The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
William Newman *Technology and Alchemical Debate in the Late Middle
Ages
Isis,
80 (3Sept., 1989, 423-445.
Content
Alchemical Debate in the Thirteenth
Century Vincent of Beauvais, Albertus Magnus, and Roger
Bacon Alchemical Debate in the Late Thirteenth Century: Paul
of Taranto Anti-Alchemical Sentiment in the Late Thirteenth Century Appendix: Text of Paul of Taranto’s Discussion of the Types of Human Technology |
THE MEDIEVAL ATTITUDE toward technology is one of the
more interesting topics available to historians concerned with the transition
from antiquity to modernity. Considerable debate has focused on the
sweeping claims made by Lynn White for the social and cultural impact of
technological changes wrought in the Middle Ages. [1] Others, such as Guy Beaujouan and James
Weisheipl, have looked at Scholastic classifications of the arts and sciences
and found a higher appreciation for the role of the artisan in society than
earlier sources betray. [2] Despite the growing consensus that the Middle Ages
provided a fertile seedbed for technological development, one significant
contemporary debate has been largely overlooked, namely, the late medieval
dispute over the importance of alchemy - whether it fit into the legitimate
fields of knowledge and whether its claims were possible or even legal.
3 Why should we consider this topic within the context of
medieval technology? As I shall
show in this essay, alchemy provided a natural focus for the issue of man’s
artisanal power in the natural world.
The medieval world view was marked by a deep division
between art and nature. Stemming
partly from Aristotle, and partly from other Greek, Latin,
and
* Department of
History of Science, Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts
02138.
The research for this article was made possible through
the generous funding of the Belgian American Educational Foundation, the Sheldon
Traveling Fellowship and the Niles G. Whiting Fellowship of Harvard University,
and the National Science Foundation. I would also like to thank John E.
Murdoch of Harvard University and Robert Halleux of the Université de Liege.
An earlier version of the article
won the Schuman Prize in 1986.
1. Lynn White, jr., Medieval Technology and Social
Change (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1962). A generally positive assessment of
White’s work can be found in Brian Stock, “Science, Technology, and Economic
Progress in the Early Middle Ages,” in Science in the Middle Ages, ed.
David C. Lindberg (Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press, 1978), pp. 1-51. For general treatments of medieval
technology, see Bertrand Gille, Histoire generale des techniques, ed.
Maurice Daumas, 5 vols. (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1962-1979),
Vol. I, pp. 427-598, and Vol. II, pp. 2-139; and Jean Gimpel, The
Medieval Machine (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1976). For the aura of magic surrounding
technology in the Middle Ages see William Eamon, “Technology as Magic in the
Late Middle Ages and the Renaissance,” Janus, 1983,
70(3-4):171-212. See also
Bert Hanson, “Science and Magic,” in Lindberg, Science in the Middle Ages,
pp. 483-506.
2. Guy Beaujouan, L’interdépendence entre la
science scolastique et les techniques utilitaires (XIIe, XIIIe, et XIVe siècles)
(Conference faite au Palais de la Découverte, ser. D, 46) (Paris: Université
de Paris, 1957); James Weisheipl, “The Nature, Scope, and Classification of the
Sciences,” in Lindberg, Science in the Middle Ages, pp. 473-474, 480; and
Weisheipl, “Classification of the Sciences in Medieval Thought,” Mediaeval
Studies, 1965, 27:54-90. See also Jan Legowizc, “Le problème
de la theorie dans les artes illiberales et la conception de la science
au moyen age,” in Arts libéraux et philosophie au moyen age: Actes du
quatriême congrès internationale de philosophie médiévale (Montreal:
Institut d’Etudes Médiévales, 1969), pp. 1057-1061.
3. On the issue of legality in this context see Johannes
Chrisippus Fanianus, De lure artis alchemiae in J. J. Manget,
Bibliotheca chemica curiosa, Vol. I (Geneva, 1702), pp.
210-216.
423
Arabic sources, this view placed strict boundaries on
the conceptual limits of technical innovation. The twelfth-century monastic writer Hugh
of Saint Victor, famous for his influential inclusion of technology in the field
of the sciences, wrote that “the products of artificers, while not nature,
imitate nature, and in the design by which they imitate, they express the form
of their exemplar, which is nature.” Here Hugh is merely echoing the
conviction of ancient Greek philosophy that the various branches of the
“mechanical arts,” what we would call technology, were originally learned by
copying natural processes. As he
also writes, “The human work, because it is not nature but only imitative of
nature, is fitly called mechanical, that is adulterate.” [4] The pejorative view that the mechanical arts derived
their name from the Greek word for adultery (moicheia), because of their
trickery, was of course widespread in the Latin West. [5] Although man could copy nature by means of art, his
products - however cunning - could never be identical to their natural models.
