The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Walter Lippman
MacMillan, NYC, 1960 (©
1922)
CHAPTER
THE WORLD
OUTSIDE AND THE PICTURES
IN OUR
HEADS
THERE is an island in the ocean where in 1914 a few Englishmen,
Frenchmen, and Germans lived. No
cable reaches that island, and the British mail steamer comes but once in sixty
days. In September it had not yet
come, and the islanders were still talking about the latest newspaper which told
about the approaching trial of Madame Caillaux for the shooting of Gaston
Calmette. It was, therefore, with
more than usual eagerness that the whole colony assembled at the quay on a day
in mid-September to hear from the captain what the verdict had been. They learned that for over six weeks now
those of them who were English and those of them who were French had been
fighting in behalf of the sanctity of treaties against those of them who were
Germans. For six strange weeks they
had acted as if they were friends, when in fact they were
enemies.
But their plight was not so different from that of most of the population
of
3
an interval. There was a
moment when the picture of Europe on which men were conducting their business as
usual, did not in any way correspond to the Europe which was about to make a
jumble of their lives. There was a
time for each man when he was still adjusted to an environment that no longer
existed. All over the world as late
as July 25th men were making goods that they would not be able to
ship, buying goods they would not be able to import, careers were being planned,
enterprises contemplated, hopes and expectations entertained, all in the belief
that the world as known was the world as it was. Men were writing books describing that
world. They trusted the picture in
their heads. And then over four
years later, on a Thursday morning, came the news of an armistice, and people
gave vent to their unutterable relief that the slaughter was over. Yet in the five days before the real
armistice came, though the end of the war had been celebrated, several thousand
young men died on the battlefields.
Looking back we can see how indirectly we know the environment in which
nevertheless we live. We can see
that the news of it comes to us now fast, now slowly; but that whatever we
believe to be a true picture, we treat as if it were the environment itself.
It is harder to remember that about
the beliefs upon which we are now acting, but in respect to other peoples and
other ages we flatter ourselves that it is easy to see when they were in deadly
earnest about ludicrous pictures of the world. We insist, because of our superior
hindsight, that the world as they needed to know it, and the world as they did
know it, were
4
often two quite contradictory things. We can see, too, that while they governed
and fought, traded and reformed in the world as they imagined it to be, they
produced results, or failed to produce any, in the world as it was. They started for the
Writing about the year 389, St. Ambrose stated the case for the prisoner in Plato’s cave who resolutely declines to turn his head. “To discuss the nature and position of the earth does not help us in our hope of the life to come. It is enough to know what Scripture states. ‘That He hung up the earth upon nothing’ (Job xxvi. 7). Why then argue whether He hung it up in air or upon the water, and raise a controversy as to how the thin air could sustain the earth; or why, if upon the waters, the earth does not go crashing down to the bottom? Not because the earth is in the middle, as if suspended on even balance, but because the majesty of God constrains it by the law of His will, does it endure stable upon the unstable and the void.” 1
It does not help us in our hope of the life to come. It is enough to know what Scripture
states. Why then argue? But a century and a half after St.
Ambrose, opinion was still troubled, on this occasion by the problem of the
antipodes. A monk
1
Hexaëmeron, i. cap 6, quoted in The Mediaeval Mind, by Henry Osborn Taylor, Vol. 1, p. 73.5
named Cosmas, famous for his scientific attainments, was therefore
deputed to write a Christian Topography, or “Christian Opinion concerning the
World.” 1 It is clear
that he knew exactly what was expected of him, for he based all his conclusions
on the Scriptures as he read them. It appears, then, that the world is a
flat parallelogram, twice as broad from east to west as it is long from north to
south. In the center is the earth
surrounded by ocean, which is in turn surrounded by another earth, where men
lived before the deluge. This other
earth was Noah’s port of embarkation. In the north is a high conical mountain
around which revolve the sun and moon. When the sun is behind the mountain it is
night. The sky is glued to the edges of the outer earth. It consists of four high walls which meet
in a concave roof, so that the earth is the floor of the universe. There is an ocean on the other side of
the sky, constituting the “waters that are above the firmament.” The space between the celestial ocean and
the ultimate roof of the universe belongs to the blest. The space between the earth and sky is
inhabited by the angels. Finally,
since
Far less should he go to the
1
Lecky, Rationalism in
2.
