The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
May 2003
Nathan Rosenberg
Exploring the Black Box:
Technology, economics and history
3
Joseph Schumpeter: radical economist
Cambridge
University Press
Cambridge,
U.K. 1994
pp.
47-61
Index
II - Stationary Capitalism
as a Contradiction in Terms
III – Schumpeterian
Competition
IV – The Growth and
Limitations of Rationality
HHC –
titling and index added
This chapter will deal with Schumpeter’s book, Capitalism, Socialism
and Democracy, as the mature statement of the most radical scholar in the
discipline of economics in the twentieth century.
Of course, I do not mean to suggest that Joseph Schumpeter held views
on the organization of the economy, or society generally, that make it
appropriate to label him as a radical in the political sense. In his social and political views Schumpeter
was anything but radical. In fact, one
could make a case - although I do not propose to do so - that Schumpeter was
not merely conservative in his social views, but reactionary. In his most private thoughts, as suggested by
a recent biography, he seemed to possess an insatiable longing for the glorious
later days of the Hapsburg monarchy. Moreover,
the most charitable characterization of his attitude toward Nazi Germany in the
darkest days of the 1930s and the Second World War is that he was ambivalent.
The reason I propose to call Schumpeter a radical is that he urged the
rejection of the most central and precious tenets of neo-classical theory. Indeed, I want to insist that very little of
the complex edifice of neo-classical economics, as it existed in the late 1930s
and 1940s, survives the sweep of Schumpeter’s devastating assaults. But in examining Schumpeter’s criticisms, it
is not my primary intention to enlist his authority in an attack upon
neo-classical economics. Rather, I
propose to show that the quintessential, later Schumpeter, the author of Capitalism,
Socialism and Democracy, held views that were not only genuinely radical,
but that are deserving of far more serious attention than they receive today,
even, or perhaps especially,
This chapter was first presented at the
meetings of the Schumpeter Society in Kyoto, in August, 1992. That meeting
marked the fiftieth anniversary of the publication of Capitalism, Socialism,
and Democracy.
47
from scholars who think of themselves as working within the
Schumpeterian tradition. While this
chapter focuses on Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, I draw upon
Schumpeter’s other writings to round out the argument and interpretation that I
am proposing.
II - Stationary Capitalism as a
Contradiction in Terms
I begin by quoting from Schumpeter’s preface to the Japanese edition of
The Theory of Economic Development, for in that preface Schumpeter
sketches out what is probably the most precise and succinct statement of his
own intellectual agenda that he ever committed to print. That agenda focuses not only upon the
understanding of how the economic system generates economic change, but also
upon how that change occurs as a result of the working out of purely endogenous
forces:
If my Japanese readers asked me before opening the
book what it is that I was aiming at when I wrote it, more than a quarter of a
century ago, I would answer that I was trying to construct a theoretic model of
the process of economic change in time, or perhaps more clearly, to answer the question
how the economic system generates the force which incessantly transforms it...
I felt very strongly that there was a source of energy within the economic
system which would of itself disrupt any equilibrium that might be attained. If this is so, then there must be a purely
economic theory of economic change which does not merely rely on external
factors propelling the economic system from one equilibrium
to another. It is such a theory that I
have tried to build. [1]
It should be noted that these words were published in 1937, when
Schumpeter was, as we know, already at work on Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy. In fact, I regard Capitalism,
Socialism and Democracy as the fulfillment of precisely the intellectual
agenda that Schumpeter articulated in the passage to his Japanese readers that
I have just quoted.
Of course, an account of how and why economic change took place was
precisely something that could not be provided within the “rigorously static”
framework of neo-classical equilibrium analysis, as Schumpeter referred to it. Schumpeter also observed that it was Walras’ view that economic theory was only capable of
examining a “stationary process,” that is, “a process which actually does not
change of its own initiative, but merely produces constant rates of real income
as it flows along in time.” As
Schumpeter interprets Walras:
1. Joseph Schumpeter, Preface to Japanese edition of Theorie Der Wirtschaftlichen Eniwicklung, as
translated by I. Nakayama and S. Tobata, Tokyo, Iwanami Shoten,
1937. As reprinted in Essays of J.A.
Schumpeter, ed. Richard V. Clemence,
Addison-Wesley, Cambridge (MA), 1951, p. 158.