Hugh of Saint Victor was one of the
more appreciative writers to consider the “adulterine arts,” among which he
grouped “fabric making, armament, commerce, agriculture, hunting, medicine, and
theatrics,” [6] but he too
considered them to be born of - and limited to - the mimicry of
nature.
Latin alchemists did not generally strive to vitiate the
principle enunciated by Hugh of Saint Victor; on the contrary, few medieval
alchemical works fail to pay homage to the notion that “art imitates nature.”
But alchemical writers, unlike
those in the mainstream of the Scholastic tradition, were willing to argue that
human art, even if it learned by imitating natural processes, could successfully
reproduce natural products or even surpass them. In so doing the alchemists of the Middle
Ages developed a clearly articulated philosophy of technology, in which human
art is raised to a level of appreciation difficult to find in
other
4. The Didascalicon of Hugh of Saint Victor, ed.
and trans. Jerome Taylor (New York: Columbia Univ. Press, 1961), pp. 51,
55-56 (all quotations here from Hugh’s Didascalicon are from
Taylor’s English translation). Taylor suggests that Hugh’s depiction of
the relationship between art and nature is drawn from Chalcidius’s early
medieval commentary on the Timaeus. See also, e.g., Aristotle,
Meteorologica, 381b6-7; Physics, 199a15-17. Further sources are explored in Kurt
Flasch, “Ars imitatur naturam,” in Parusia: Studien zur Philosophie Platons
und zur Problemgeschichte des Platonismus (Frankfurt: Minerva, 1965), pp.
265-306. Stock has found Hugh of
Saint Victor’s inclusion of seven mechanical arts among the traditional liberal
ones “in an early Ysagoge in theologiam, in an exposition of Martianus of
Capella, and in the Aeneid commentary attributed to Bernard Silvester”:
“Science, Technology” (cit. n. 1), pp. 45-48. See also George Ovitt, Jr., “The Status
of the Mechanical Arts in Medieval Classifications of Learning,” Viator,
1983, 14:89-105, and Lynn White, jr., “Cultural Climates and Technological
Advance in the Middle Ages,” Viator, 1971, 2: 171-201, esp. pp.
196-197, where the positive influence of Hugh’s Didascalicon is
discussed.
5. Lynn White’s belief that this spurious etymology “was
to have small influence in the West” (“Cultural Climates,” cit. n. 4, pp.
192-193) is contradicted by the many examples collected by Peter Sternagel,
Die artes mechanicae im Mittelalter, Vol.
II of Münchener Historische
Studien, Abteilung Mittelalterliche Geschichte (Kallmünz Uber Regensburg:
Michael Lassleben, 1966). Among
these we find the 9th-century monastic writer Martin of Laon, who very possibly
originated this derivation of mechanica, the 9th-l0th-century figure
Remigius of Auxerre; the anonymous Bamberger classification of the sciences
dating from the early 12th century; the 12th-century writers Richard of Saint
Victor, Bernardus Silvestris, and the canonist Hugutio; an anonymous commentary
on Aristotle’s Perihermeneias; and such 13th-century authors as Radolfus
de Longo Campo (c. 1216), Vincent of Beauvais, Albertus Magnus, Johannes Balbi
(c. 1286), and Engelbert of Admont (fi. 1250-1331); see pp. 45-46, 89-91. Sternagel maintains that learned society
gradually devalued the mechanical arts between the beginning of the 12th century
and the middle of the 13th; the artisans themselves were of course making real
technological progress.
6. Hugh, Didascalicon (cit. n. 4), p.
74.
424
writings until the Renaissance. The degree to which medieval alchemists and their supporters were forced to develop their positive views about the power of technology in order to salvage their art from the increasingly hostile audience of the late Middle Ages is truly remarkable. This essay will attempt to trace the alchemical debate from its inception in the second half of the twelfth century up to a definite crisis reached in the first quarter of the fourteenth century.
[7]
ALCHEMICAL DEBATE IN THE
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
Alchemy first made its appearance in the Latin West
around the mid twelfth century, when Robert of Ketton translated the De
compositione alchemiae of Morienus from Arabic into Latin. Between the time of Robert’s translation
and the end of the fourteenth century, a massive quantity of alchemical
literature appeared in Latin, much of it original in character. Yet the university curricula of the
Middle Ages did not choose to incorporate alchemy, nor did any institutes of
higher learning teach it until the early seventeenth century. [8] Although many medieval alchemical works were apparently
written by Scholastic authors, using their characteristically dry, orderly style
of exposition, the Scholastics effectually relegated alchemy to the category of
marginality by denying it university status.