6
would any pious mariner wish to try. For Cosmas there was nothing in the least
absurd about his map. Only by
remembering his absolute conviction that this was the map of the universe can we
begin to understand how he would have dreaded Magellan or Peary or the aviator
who risked a collision with the angels and the vault of heaven by flying seven
miles up in the air. In the same
way we can best understand the furies of war and politics by remembering that
almost the whole of each party believes absolutely in its picture of the
opposition, that it takes as fact, not what is, but what it supposes to be the
fact. And that therefore, like
Hamlet, it will stab Polonius behind the rustling curtain, thinking him the
king, and perhaps like Hamlet add:
“Thou wretched, rash, intruding fool,
farewell!
I took thee for thy better; take thy
fortune.”
Great men, even during their lifetime, are usually known to the public
only through a fictitious personality. Hence the modicum of truth in the old
saying that no man is a hero to his valet. There is only a modicum of truth, for the
valet, and the private secretary, are often immersed in the fiction themselves.
Royal personages are, of course,
constructed personalities. Whether
they themselves believe in their public character, or whether they merely permit
the chamberlain to stage-manage it, there are at least two distinct selves, the
public and regal self, the private and human. The biographies of great people fail more
or less readily into the histories of these two
7
selves. The official
biographer reproduces the public life, the revealing memoir the other. The Charnwood Lincoln, for example, is a
noble portrait, not of an actual human being, but of an epic figure, replete
with significance, who moves on much the same level of reality as Aeneas or St.
George. Oliver’s
But the most interesting kind of portraiture is that which arises
spontaneously in people’s minds. When
1. Lytton
Strachey, Queen Victoria,
p.72.
8
and here at last, crowned and radiant, was the
spring.”
M. Jean de Pierrefeu 1 saw hero-worship at first hand, for he
was an officer on Joffre’s staff at the moment of that soldier’s greatest
fame:
“For two years, the entire world paid an almost divine homage to the victor of the
1. Jean de
Pierrefeu, G.Q.G Trois ans au Grand
Quartier General, pp. 94-95.
9
And not only Frenchmen, but Americans, Argentinians,
Australians, etc. etc. . . . Thousands of little children, without
their parents’ knowledge, took pen in hand and wrote to tell him their love:
most of them called him Our Father. And there was poignancy about their
effusions, their adoration, these sighs of deliverance that escaped from
thousands of hearts at the defeat of barbarism. To all these naif little souls, Joffre
seemed like St. George crushing the dragon. Certainly he incarnated for the
conscience of mankind the victory of good over evil, of light over
darkness.
Lunatics, simpletons, the half-crazy and the crazy turned their darkened brains toward him as toward reason itself. I have read the letter of a person living in
Finally, some hundreds of young girls, overcoming the
timidity of their sex, asked for engagements, their families not to know about
it; others wished only to serve him.”
This ideal Joffre was compounded out of the victory won by him, his staff
and his troops, the despair of the war, the personal sorrows, and the hope of
future victory. But beside
hero-worship there is the exorcism of devils. By the same mechanism through which
heroes are incarnated, devils are made. If everything good was to come from
Joffre, Foch, Wilson, or Roosevelt, everything evil originated in the Kaiser
Wilhelm, Lenin and Trotsky. They
were as omnipotent for evil as the heroes were omnipotent for good. To many simple and frightened minds there
was no political reverse, no strike, no obstruc-
10
tion, no mysterious death or mysterious conflagration anywhere in the
world of which the causes did not wind back to these personal sources of
evil.