48
He would have said (and, as a matter of fact, he did
say it to me the only time that I had the opportunity to converse with him)
that of course economic life is essentially passive and merely adapts itself to
the natural and social influences which may be acting on it, so that the theory
of a stationary process constitutes really the whole of theoretical economics
and that as economic theorists we cannot say much about the factors that
account for historical change, but must simply register them. [2]
The critical point here is that Schumpeter directly rejects the view of
Walras that economic theory must be confined to the
study of the stationary process, and that it cannot go farther than
demonstrating how departures from equilibrium, such as might be generated by a
growth in population or in savings, merely set into motion forces that restore
the system to an equilibrium path. In
proposing to develop a theory showing how a stationary process can be disturbed
by internal as well as external forces, Schumpeter is suggesting that the
essence of capitalism lies not in equilibrating forces but in the inevitable
tendency of that system to depart from equilibrium - in a word, to disequilibrate. Equilibrium analysis fails to capture the
essence of capitalist reality. Lest
there should be any doubt about Schumpeter’s position on this critical matter,
we cite his own forceful formulation: “Whereas a stationary feudal economy
would still be a feudal economy, and a stationary socialist economy would still
be a socialist economy, stationary capitalism is a contradiction in terms.” [3]
Although Schumpeter did in fact make important use of Walrasian general equilibrium in his analysis of the
circular flow in a stationary state, he used the concept precisely as a means
of demonstrating how capitalist economies would behave if they were deprived
of their essential feature: that is, innovative activities that are the
primary generator of economic change.
It is important to understand this methodological use that Schumpeter
makes of the neo-classical analysis of a stationary economic process. As Schumpeter stated: “In
appraising the performance of competitive enterprise, the question whether it
would or would not tend to maximize production in a perfectly equilibrated
stationary condition of the economic process is... almost, though not quite,
irrelevant.” [4]
The reason it is not completely irrelevant is that the model of a
stationary competitive process helps us to understand the behavior of an
economy that possesses no internal forces generating economic change. Thus, the model of a Walrasian
circular flow constitutes Schumpeter’s starting point in understanding the
essential elements of capitalist reality because it shows
2. Ibid., pp. 2-3.
3. Joseph Schumpeter, “Capitalism in the Postwar World,” in Essays of
J.A. Schumpeter, ed. Clemence, p. 174.
4. Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy, second edition, George Allen & Unwin,
Ltd., London, 1943, p. 77.
49
how that system would behave in the absence of its most
distinctive feature - innovation. It is
an invaluable abstraction precisely because it makes it possible to trace out
with greater precision the impact of innovative activity. This is the role served by the Walrasian conception of the circular flow in Schumpeter’s
analysis of business cycles as well as growth.
Of course, one can always adopt the position that Schumpeter and neo-classical
economics address very different questions, and that the theoretical analysis
of each is valid in its particular intellectual context. Newton’s law of gravity, after all, was not
invalidated by Mendeleev’s periodic table of the
elements. Each theory was devised to
account for different classes of phenomena. They do not contradict each other and they
may, therefore, be simultaneously valid - or invalid.
I believe that there is something to be said in support of such a
position. But I am not at all confident
that the Schumpeter of part II of Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy would
have been satisfied with it. Schumpeter’s position seems to be that, if you
want to understand what capitalism is all about as an economic system, the
fundamental question is how it generates economic change rather than how it
restores stability. Not all theoretical
frameworks are equally useful in analyzing the essential feature of modern
capitalism. And again, the essential
feature, in Schumpeter’s view, is economic change. This is because the capitalist form of
economic organization has a built-in logic that dominates the behavior of that
economic system. Thus, economists who
purport to have something to say that is pertinent to the contemporary
operation of capitalism have the obligation to deal with certain distinctive
patterns of capitalist behavior and to explain their consequences. The behavior of capitalism is totally
dominated by the continual working out of its inner logic, the essence of which
is economic change resulting from the impact of the innovation process.
Equilibrium analysis, on the other hand, focuses upon adjustment
mechanisms that are only peripheral, and not central, to the logic of
capitalist organization and incentives. Therefore
a theoretical approach that neglects persistent disequilibrium, instability and
growth is an approach that deals with processes that
are, at best, phenomena of secondary importance, or only mere epiphenomena. [5]
III – Schumpeterian Competition
I do not propose to examine in any detail Schumpeter’s views on innovation,
or the breadth of his definition of innovation, since these are
5. For a
perceptive examination of the limits of equilibrium analysis in the context of
innovation studies, see Richard R. Nelson, “Schumpeter and Contemporary
Research on the Economics of Innovation,” unpublished manuscript, Columbia
University, February 1992.