The reasons for this are complex. It is not enough to say that the medieval
universities were bastions of Aristotelianism and that Aristotle had nothing to
say about alchemy. Although both
halves of this statement are from a modern perspective true, they are
misleading. First, some Scholastic
writers steeped in Aristotle, such as Albertus Magnus and Roger Bacon,
definitely believed in the possibility of alchemical transmutation, as I shall
presently elaborate. In fact, the
alchemy of the late Middle Ages was a perfectly reasonable and sober offshoot of
Aristotle’s theory of matter. In
this we must carefully distinguish medieval alchemy from the eclectic,
Neoplatonic alchemy of the Renaissance, suffused with theosophy and
cabalism.
Second, it was commonly believed in the late Middle Ages
that Aristotle himself had written about alchemy. At least eighteen different pseudonymous
works on alchemy attributed to Aristotle in the late Middle Ages survive in
modern libraries. One alchemical
work of the late twelfth or early thirteenth century
7. This topic has been touched on in a brief and rather
ahistorical fashion by Reijer Hooykaas, Religion and the Rise of Modern
Science (Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press, 1972), pp. 55-58. A more useful synopsis ignores the
influence of Avicenna: Chiara Crisciani, “La ‘quaestio de alchimia’ fra duecento
e trecento,” Medioevo: Rivista di Storia della Filosofia Medievale, 1976,
2:119-168. Crisciani’s useful study of an alchemical systematist of the l330s
falls outside the chronological scope of this essay: “The Conception of Alchemy
as Expressed in the Pretiosa Margarita Novella of Petrus Bonus of
Ferrara,” Ambix, 1973, 20: 147-162.
8. For Robert of Ketton see Robert Halleux, Les textes
alchimiques: Typologie des sources du moyen age occidental (Turnhout,
Belgium: Brepols, 1979), fasc. 39, pp. 49, 70; this work contains by far the
best available treatment of the historiography of medieval alchemy as a whole.
Some controversy still lingers as
to the genuineness of the Morienus text and its ascription to Robert; see Julius
Ruska, “Zwei Bûcher de compositione alchemiae und ihre Vorreden,” Archiv für
die Geschichte der Mathematik, der Naturwissenschaften, und der Technik,
1928, 11:28-37; and Lee Stavenhagen, “The Original Text of the Latin
Morienus,” Ambix, 1970, 17:1-12. On the integration of alchemy into the
German universities during the Scientific Revolution see Owen Hannaway, The
Chemists and the Word: The Didactic Origins of Chemistry (Baltimore, Md.:
Johns Hopkins Press, 1975).
425
attributed to Aristotle exists today in over thirty-five manuscripts, many of them medieval
. [9] Similarly, a long section of Avicenna’s Book of the Remedy that attacked alchemy was habitually attributed to Aristotle by medieval writers. Some, confronted by Aristotle’s seeming to support alchemy in one text while attacking it in another, went so far as to devise a developmental hypothesis in which the young Stagyrite was harshly critical but changed his views in the wisdom of old age. [10Nor is it sufficient to argue that alchemy was denied
university status because of its characterization as a technology (mechanical
art). In fact, alchemy occupied a
medial position between the arts and the sciences, a position also occupied by
medicine. Like medicine, alchemy
consisted of a body of theory about certain aspects of the natural world; this
theory was then used to support a plethora of manual practices. Thomas Aquinas, to cite one example,
variously calls alchemy an “operative science,” a “mechanical art,” and an
“operative art.” In the first case,
he ranks “medicine, alchemy, and moral [philosophy] [11] together, since they have a
practical use and pertain more to specific subjects than do such fields as
metaphysics, physics, and mathematics. In the second and third cases, Thomas
groups alchemy with agriculture and medicine as technological pursuits
subordinate to physics.” But the
medieval university curriculum frequently included such subjects as medicine and
moral philosophy, despite Thomas’s classification of them as, respectively,
“mechanical” or “operative.” We
cannot therefore view the learned disdain for the practical and technological as
sufficient cause for alchemy’s exclusion from the medieval university, though it
may have been a contributing factor.