Worldwide concentration of this kind on a symbolic personality is rare
enough to be clearly remarkable, and every author has a weakness for the
striking and irrefutable example. The vivisection of war reveals such
examples, but it does not make them out of nothing. In a more normal public life, symbolic
pictures are no less governant of behavior, but each symbol is far less
inclusive because there are so many competing ones. Not only is each symbol charged with less
feeling because at most it represents only a part of the population, but even
within that part there is infinitely less suppression of individual difference.
The symbols of public opinion, in
times of moderate security, are subject to check and comparison and argument.
They come and go, coalesce and are
forgotten, never organizing perfectly the emotion of the whole group. There is, after all, just one human
activity left in which whole populations accomplish the union sacrée. It occurs in those middle phases of a war
when fear, pugnacity, and hatred have secured complete dominion of the spirit,
either to crush every other instinct or to enlist it, and before weariness is
felt.
At almost all other times and even in war when it is deadlocked, a
sufficiently greater range of feelings is aroused to establish conflict, choice,
hesitation, and compromise. The
symbolism of public opinion
11
usually bears, as we shall see,1 the marks of this balancing
of interest. Think, for example, of
how rapidly, after the armistice, the precarious and by no means successfully
established symbol of Allied Unity disappeared, how it was followed almost
immediately by the breakdown of each nation’s symbolic picture of the other:
Britain the Defender of Public Law,
France watching at the Frontier of Freedom, America the Crusader. And think then of how within each nation
the symbolic picture of itself frayed out, as party and class conflict and
personal ambition began to stir postponed issues. And then of how the symbolic pictures of
the leaders gave way, as one by one, Wilson, Clemenceau, Lloyd George, ceased to
be the incarnation of human hope, and became merely the negotiators and
administrators for a disillusioned world.
Whether we regret this as one of the soft evils of peace or applaud it as
a return to sanity is obviously no matter here. Our first concern with fictions and
symbols is to forget their value to the existing social order, and to think of
them simply as an important part of the machinery of human communication. Now in any society that is not
completely self-contained in its interests and so small that everyone can know
all about everything that happens, ideas deal with events that are out of sight
and hard to grasp. Miss Sherwin of
Gopher Prairie,2 is aware that a war is raging in
1. Part
V
2 See
Sinclair Lewis,
12
Pictures of French and German soldiers she has seen, but it is impossible
for her to imagine three million men. No one, in fact, can imagine them, and
the professionals do not try. They
think of them as, say, two hundred divisions. But Miss Sherwin has no access to the
order of battle maps, and so if she is to think about the war, she fastens upon
Joffre and the Kaiser as if they were engaged in a personal duel. Perhaps if you could see what she sees
with her mind’s eye, the image in its composition might be not unlike an
Eighteenth Century engraving of a great soldier. He stands there boldly unruffled and more
than life size, with a shadowy army of tiny little figures winding off into the
landscape behind. Nor it seems are
great men oblivious to these expectations. M. de Pierrefeu tells of a photographer’s
visit to Joffre. The General was in
his “middle class office, before the worktable without papers, where he sat down
to write his signature. Suddenly it
was noticed that there were no maps on the walls. But since according to popular ideas it
is not possible to think of a general without maps, a few were placed in
position for the picture, and removed soon afterwards.”
1
The only feeling that anyone can have about an event he does not
experience is the feeling aroused by his mental image of that event. That is why until we know what others
think they know, we cannot truly understand their acts. I have seen a young girl, brought up in a
1. Op. cit, p. 99
13
paroxysm of grief when a gust of wind cracked the kitchen window-pane.