50
familiar to all readers of his major works. I do, however, propose to underline the rather
radical implications that Schumpeter himself drew from the primacy that he
attached to innovation - implications that have received little attention. The dynamic forces that are inherent in the
capitalist structure lead Schumpeter to treat capitalism as a system whose
essential feature is an evolutionary process and not the mechanisms that force
the system to revert to an equilibrium after some
external force has produced a small departure from that equilibrium. For those who find the term “disequilibrium
analysis” too paradoxical to be useful as a description of Schumpeter’s mode of
economic analysis, I suggest the propriety of the term “evolutionary.” My justification is a simple one: it is
Schumpeter’s own frequently used term in Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy:
The essential point to grasp is that in dealing with
capitalism we are dealing with an evolutionary process... Capitalism... is by
nature a form or method of economic change and not only never
is but never can be stationary. And this
evolutionary character of the capitalist process is not merely due to the fact
that economic life goes on in a social and natural environment which changes
and by its changes alters the data of economic action; this fact is important
and these changes (wars, revolutions and so on) often condition industrial
change, but they are not its prime movers. Nor is this evolutionary character due to a
quasi-automatic increase in population and capital or to the vagaries of
monetary systems of which exactly the same thing holds true. [6]
I ask readers of Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy to ponder the far-reaching implications of this statement. For it involves not only the recognition of
the inherently dynamic nature of capitalism. It involves also nothing less than the
rejection of the competitive ideal itself, as that ideal is enshrined not only
in economists’ models but also in decades of government regulation and, in the
United States, in a full century of anti-trust legislation. In this view, textbook competition is not an
ideal state to be pursued. The welfare
implications of the competitive ideal reflect a mistaken preoccupation with the
distinctly secondary issue of how the economy allocates an existing stock of
resources; whereas the far more significant concern for Schumpeter is how
successful an economic system is at generating growth - growth in a qualitative
as well as a quantitative sense. In my
own reading, this deserves to be regarded as the central message of Capitalism,
Socialism and Democracy. Capitalists
survive, if they survive at all, by learning to live in, and to participate in,
a “perennial gale of creative destruction... the problem that is usually being
visualized is how capitalism administers existing structures, whereas the
relevant problem is how it creates and destroys them.” [7] I call attention to the
5. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, p. 82. See also ibid.,
p. 58.
6. Ibid., p. 84.
51
significant fact that Schumpeter attached so much importance
to this last observation that he repeated it, almost verbatim, in the preface
to the second edition of Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy.[8]
In my view, if one is looking for a distinctively “Schumpeterian
hypothesis,” it lies in this definition of the essential nature of the
competitive process. Perhaps this should
not be regarded as a hypothesis, since it is difficult to reduce it to a
testable, potentially refutable form. It
is more in the nature of a conception or, better, to use a favorite
Schumpeterian term, a “vision” of the essential nature of capitalism. It is a vision in which it is a mistake to
reduce monopoly to the purely restrictive and anti-social consequences that are
normally ascribed to it, since monopoly power is often a temporary adjunct of
the process of creative destruction. The
Schumpeter of Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy does indeed attach
considerable significance to the growth in the absolute size of the firm in the
course of the twentieth century. At the
same time, I would like to insist that a “Schumpeterian hypothesis,” which postulates
a strong association between market power and innovation, is an extreme
oversimplification of a much more sophisticated - and much more radical - view
of the meaning of competition. [9]
Thus, Schumpeter is involved in an explicit rejection of the central
neo-classical notion that atomistic competition offers unique welfare advantages.
In Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy he posits a novel conception of competition based upon innovation
as a central element in a disequilibrium process that leads the economy to
higher levels of income, output, and, presumably, well-being. In the course of the twentieth century the
large-scale firm, with its internal research capabilities, has become the
dominant engine of technical progress. This
is a main theme of Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, as opposed to
his earlier book, The Theory of Economic Development. Schumpeter’s argument is certainly closely
tied to bigness and to the dismissal of the virtues of perfect competition. It recognizes some degree of monopoly power as
a passing phase of the innovation process. But rejecting the virtues of perfect
competition is not the same thing as saying that monopoly power is inherently
favorable to innovation.
