general no cushion to sleep on. As it can be gained, so it can be
retained only by alertness and energy. What soporific influence there is in
modern business is due to another cause that will be mentioned
later.
(c) In the short run,
genuine monopoly positions or positions approximating monopoly are much more
frequent. The grocer in a village
on the
Ohio may be a true monopolist for hours or even days during
an inundation. Every successful
corner may spell monopoly for the moment. A firm specializing in paper labels for
beer bottles may be so circumstanced - potential competitors realizing that what
seem to be good profits would be immediately destroyed by their entering the
field - that it can move at pleasure on a moderate but still finite stretch of
the demand curve, at least until the metal label smashes that demand curve to
pieces.
New methods of production
or new commodities, especially the latter, do not per se confer monopoly, even
if used or produced by a single firm.
The product of the new method has to compete with the products of the old
ones and the new commodity has to be introduced, i.e. its demand schedule has to
be built up. As a rule neither
patents nor monopolistic practices avail against that. But they may in cases of spectacular
superiority of the new device, particularly if it can be leased like shoe
machinery; or in cases of new commodities, the permanent demand schedule for
which has been established before the patent has
expired.
Thus it is true that there
is or may be an element of genuine monopoly gain in those entrepreneurial
profits which are the prizes offered by capitalist society to the successful
innovator. But the quantitative
importance of that element, its volatile nature and its function in the process
in which it emerges put it in a class by itself. The main value to a concern of a single
seller position that is secured by patent or monopolistic strategy does not
consist so much in the opportunity
21. See however
supra §
1.
102
to behave temporarily
according to the monopolist schema, as in the protection it affords against
temporary disorganization of the market and the space it secures for long-range
planning. Here however the argument merges into the analysis submitted
before.
6. Myth of Perfect Competition
6.
Glancing back we realize that most of the facts and
arguments touched upon in this chapter tend to dim the halo that once surrounded
perfect competition as much as they suggest a more favorable view of its
alternative. I will now briefly
restate our argument from this angle.
Traditional theory itself,
even within its chosen precincts of a stationary or steadily growing economy,
has since the time of Marshall and Edgeworth been discovering an increasing
number of exceptions to the old propositions about perfect competition and,
incidentally, free trade, that have shaken that unqualified belief in its
virtues cherished by the generation which flourished between Ricardo and
Marshall – roughly, J. S. Mill’s generation in England and Francesco Ferrara s
on the Continent. Especially the
propositions that a perfectly competitive system is ideally economical of
resources and allocates them in a way that is optimal with respect to a given
distribution of income – propositions very relevant to the question of the
behavior of output – cannot be held with the old confidence.
22
Much more serious is the
breach made by more recent work in the field of dynamic theory (Frisch,
Tinbergen, Roos, Hicks and others).
Dynamic analysis is the analysis of sequences in time. In explaining why a certain economic
quantity, for instance a price, is what we find it to be at a given moment, it
takes into consideration not only the state of other economic quantities at the
same moment, as static theory does, but also their state at preceding points of
time, and the expectations about their future values. Now the first thing we discover in
working out the propositions that thus relate quantities belonging to different points of time 23
is the fact that, once equilibrium has been destroyed by some disturbance,
the process of establishing a new one is not so sure and prompt and economical
as the old theory of perfect competition made it out to be; and the possibility
that the very struggle for adjustment might lead such a system farther away from
instead of nearer to a new equilibrium. This will happen in most cases unless the
disturbance is small. In many
cases, lagged adjustment is sufficient to produce this
result.
All I can do here is to
illustrate by the oldest, simplest and most familiar example. Suppose that demand and intended
supply are in
22. Since we cannot enter
into the subject,
I will refer
the
reader to Mr. R. F. Kahn’s
paper entitled “Some Notes on Ideal Output”
(Economic Journal for March
1935), which covers much of
this ground.
23. The term dynamics is
loosely used and carries many different meanings.
The above definition was formulated by
Ragnar Frisch.
103
equilibrium in a perfectly
competitive market for wheat, but that bad weather reduces the crop below what
farmers intended to supply. If
price rises accordingly and the farmers thereupon produce that quantity of wheat
which it would pay them to produce if that new price were the equilibrium price,
then a slump in the wheat market will ensue in the following year. If now the farmers correspondingly
restrict production, a price still higher than in the first year may result to
induce a still greater expansion of production than occurred in the second year.
And so on (as far as the pure logic
of the process is concerned) indefinitely. The reader will readily perceive, from a
survey of the assumptions involved, that no great fear need be entertained of
ever higher prices’ and ever greater outputs’ alternating till doomsday. But even if reduced to its proper
proportions, the phenomenon suffices to show up glaring weaknesses in the
mechanism of perfect competition. As soon as this is realized much of the
optimism that used to grace the practical implications of the theory of this
mechanism passes out through the ivory gate.
But from our standpoint we
must go further than that. 24 If we try to visualize how perfect
competition works or would work in the process of creative destruction, we
arrive at a still more discouraging result. This will not surprise us, considering
that all the essential facts of that process are absent from the general schema
of economic life that yields the traditional propositions about perfect
competition. At the risk of
repetition I will illustrate the point once more.