For hours she was inconsolable, and
to me incomprehensible. But when
she was able to talk, it transpired that if a windowpane broke it meant that a
close relative had died. She was,
therefore, mourning for her father, who had frightened her into running away
from home. The father was, of
course, quite thoroughly alive as a telegraphic inquiry soon proved. But until the telegram came, the cracked
glass was an authentic message to that girl. Why it was authentic only a prolonged
investigation by a skilled psychiatrist could show. But even the most casual observer could
see that the girl, enormously upset by her family troubles, had hallucinated a
complete fiction out of one external fact, a remembered superstition, and a
turmoil of remorse, and fear and love for her father.
Abnormality in these instances is only a matter of degree. When an Attorney-General, who has been
frightened by a bomb exploded on his doorstep, convinces himself by the reading
of revolutionary literature that a revolution is to happen on
14
first stone who did not believe in the Russian army that passed through
In all these instances we must note particularly one common factor. It is the insertion between man and his
environment of a pseudo-environment. To that pseudo-environment his behavior
is a response. But because it is
behavior, the consequences, if they are acts, operate not in the
pseudo-environment where the behavior is stimulated, but in the real environment
where action eventuates. If the
behavior is not a practical act, but what we call roughly thought and emotion,
it may be a long time before there is any noticeable break in the texture of the
fictitious world. But when the
stimulus of the pseudo-fact results in action on things or other people,
contradiction soon develops. Then
comes the sensation of butting one’s head against a stone wall, of learning by
experience, and witnessing Herbert Spencer’s tragedy of the murder of a
Beautiful Theory by a Gang of Brutal Facts, the discomfort in short of a
maladjustment. For certainly, at
the level of social life, what is called the adjustment of man to his
environment takes place through the medium of fictions.
By fictions I do not mean lies. I mean a representation of the
environment which is in lesser or greater degree made by man himself. The range of
fiction
15
extends all the way from complete hallucination to the scientists’
perfectly self-conscious use of a schematic model, or his decision that for his
particular problem accuracy beyond a certain number of decimal places is not
important. A work of fiction may
have almost any degree of fidelity, and so long as the degree of fidelity can be
taken into account, fiction is not misleading. In fact, human culture is very largely
the selection, the rearrangement, the tracing of patterns upon, and the
stylizing of, what William James called “the random irradiations and
resettlements of our ideas.”1 The alternative to the use of fictions is
direct exposure to the ebb and flow of sensation. That is not a real alternative, for
however refreshing it is to see at times with a perfectly innocent eye,
innocence itself is not wisdom, though a source and corrective of
wisdom.
For the real environment is altogether too big, too complex, and too
fleeting for direct acquaintance. We are not equipped to deal with so much
subtlety, so much variety, so many permutations and combinations. And although we have to act in that
environment, we have to reconstruct it on a simpler model before we can manage
with it. To traverse the world men
must have maps of the world. Their
persistent difficulty is to secure maps on which their own need, or someone
else’s need, has not sketched in the coast of
The analyst of public opinion must begin then, by recognizing the
triangular relationship between the
1.
James, Principles of Psychology, Vol. II, p.
638.
16
scene of action, the human picture of that scene, and the human response
to that picture working itself out upon the scene of action. It is like a play suggested to the actors
by their own experience, in which the plot is transacted in the real lives of
the actors, and not merely in their stage parts. The moving picture often emphasizes with
great skill this double drama of interior motive and external behavior. Two men are quarreling, ostensibly about
some money, but their passion is inexplicable. Then the picture fades out and what one
or the other of the two men sees with his mind’s eye is reënacted. Across the table they were quarre1ing
about money. In memory they are
back in their youth when the girl jilted him for the other man. The exterior drama is explained: the hero
is not greedy; the hero is in love.
A scene not so different was played in the United States Senate. At breakfast on the morning of
FACTS NOW
ESTABLISHED
“The following important facts appear already established. The orders to Rear Admiral Andrews commanding the American naval forces in the
17
WITHOUT DANIELS’
KNOWLEDGE
“Mr. Daniels was admittedly placed in a peculiar position when cables reached here stating that the forces over which he is presumed to have exclusive control were carrying on what amounted to naval warfare without his knowledge. It was fully realized that the British Admiralty might desire to issue orders to Rear Admiral Andrews to act on behalf of
“It was further realized that under the new league of
nations plan foreigners would be in a position to direct American Naval forces
in emergencies with or without the consent of the American Navy Department. . .