Thus it is not sufficient to argue that because perfect
competition is impossible under modern industrial conditions - or because it
always has been impossible - the large-scale establishment or unit of control
must be accepted as a necessary evil inseparable from the economic progress
which it is prevented from sabotaging by the forces inherent in its productive
apparatus. What we have got to accept is
that it
8. Ibid., p. x.
9. See Nelson, “Schumpeter and Contemporary Research on the Economics of
Innovation,” for an illuminating discussion of this issue.
52
has come to be the most powerful engine of that progress
and in particular of the long-run expansion of total output not only in spite
of, but to a considerable extend through, this strategy which looks so
restrictive when viewed in the individual case and from the individual point of
time. In this respect, perfect
competition is not only impossible but inferior, and has no title to being set
up as a model of ideal efficiency. [10]
Indeed, the perennial gale of creative destruction is continually
sweeping away entrenched monopoly power that appeared so secure until a new
innovation consigned it to the scrapheap of history. That is precisely why the perennial gale is
such a critically important economic force.
IV – The Growth and Limitations of Rationality
But there is much more to Schumpeter the radical anti-neo-classicist
than has been suggested so far. This
becomes apparent as soon as it is recognized that innovation, the central
feature of capitalist reality, is not a product of a decision-making process
that can be described or analyzed as “rational”:
the assumption that business behaviour
is ideally rational and prompt, and also that in principle it is the same with
all firms, works tolerably well only within the precincts of tried experience
and familiar motive. It breaks down as
soon as we leave those precincts and allow the business community under study
to be faced by - not simply new situations, which also occur as soon as
external factors unexpectedly intrude but by - new possibilities of business
action which are as yet untried and about which the most complete command of
routine teaches nothing. Those differences
in the behaviour of different people which within
those precincts account for secondary phenomena only, become essential in the
sense that they now account for the outstanding features of reality and that a
picture drawn on the Walras-Marshallian lines ceases
to be true - even in the qualified sense in which it is true of stationary and
growing processes: it misses those features, and becomes wrong in the endeavour to account by means of its own analysis for
phenomena which the assumptions of that analysis exclude. [11]
It is, of course, difficult to imagine a more profound rejection of
neo-classical economics than is embodied in Schumpeter’s forceful assertion
that the most important feature of capitalist reality - innovation - is one to
which rational decision-making has no direct application. The nature of the innovation process, the
drastic departure from existing routines, is inherently one that cannot be
reduced to mere calculation, although subsequent imitation of the innovation,
once accomplished, can be so reduced. Innovation
is the creation of knowledge that cannot, and therefore should
10. Schumpeter, Capitalism,
Socialism and Democracy, p. 106.
11. Joseph Schumpeter, Business Cycles, 2 vols.,
McGraw-Hill Book Company, New York, 1939, vol. I, pp. 98-99.
53
not, be “anticipated” by the theorist in a purely formal
manner, as is done in the theory of decision-making under uncertainty. In Schumpeter’s view, it would be entirely
meaningless to speak of “the future state of the world,” as that state is not
merely unknown, but also indefinable in empirical and historical terms. Serious doubt is thus cast on what meaning, if
any, can be possessed by intertemporal models of
equilibrium under uncertainty, in which the essential nature of innovation is
systematically neglected.
Thus, if rationality is reduced in the neo-classical world more and
more to the tautology that people do the best they can, given the whole gamut
of constraints they face - among the most important of which is the
informational constraint - then accepting Schumpeter’s concept of innovation
means that human actions are always second best in a way that ultimately cannot
be subjected to further analysis. For
rational behavior, in Schumpeter’s view, is most significant in a world of
routine and repetition of similar events. (Needless to say, the modern
literature on rational expectations does not overcome Schumpeter’s strictures
here. The “rationality” of rational
expectations is limited by currently available information, and thus the
inherent uncertainty concerning the future is not eliminated).