Perfect competition implies
free entry into every industry. It
is quite true, within that general theory, that free entry into all industries
is a condition for optimal allocation of resources and hence for maximizing
output. If our economic world
consisted of a number of established industries producing familiar commodities
by established and substantially invariant methods and if nothing happened
except that additional men and additional savings combine in order to set up new
firms of the existing type, then impediments to their entry into any industry
they wish to enter would spell loss to the community. But perfectly free entry into a new field may make it
impos-
24. It should be observed that the defining feature of dynamic
theory has nothing to do with the nature of the economic reality to which it is
applied. It is a general method of
analysis rather than a study of a particular process. We can use it in order to analyze a
stationary economy, just as an evolving one can be analyzed by means of the
methods of statics (“comparative statics”). Hence dynamic theory need not take, and
as a matter of fact has not taken, any special cognizance of the process of
creative destruction which we have taken to be the essence of capitalism. It is no doubt better equipped than is
static theory to deal with many questions of mechanism that arise in the
analysis of that process. But it is not an analysis of that
process itself, and it treats the resulting individual disturbances of given
states and structures just as it treats other disturbances. To judge the functioning of perfect
competition from the standpoint of capitalist evolution is therefore not the
same thing as judging it from the standpoint of dynamic
theory.
104
sible to enter at all. The introduction of new methods of
production and new commodities is hardly conceivable with perfect – and
perfectly prompt – competition from the start. And this means that the bulk of what we
call economic progress is incompatible with it. As a matter of fact, perfect competition
is and always has been temporarily suspended whenever anything new is being
introduced – automatically or by measures devised for the purpose – even in
otherwise perfectly competitive conditions.
Similarly, within the
traditional system the usual indictment of rigid prices stands all right. Rigidity is a type of resistance to
adaptation that perfect and prompt competition excludes. And for the kind of adaptation and for
those conditions which have been treated by traditional theory, it is again
quite true that such resistance spells loss and reduced output. But we have seen that in the spurts and
vicissitudes of the process of creative destruction the opposite may be true:
perfect and instantaneous flexibility may even produce functionless
catastrophes. This of course can
also be established by the general dynamic theory which, as mentioned above,
shows that there are attempts at adaptation that intensify
disequilibrium.
Again, under its own
assumptions, traditional theory is correct in holding that profits above what is
necessary in each individual case to call forth the equilibrium amount of means
of production, entrepreneurial ability included, both indicate and in themselves
imply net social loss and that business strategy that aims at keeping them alive
is inimical to the growth of total output. Perfect competition would prevent or
immediately eliminate such surplus profits and leave no room for that strategy.
But since in the process of
capitalist evolution these profits acquire new organic functions –I do not want
to repeat what they are – that fact cannot any longer be unconditionally
credited to the account of the perfectly competitive model, so far as the
secular rate of increase in total output is
concerned.
Finally, it can indeed be
shown that, under the same assumptions which amount to excluding the most
characteristic features of capitalist reality, a perfectly competitive economy
is comparatively free from waste and in particular from those kinds of waste
which we most readily associate with its counterpart. But this does not tell us anything about
how its account looks under the conditions set by the process of creative
destruction.
On the one hand, much of
what without reference to those conditions would appear to be unrelieved waste
ceases to qualify as such when duly related to them. The type of excess capacity for example
that owes its existence to the practice of “building ahead of demand” or to the
practice of providing capacity for the cyclical peaks of demand would in a
regime of perfect competition be much reduced. But when all the facts of the case
are taken into consideration,
105
it is no longer correct to
say that perfect competition wins out on that score. For though a concern that has to accept
and cannot set prices would, in fact, use all of its capacity that can produce
at marginal costs covered by the ruling prices, it does not follow that it would
ever have the quantity and quality of capacity that big business has created and
was able to create precisely because it is in a position to use it
“strategically.” Excess capacity of
this type may – it does in some and does not in other cases –constitute a reason
for claiming superiority for a socialist economy. But it should not without qualification
be listed as a claim to superiority of the perfectly competitive species of
capitalist economy as compared with the “monopoloid”
species.
On the other hand, working
in the conditions of capitalist evolution, the perfectly competitive arrangement
displays wastes of its own. The
firm of this type that is compatible with perfect competition is in many cases
inferior in internal, especially technological efficiency. If it is then it wastes opportunities.
It may also in its endeavors to
improve its methods of production waste capital because it is in a less
favorable position to evolve and to judge new possibilities. And, as we have seen before, a perfectly
competitive industry is much more apt to be routed – and to scatter the bacilli
of depression – under the impact of progress or of external disturbance than is
bog business. In the last resort,
American agriculture, English coal mining, the English textile industry are
costing consumers much more and are affecting total output much more
injuriously than they would if controlled, each of them, by a dozen good
brains.
7. Conclusion
Thus it is not sufficient
to argue that because perfect competition is impossible under modern industrial
conditions - or because it always has been impossible - the large-scale
establishment or unit of control must be accepted as a necessary evil
inseparable from the economic progress which it is prevented from sabotaging by
the forces inherent in its productive apparatus. What we have got to accept is that it
has come to be the most powerful engine of that progress and in particular of
the long-run expansion of total output not only in spite of, but to a
considerable extent through, the strategy which looks so restrictive when viewed
in the individual case and from the individual point of time. In this respect, perfect competition is
not only impossible but inferior
and has no title to being set up as a model of ideal efficiency. It is hence a mistake to base the theory
of government regulation of industry on the principle that big business should
be made to work as the respective industry would work in perfect competition.
And socialists should rely for
their criticisms on the virtues of a socialist economy rather than on those of
the competitive model.
106
APA
Home Page