.“ etc. (Italics mine).
The first Senator to comment is Mr. Knox of
18
acted “under orders of a Supreme Council sitting somewhere,” but he
cannot recall who represents the
So far the Senators still recognize vaguely that they are discussing a
rumor. Being lawyers they still
remember some of the forms of evidence. But as red-blooded men they already
experience all the indignation which is appropriate to the fact that American
marines have been ordered into war by a foreign government and without the
consent of Congress. Emotionally
they want to believe it, because they are Republicans fighting the
A few days later an official report showed that the marines were not
landed by order of the British Government or of the Supreme Council. They
had
19
not been fighting the Italians. They had been landed at the request of
the Italian Government to protect Italians, and the American commander had been
officially thanked by the Italian authorities. The marines were not at war with
The scene of action was the
Whether in this particular case the Senate was above or below its normal
standard, it is not necessary to decide. Nor whether the Senate compares favorably
with the House, or with other parliaments. At the moment, I should like to think
only about the world-wide spectacle of men acting upon their environment, moved
by stimuli from their pseudo-environments. For when full allowance has been made for
deliberate fraud, political science has still to account for such facts as two
nations attacking one another, each convinced that it is acting in self-defense,
or two classes at war each certain that it speaks for the common interest. They live, we are likely to say, in
different worlds. More accurately,
they live in the same world, but they think and feel in different
ones.
20
It is to these special worlds, it is to these private or group, or class,
or provincial, or occupational, or national, or sectarian artifacts, that the
political adjustment of mankind in the Great Society takes place. Their variety and complication are
impossible to describe. Yet these
fictions determine a very great part of men’s political behavior. We must think of perhaps fifty sovereign
parliaments consisting of at least a hundred legislative bodies. With them belong at least fifty
hierarchies of provincial and municipal assemblies, which with their executive,
administrative and legislative organs, constitute formal authority on earth.
But that does not begin to reveal
the complexity of political life. For in each of these innumerable centers
of authority there are parties, and these parties are themselves hierarchies
with their roots in classes, sections, cliques and clans; and within these are
the individual politicians, each the personal center of a web of connection and
memory and fear and hope.
Somehow or other, for reasons often necessarily obscure, as the result of
domination or compromise or a logroll, there emerge from these political bodies
commands, which set armies in motion or make peace, conscript life, tax, exile,
imprison, protect property or confiscate it, encourage one kind of enterprise
and discourage another, facilitate immigration or obstruct it, improve
communication or censor it, establish schools, build navies, proclaim
“policies,” and “destiny,” raise economic barriers, make property or unmake it,
bring one people under the rule of another, or favor one class as
against
21
another. For each of these
decisions some view of the facts is taken to be conclusive, some view of the
circumstances is accepted as the basis of inference and as the stimulus of
feeling. What view of the facts,
and why that one?
And yet even this does not begin to exhaust the real complexity. The formal political structure exists in
a social environment, where there are innumerable large and small corporations
and institutions, voluntary and semi-voluntary associations, national,
provincial, urban and neighborhood groupings, which often as not make the
decision that the political body registers. On what are these decisions
based?
“Modern society,” says Mr. Chesterton, “is intrinsically insecure because
it is based on the--notion that all men will do the same thing for different
reasons . . . . And as within the head of any convict may be the hell of a quite
solitary crime, so in the house or under the hat of any suburban clerk may be
the limbo of a quite separate philosophy. The first man may be a complete
Materialist and feel his own body as a horrible machine manufacturing his own
mind. He may listen to his thoughts
as to the dull ticking of a clock. The man next door may be a Christian
Scientist and regard his own body as somehow rather less substantial than his
own shadow. He may come almost to
regard his own arms and legs as delusions like moving serpents in the dream of
delirium tremens. The third man in
the street may not be a Christian Scientist but, on the contrary, a Christian.