But this is not the end of Schumpeter’s rather complex treatment of the
role of rationality. If one considers
rationality in the long historical context, Schumpeter mounts an argument in Capitalism,
Socialism and Democracy the essential element of which is that capitalism,
considered as a civilization, has continuously enlarged the social space within
which rationalistic attitudes and habits of thought come to prevail. [12] In chapter 11, “The
Civilization of Capitalism,” Schumpeter argues that capitalism has expanded the
sphere within which “rational cost-profit calculations” could be carried out. Moreover,
primarily a product of the evolution of economic rationality,
the cost-profit calculus in turn reacts upon that rationality; by crystallizing
and defining numerically, it powerfully propels the logic of enterprise. And thus defined and quantified for the
economic sector, this type of logic or attitude or method then starts upon its
conqueror’s career, subjugating - rationalizing - man’s tools and philosophies,
his medical practice, his picture of the cosmos, his outlook on life,
everything in fact including his concepts of beauty and justice and his
spiritual ambitions. [13]
This aspect of Schumpeter’s argument - what he himself might have
described as his own “economic sociology” - is, in my opinion, analytically
brilliant, breathtaking in its sweep and, historically, substantially correct. I regret that it is impossible here to examine
his argument in detail. I remind
12. Contrast this view with Babbage’s treatment of rationality
and the “Mental Division of Labour” in the previous
chapter.
13. Schumpeter, Capitalism,
Socialism and Democracy, pp. 123-124.
54
you of it now because it is the linch
pin of Schumpeter’s argument that capitalism will eventually “self-destruct.” The self-destruction is inevitable because, in
his view, the historical expansion of rationality brings in its wake two
crucial consequences.
The first is that rationality challenges and unfrocks beliefs and
institutions that cannot survive the searching and corrosive glare of a
(presumably narrow) rationality: “When
the habit of rational analysis of, and rational behavior in, the daily tasks of
life has gone far enough, it turns back upon the mass of collective ideas and
criticizes and to some extent ‘rationalizes’ them by way of such questions as
why there should be kings and popes or subordination or tithes or property.” [14]
The second consequence is that, as capitalism expands the sphere to
which rationality applies, it learns eventually how to supplant the entrepreneur,
the human “carrier” of innovation, with institutions that do away with the
social leadership of the entrepreneur himself. The entrepreneurial function itself becomes
rationalized - or bureaucratized - with the growth of the large firm. “For... it is now much easier than it has been
in the past to do things that lie outside familiar routine - innovation itself
has been reduced to routine. Technological
progress is increasingly becoming the business of teams of trained specialists
who turn out what is required and make it work in predictable ways.” [15]
Of course, the growth of large-scale enterprise and the “obsolescence of
the entrepreneurial function” led Schumpeter, through the rich argument of his
economic and political sociology, to his conclusion that capitalism cannot
survive. The ideology and social myths
that once sustained it cannot survive its tendency to “automatize
progress” [16] and thus to reveal its
new-found ability to do without the leadership and vitality once provided by
the entrepreneur and the bourgeoisie.
My own view - with the easy wisdom of fifty years of retrospection - is
that Schumpeter much overstated the extent to which technological progress
would become automatized. I believe that this, in turn, is partly due to
his intensive focus upon the earliest stages in the innovation process, and to
his failure to consider the degree to which commercial success is dependent
upon subsequent stages in the carrying out of an innovation. But, regrettably, these issues cannot be
explored here. What is essential to my
examination of Schumpeter the radical is the observation that, both in the past
and in the future, it is Schumpeter’s view that a
rational approach to the innovation process is incompatible with capitalist
institutions. So long as the function
was carried out by the individual entrepreneur, it was an act based upon
intuition and charismatic leadership; when capitalist
14. Ibid., p. 122.
15. Ibid., p. 132.
16 Ibid., p. 134.
55
institutions eventually, at some future date, succeed in
subjecting innovation to a rationalized routine, those institutions will, ipso
facto, lose their lustre and social
justification, and be replaced by a socialized state.
Thus, in a world where capitalist institutions continue to prevail,
innovation calls upon a decision-making process that goes beyond rational
calculation. When capitalist development
eventually leads to the institutionalization of innovation, the organizational
basis of the economy will, Schumpeter believes, be transformed into some form
of socialism. In neither case,
ironically, does Schumpeter concede a significant role for the neo-classical
analysis of rational behavior.