He may live in a fairy tale as his
neighbors would say; a secret but solid fairy tale full of
the
22
faces and presences of unearthly friends. The fourth man may be a theosophist, and
only too probably a vegetarian; and I do not see why I should not gratify myself
with the fancy that the fifth man is a devil worshiper. . . . Now whether or not
this sort of variety is valuable, this sort of unity is shaky. To expect that all men for all time will
go on thinking different things, and yet doing the same things, is a doubtful
speculation. It is not.founding
society on a communion, or even a convention, but rather on a coincidence. Four men may meet under the same lamp
post; one to paint it pea green as part of great municipal reform; one to read
his breviary in the light of it; one to embrace it with accidental ardour in a
lit of alcoholic enthusiasm; and the last merely because the pea green post is a
conspicuous point of rendezvous with his young lady. But to expect this to happen night after
night is unwise. . . 1
For the four men at the lamp post substitute the governments, the
parties, the corporations, the societies, the social sets, the trades and
professions, universities, sects, and nationalities of the world. Think of the legislator voting a statute
that will affect distant peoples, a statesman coming to a decision. Think of the Peace Conference
reconstituting the frontiers of
1.
G. K.
Chesterton, “The Mad Hatter and the Sane Householder,” Vanity Fair, January, 1921, p.
54.
23
the police to regulate amusement, a club lounging-room making up its mind
about a strike, a sewing circle preparing to regulate the schools, nine judges
deciding whether a legislature in Oregon may fix the working hours of women, a
cabinet meeting to decide on the recognition of a government, a party convention
choosing a candidate and writing a platform, twenty-seven million voters casting
their ballots, an Irishman in Cork thinking about an Irishman in Belfast, a
Third International planning to reconstruct the whole of human: society, a board
of directors confronted with a set of their employees’ demands, a boy choosing a
career, a merchant estimating supply and demand for the coming season, a
speculator predicting the course of the market, a banker deciding whether to put
credit behind a new enterprise, the advertiser, the reader of advertisments. . .
.Think of the different sorts of Americans thinking about their notions of “The
British Empire” or
“
And so before we involve ourselves in the jungle of obscurities about the
innate differences of men, we shall do well to fix our attention upon the
extraordinary differences in what men know of the world.1 I do not doubt that there are important
biological differences. Since man
is an animal it would be strange if there were not. But as rational beings
it
24
is worse than shallow to generalize at all about comparative behavior
until there is a measurable similarity between .the environments to which
behavior is a response. -
The pragmatic value of this idea is that it introduces a much needed refinement into the ancient controversy about nature and nurture, innate quality and environment. For the pseudo-environment is a hybrid compounded of “human nature” and “conditions.” To my mind it shows the uselessness of pontificating about what man is and always will be from what we observe man to be doing, or about what are the necessary conditions of society. For we do not know how men would behave in response to the facts of the Great Society. All that we really know is how they behave in response to what can fairly be called a most inadequate picture of the Great Society. No conclusion about man or the Great Society can honestly be made on evidence like that.
This, then, will be the clue to our inquiry. We shall assume that what each man does
is based not on direct and certain knowledge, but on pictures made by himself or
given to him. If his atlas tells
him that the world is flat he will not sail near what he believes to be the edge
of our planet for fear of falling off. If his maps include a fountain of eternal
youth, a Ponce de Leon will go in quest of it. If someone digs up yellow dirt that looks
like gold, he will for a time act exactly as if he had found gold. The way in which the world is imagined
determines at any particular moment what men will do. It does not
25
determine what they will achieve. It determines their effort, their
feelings, their hopes, not their accomplishments and results. The very men who most loudly proclaim
their “materialism” and their contempt for “ideologues,” the Marxian communists,
place their entire hope on what? On
the formation by propaganda of a class-conscious group. But what is propaganda if not the effort
to alter the picture to which men respond, to substitute one social pattern for
another? What is class
consciousness but a way of realizing the world? National consciousness but another way?