Schumpeter’s radical anti-neo-classical stance extends even to the
issue of what it is that constitutes the explicanda
of economic analysis. It is normal
practice for neo-classical economists to take tastes and technology as
exogenously given, and to seek to examine issues of resource allocation by
explicit reference to changes in incomes and relative prices. [17]
Thus, Schumpeter’s assault upon neo-classical economics includes even
his deliberate violation of the sanctum sanctorum of the neo-classical
citadel: the commitments to the exogeneity of
consumer preferences and the associated virtues of consumer sovereignty. His belief that the central problem of the
economist is to account for economic change over time undoubtedly played an
important role in sharpening his perception of the forces influencing consumer
preferences:
Innovations in the economic system do not as a rule
take place in such a way that first new wants arise spontaneously in consumers
and then the productive apparatus swings round through their pressure. We do not deny the presence of this nexus. It is, however, the producer who as a rule
initiates economic change, and consumers are educated by him if necessary; they
are, as it were, taught to want new things, or things which differ in some
respect or other from those which they have been in the habit of using. Therefore, while it is permissible and even
necessary to consider consumers’ wants as an independent and indeed the
fundamental force in a theory of the circular flow, we must take a different
attitude as soon as we analyse change. [18]
Schumpeter made the same essential point later on in Business
Cycles:
We will, throughout, act on the
assumption that consumers’ initiative in changing their tastes - i.e., in
changing that set of our data which general theory comprises in
17. See George Stigler and Gary Becker, “De Gustibus
non est Disputandum,” American
Economic Review, 67 (1977), pp. 76-90.
18. Joseph Schumpeter, The Theory of Economic Development, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge (MA), 1949, p. 65 Schumpeter’s italics. (first published in German in 1911).
56
the concepts of “utility functions” or “indifference
varieties” - is negligible and that all change in consumers’ tastes is incident
to, and brought about by, producers’ actions. This requires both justification and
qualification.
The fact on which we stand is,
of course, common knowledge. Railroads
have not emerged because any consumers took the initiative in displaying an
effective demand for their service in preference to the services of mail
coaches. Nor did the consumers display
any such initiative wish to have electric lamps or rayon stockings, or to
travel by motorcar or airplane, or to listen to radios, or to chew gum. There is obviously no lack of realism in the
proposition that the great majority of changes in commodities consumed has been forced by producers on consumers who, more often
than not, have resisted the change and have had to be educated up by elaborate psychotechnics of advertising. [19]
Although modern economists have, of course, investigated the consequences
of endogenous preferences for welfare judgments, most have considered it
better, for reasons of division of labor with other disciplines, in particular
psychology, to neglect the investigation of why and how tastes change. [20] But Schumpeter asserted
that innovation, the fundamental driving force of the historical evolution of
capitalism, would mould tastes as well as technology in unexpected ways. The implications, both for the development of
the economic and social systems, as well as for microeconomic welfare judgments
were, as Schumpeter recognized, potentially radical. Just before his death in 1950 he severely
criticized economists for the uncritical belief that so many seem to harbor in
the virtues of consumers’ choice:
First of all, whether we like it or not, we are
witnessing a momentous experiment in malleability of tastes - is not this worth
analyzing? Second, ever since the physiocrats (and before), economists have professed
unbounded respect for the consumers’ choice - is it not time to investigate
what the bases for this respect are and how far the traditional and, in part,
advertisement-shaped tastes of people are subject to the qualification that
they might prefer other things than those which they want at present as soon as
they have acquired familiarity with these other things? In matters of education, health, and housing
there is already practical unanimity about this - but might the principle not
be carried much further? Third, economic
theory accepts existing tastes as data, no matter whether it postulates utility
functions or indifference varieties or simply preference directions, and these
data are made the starting point of price theory. Hence, they must be considered as independent
of prices. But considerable and
persistent changes in prices obviously do react upon tastes. What, then, is to become of our theory and
the whole of microeconomics? It is
investigations of this kind, that might break new
ground, which I miss. [21]
19. Schumpeter,
Business Cycles, vol. I, p. 73.
20. See, for
example, Milton Friedman, Price Theory, Aldine Publishing Company, New York,
1976, p. 13.
21. Joseph
Schumpeter, “English Economists and the State-Managed Economy,” Journal of Political
Economy (1949), pp. 380-381. Schumpeter’s italics.
57
The earlier discussion of Schumpeter’s analysis of innovation has
already anticipated his unwillingness to treat technological change, as well as
consumers’ tastes, as an exogenous phenomenon. But it is necessary to distinguish between the
earlier Schumpeter of The Theory of Economic Development (1911) and the
later Schumpeter of Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (1942). In his earlier book, Schumpeter looked upon
invention as an exogenous activity and upon innovation as endogenous. Whereas inventors conducted their activities
off the economic stage and contributed their artifacts to a pool of invention,
the timing of the entrepreneurial decision to draw from this pool was
decisively shaped by economic forces. But
the later Schumpeter saw both invention and innovation as generated by economic
forces inside the large firm with its own internal research capabilities. The reason for the change in Schumpeter’s
views during this period is not far to seek: the economic world, the object of
Schumpeter’s studies, had changed substantially during the period between the
publication of the two books. Schumpeter’s altered views were an
acknowledgment of empirical changes that had occurred during his own
professional lifetime.