And Professor Giddings’
consciousness of kind, but a process of believing that we recognize among the
multitude certain ones marked as our kind?
Try to explain social life as the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance
of pain. You will soon be saying
that the hedonist begs the question, for even supposing that man does pursue
these ends, the crucial problem of why he thinks one course rather than another
likely to produce pleasure, is untouched. Does the guidance of man’s conscience
explain? How then does he happen to
have the particular conscience which he has? The theory of economic self-interest?
But how do men come to conceive
their interest in one way rather than another? The desire for security, or prestige, or
domination, or what is vaguely called self-realization? How do men conceive their security, what
do they consider prestige, how do they figure out the means of domination, or
what is the notion of self which they wish to realize? Pleasure, pain, conscience, acquisition,
protection,
26
enhancement, mastery, are undoubtedly names for some of the ways people
act. There may be instinctive
dispositions which work toward such ends. But no statement of the end, or any
description of the tendencies to seek it, can explain the behavior which
results. The very fact that men
theorize at all is proof that their pseudo-environments, their interior
representations of the world, are a determining element in thought, feeling, and
action. For if the connection
between reality and human response were direct and immediate, rather than
indirect and inferred, indecision and failure would be unknown, and (if each of
us fitted as snugly into the world as the child in the womb), Mr Bernard Shaw
would not have been able to say that except for the first nine months of its
existence no human being manages its affairs as well as a
plant.
The chief difficulty in adapting the psychoanalytic scheme to political thought arises in this connection. The Freudians are concerned with the maladjustment of distinct individuals to other individuals and to concrete circumstances. They have assumed that if internal derangements could be straightened out, there would be little or no confusion about what is the obviously normal relationship. But public opinion deals with indirect, unseen, and puzzling facts, and there is nothing obvious about them. The situations to which public opinions refer are known only as opinions. The psychoanalyst, on the other hand, almost always assumes that the environment is knowable, and if not knowable then at least bearable, to any unclouded intelligence. This assump-
27
tion of his is the problem of public opinion. Instead of taking for granted an
environment that is readily known, the social analyst is most concerned in
studying how the larger political environment is conceived, and how it can be
conceived more successfully. The
psychoanalyst examines the adjustment to an X, called by him the environment;
the social analyst examines the X, called by him the
pseudo-environment.
He is, of course, permanently and constantly in debt to the new
psychology, not only because when rightly applied it so greatly helps people to
stand on their own feet, come what may, but because the study of dreams, fantasy
and rationalization has thrown light on how the pseudo-environment is put
together. But he cannot assume as
his criterion either what is called a “normal biological career”1
within the existing social order, or a career “freed from religious suppression
and dogmatic conventions” outside.2 What for a sociologist is a normal social
career? Or one freed from
suppressions and conventions? Conservative critics do, to be sure,
assume the first, and romantic ones the second. But in assuming them they are
taking the whole world for granted. They are saying in effect either that
society is the sort of thing which corresponds to their idea of what is normal,
or the sort of thing which corresponds to their idea of what is free. Both ideas are merely public opinions,
and while the psychoanalyst as physician may perhaps assume them, the
sociologist may not take the products of existing
1
Edward J.
Kempf, Psychopathology,. p.
116.
2.
28
public opinion as criteria by which to study public
opinion.
The world that we have to deal with politically is out of reach, out of
sight, out of mind. It has to be
explored, reported, and imagined.
Man is no Aristotelian god contemplating all existence at one
glance. He is the creature of an
evolution who can just about span a sufficient portion of reality to manage his
survival, and snatch what on the scale of time are but a few moments of insight
and happiness. Yet this same
creature has invented ways of seeing what no naked eye could see, of hearing
what no ear couId hear, of weighing immense masses and infinitesimal ones, of
counting and separating more items than he can individually remember. He is learning to see with his mind vast
portions of the world that he could never see, touch, smell, hear, or remember.
Gradually he makes for himself a
trustworthy picture inside his head of the world beyond his
reach.
Those features of the world outside which have to do with the behavior of
other human beings, in so far as that behavior crosses ours, is dependent upon
us, or is interesting to us, we call roughly public affairs. The pictures inside the heads of these
human beings, the pictures of themselves, of others, of their needs, purposes,
and relationship, are their public opinions. Those pictures which are acted upon by
groups of people, or by individuals acting in the name of groups, are Public
Opinion with capital letters. And
so in the chapters which follow we shall inquire
29
first into some of the reasons why the picture inside so often misleads men in their dealings with the world outside. Under this heading we shall consider first the chief factors which limit their access to the facts. They are the artificial censorships, the limitations of social contact, the comparatively meager time available in each day for paying attention to public affairs, the distortion arising because events have to be compressed into very short messages, the difficulty of making a small vocabulary express a complicated world, and finally the fear of facing those facts which would seem to threaten the established routine of men’s lives.
The analysis then turns from these more or less external limitations to the question of how this trickle of messages from the-outside is affected by the stored up images, the preconceptions, and prejudices which interpret, fill them out, and in their turn powerfully direct the play of our attention, and our vision itself. From this it proceeds to examine how in the individual person the limited messages from outside, formed into a pattern of stereotypes, are identified with his own interests as he feels and conceives them. In the succeeding sections it examines how opinions are crystallized into what is called Public Opinion, how a National Will, a Group Mind, a Social Purpose, or whatever you choose to call it, is formed.
The first five parts constitute the descriptive section of the book.
There follows an analysis of the
traditional democratic theory of public opinion. The substance of the argument is that
democracy in its
30
original form never seriously faced the problem which arises because the
pictures inside people’s heads do not automatically correspond with the world
outside. And then, because the
democratic theory is under criticism by socialist thinkers, there follows an
examination of the most advanced and coherent of these criticisms, as made by
the English Guild Socialists. My
purpose here is to find out whether these reformers take into account the main
difficulties of public opinion. My
conclusion is that they ignore the difficulties, as completely as did the
original democrats, because they, too, assume, and in a much more complicated
civilization, that somehow mysteriously there exists in the hearts of men a
knowledge of the world beyond their reach.
I argue that representative government, either in what is ordinarily
called politics, or in industry, cannot be worked successfully, no matter what
the basis of election, unless there is an independent, expert organization for
making the unseen facts intelligible to those who have to make the decisions.
I attempt, therefore, to argue that
the serious acceptance of the principle that personal representation must be
supplemented by representation of the unseen facts would alone permit a
satisfactory decentralization, and allow us to escape from the intolerable and
unworkable fiction that each of us must acquire a competent opinion about all
public affairs. It is argued that
the problem of the press is confused because the critics and the apologists
expect the press to realize this fiction, expect it to make up for all that was
not foreseen in the theory of democ-
31
racy, and that the readers expect this miracle to be performed at no cost or trouble to themselves. The newspapers are regarded by democrats as a panacea for their own defects, whereas analysis of the nature of news and of the economic basis of journalism seems to show that the newspapers necessarily and inevitably reflect, and therefore, in greater or lesser measure, intensify, the defective organization of public opinion. My conclusion is that public opinions must be organized for the press if they are to be sound, not by the press as is the case today. This organization I conceive to be in the first instance the task of a political science that has won its proper place as formulator, in advance of real decision, instead of apologist, critic, or reporter after the decision has been made. I try to indicate that the perplexities of government and industry are conspiring to give political science this enormous opportunity to enrich itself and to serve the public. And, of course, I hope that these pages will help a few people to realize that opportunity more vividly, and therefore to pursue it more consciously.
32