Schumpeter’s insistence upon the role of endogenous forces applies, not
only to technology, but also to science itself. The rationalizing influence of the
capitalistic mentality and institutions created “the growth of rational
science” as well as its “long list of applications.” [22] Significantly, Schumpeter
cites as examples not only “Airplanes, refrigerators, television and that sort
of thing...” but also the “modern hospital.” Although one might be surprised at the
appearance here of an institution that is not commonly operated on a profitmaking basis, Schumpeter’s explanation is illuminating.
It is
fundamentally because capitalist rationality supplied the habits of
mind that evolved the methods used in these hospitals. And the victories,
not yet completely won but in the offing, over cancer, syphilis and
tuberculosis will be as much capitalist achievements as motorcars or pipe lines
or Bessemer steel have been. In the case
of medicine, there is a capitalist profession behind the methods, capitalist
both because to a large extent it works in a business spirit and because it is
an emulsion of the industrial and commercial bourgeoisie. But even if that were not so, modern medicine
and hygiene would still be by-products of the capitalist process just as is
modern education. [23]
Thus, Schumpeter insisted that both science and technology, normally so
far from the world of phenomena examined by neo-classical economics, are in
reality highly endogenous to the economic world, subject to the gravitational
pull of economic forces. In one of the
last articles published during his own lifetime, Schumpeter identified his views
with those of Marx
22. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy,
p. 125.
23. Ibid., pp. 125-126.
58
on the role played by western capitalism in accounting for
progress in both science and technology. Schumpeter observed that Marx had, in the Communist
Manifesto, “launched out on a panegyric upon bourgeois achievement that has
no equal in economic literature.” After
quoting a relevant portion of the text, he says:
No reputable “bourgeois” economist of that or any
other time - certainly not A. Smith or J.S. Mill - ever said as much as this. Observe, in particular, the emphasis upon the
creative role of the business class that the majority of the most “bourgeois”
economists so persistently overlooked and of the business class as such,
whereas most of us would, on the one hand, also insert into the picture
non-bourgeois contributions to the bourgeois success - the contributions of
non-bourgeois bureaucracies, for instance - and, on the other hand, commit the
mistake (for such I believe it is) to list as independent factors science and
technology, whereas Marx’s sociology enabled him to see that these as well as
“progress” in such fields as education and hygiene were just as much the
products of the bourgeois culture - hence, ultimately, of the business class -
as was the business performance itself. [24]
Did Schumpeter then believe, along with Marx, in the economic interpretation
of history? I suggest that he did, with
certain qualifications. However, the
qualifications that Schumpeter imposed upon the economic interpretation of
history were of a sort that, if anything, actually strengthened its usefulness
as a device for explaining economic change. It is important here to recall that the first
four chapters of Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy are devoted
entirely to an examination of Marx’s views on a range of subjects. Schumpeter offered a sympathetic and approving
treatment of the economic interpretation of history; moreover, almost all of
his own writing fits conveniently into that interpretation. But Schumpeter also compresses the economic
interpretation into just two propositions:
1. The forms or conditions of production are the
fundamental determinants of social structures which in turn breed attitudes,
actions and civilizations.
2. The forms of production themselves have a logic of
their own; that is to say, they change according to necessities inherent in
them so as to produce their successors merely by their own working. [25]
Schumpeter asserts that “Both propositions undoubtedly contain a large
amount of truth and are, as we shall find at several turns of our way,
invaluable working hypotheses.” [26] His main qualification,
if that is what it really is, is his insistence upon the importance of lags,
that is, social forms that persist after they have lost their economic
rationale. It is far from clear that
Marx would have disagreed with such a qualification, since Marx was much too
sophisticated a historian to believe that economic changes
24. Joseph Schumpeter, “The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and
Economics,” Journal of Political Economy (1949), p.293. See also Capitalism.
Socialism and Democracy, chapter
1.
25. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy, pp. 11—12.
26. Ibid., p. 12.
59
generated the “appropriate” social changes instantaneously. Schumpeter, in making the qualification about
lags, adds that Marx, although perhaps not fully appreciating their
implications, would not have taken the simplistic position involved in denying
them a role:
Social
structures, types and attitudes are coins that do not readily melt. Once they are formed they persist, possibly
for centuries, and since different structures and types display different
degrees of this ability to survive, we almost always find that actual group and
national behaviour more or less departs from what we
should expect it to be if we tried to infer it from the dominant forms of the
productive process. Though this applies
quite generally, it is most clearly seen when a highly durable structure
transfers itself bodily from one country to another. The social situation created in Sicily by the
Norman conquest will illustrate my meaning. Such facts Marx did not overlook but he hardly
realized all their implications. [27]
Whether or not one concludes, as I do, that Schumpeter believed in a
form of the economic interpretation of history, he clearly was strongly committed
to the view that economic phenomena, in order to be meaningfully examined, must
be studied in an historical context. Since I have spent a significant portion of my
own professional life studying economic behavior in historical contexts, I am
naturally pleased to be able to invoke the authority of Schumpeter in support
of such an approach. At the same time, I
believe that this interpretation of Schumpeter is more than a merely
self-serving exercise on my part.
The fact is that most of what Schumpeter wrote qualifies as history,
both economic and intellectual. Not only
Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy but, in addition, Business Cycles
and his posthumous History of Economic Analysis are historical
works. His commitment to the historical
approach was deeply rooted in his thought. Schumpeter had a profound appreciation of the
path-dependent nature of economic phenomena and therefore of economic analysis
itself. [28] More
than this. The very subject matter of
economics, in Schumpeter’s view, is history. Economics is about economic change as it has
occurred over historical time. That is
why he insists upon the importance of studying capitalism as an evolutionary
process. It is also why he assigns such
a limited importance to the study of stationary economic processes. And these things have a great deal to do with
Schumpeter’s highest regard for some of Marx’s contributions to economic
analysis:
27. Ibid., pp. 12-13.
28. For a more precise definition of path dependence and further
analysis of the relationship between modern economic theory and historical
analysis, see chapter 1 in this book.
60
There is... one thing of fundamental importance for
the methodology of economics which he actually achieved. Economists always have either themselves done
work in economic history or else used the historical work of others. But the facts of economic history were assigned
to a separate compartment. They entered
theory, if at all, merely in the role of illustrations, or possibly of
verifications of results. They mixed
with it only mechanically. Now Marx’s
mixture is a chemical one; that is to say, he introduced them into the very
argument that produces the results. He
was the first economist of top rank to see and to teach systematically how
economic theory may be turned into historical analysis and how the historical
narrative may be turned into histoire raisonnée.
[29]
This passage, it seems to me, is also the best explanation for
Schumpeter’s frequent expression of admiration for, and intellectual
indebtedness to Marx.
I can think of no better way of closing this chapter
than by reminding you of certain views that Schumpeter expressed in chapter 2
of his History of Economic Analysis. After
stating that a “scientific” economist is to be identified by the demonstrated
command over three techniques - history, statistics, and theory - he goes on to
say:
Of these fundamental fields, economic
history - which issues into and includes present-day facts - is by far the most
important. I wish to state right now
that if, starting my work in economics afresh, I were told that I could study
only one of the three but could have my choice, it would be economic history
that I should choose. And
this on three grounds. First, the
subject matter of economics is essentially a unique process in historic time. Nobody can hope to understand the economic
phenomena of any, including the present, epoch who has
not an adequate command of historical facts and an adequate amount of
historical sense or of what may be described as historical experience. Second, the historical report cannot be
purely economic but must inevitably reflect also “institutional” facts that are
not purely economic; therefore it affords the best method for understanding how
economic and non-economic facts are related to one another and how the
various social sciences should be related to one another. Third, it is, I believe, the fact that most of
the fundamental errors currently committed in economic analysis are due to a
lack of historical experience more often than to any other shortcoming of the
economist’s equipment. [30]
It is sad to have to conclude with the observation
that some knowledge of history is still not regarded as essential to competent
economic analysis. Indeed, judging by
the curricula of the graduate programs in American universities today, the very
idea would appear to be distinctly perverse and alien. In this, as in so many other respects,
Schumpeter the radical economist still has a great deal to teach us.
29. Ibid.,
p. 44.
30. Joseph
Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, Oxford University Press, New
York, 1954, pp. 12-13. Schumpeter’s italics.
61
The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
May 2003