Far more convincing explanations for alchemy’s lack of
institutional success than such general ones as the genuine Aristotle’s silence
or the learned disdain for technology can be found by examining specific
medieval documents. It then becomes
clear that between the time of alchemy’s inception in the mid-twelfth century
and the end of the thirteenth century a general backlash against this discipline
gradually developed, with mainstream scientific and religious authorities coming
to agree in its denunciation. In
such an atmosphere it would have been academically unprofitable, to say the
least, for a university master to teach alchemy publicly. The result is that alchemical writers
went “underground.” Anyone who
seriously consults the alchemical bibliography of the Latin Middle Ages cannot
fail to be impressed by the large number of pseudepigrapha. [12] The
9. Charles B. Schmitt and Dilwyn Knox,
Pseudo-Aristoteles Latinus: A Guide to Latin Works Falsely Attributed to
Aristotle before 1500 (Warburg Institute Surveys and Texts, 12) (London:
Warburg Institute, 1985), entry 58; for texts primarily or exclusively of
alchemical content, see entries 1-5, 10, 21-22, 25-26, 54-56, 58, 73-74, 85, and
93. Other texts, such as the
Secretum secretorum, contain substantial sections on
alchemy.
10. Petrus Bonus, Margarita pretiosa, in Jean
Jacques Manget, Bibliotheca chemica curiosa, Vol. II (Geneva, 1702), pp.
76, 80.
11. See Thomas Aquinas, in his commentary on
Boethius’s De trinitate: “Et ideo etiam quanto alia scientia magis
appropinquat ad singularia, sicut scientiae operativae, ut medicina, ailchimia,
et moralis, minus possunt habere de certitudine.” S. Thomae Aquinatis opera
omnia, curante Roberto Busa S.I. (Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog, 1980), Vol.
IV, p. 536, col. 3. On p. 532, col. 1, Thomas classes agriculture, alchemy, and
“aliae artes quae dicuntur mechanicae” together, again as “operative arts,” and
at p. 533, col. 1, he explicitly subordinates medicine, alchemy, and agriculture
to physics.
12. Over 30 medieval alchemical works are
attributed to Albertus Magnus alone: Pearl Kibre, “Alchemical Writings Ascribed
to Albertus Magnus,” Speculum: A Journal of Medieval Studies, 1942,
17:499-518. I have recently
proved that the Semita recta, long considered to have the greatest claim
[to authenticity of any Albertine alchemical
work, is a forgery: William Newman,
“The Genesis of the Summa perfectionis,” Archives Internationales d’Histoire
des Sciences, 1985, 35:240-302, esp. pp. 246-260.]
HHC: [bracketed] displayed
on page 427 of original.
426
following discussion will not limit itself to the
recapitulation of Scholastic viewpoints concerning alchemy but will also examine
some of this pseudonymous literature. We shall find that, in the process of
justifying this discipline before its opponents, the alchemists and their
supporters gave a conscious and articulate defense of technology, indeed, one of
the earliest and most thorough to be found in Latin Christendom. The texts to be discussed make up a
disputation literature that may justly be called the “alchemical debate” of the
late Middle Ages, although this debate was not really resolved until the
university of the Scientific Revolution incorporated chemistry as a part of its
curriculum.
Our story begins with the English translator Alfred of Sareshel, who around 1200 translated a meteorological section of the Persian philosopher Avicenna’s (980-1037) Kitãb a1-Shifaد (The Book of the Remedy) and inserted it into the fourth book of Aristotle’s Meteorologica, already translated by Henricus Aristippu
s. [13] This short text, which came to be known in Latin as De congelatione et conglutinatione lapidum, immediately acquired the authority of a genuine Aristotelian production, since it appeared to be the conclusion of the Meteorologica’s fourth book. [14] It became thereby the locus classicus for all subsequent attacks on alchemy, and virtually any alchemical writer - whether philosophically sophisticated or not - felt obliged to respond to the arguments of “Aristotle” (i.e., Avicenna). In the process, the De congelatione of Avicenna became a focal point for the discussion of human artisanal power in general.The De congelatione contains a description of
geological processes, including the formation of the known metals - gold,
silver, copper, tin, lead, and iron. Following the doctrines of Arabic
alchemy, Avicenna asserts that these six are composed of mercury (mercury is
considered not a metal but a component of metals) and sulfur in varying
quantities and degrees of purity. It therefore comes as something of a
shock when he proceeds to denounce the doctrine of metallic transmutation, upon
which alchemical practice is based. Avicenna’s main points may be summarized
under two heads:
1. Artificial and natural products are intrinsically
different, for art is inherently inferior to nature and cannot hope to equal it.
Therefore artificers cannot change
an inferior metal to a better one, although they can produce passable imitations
of the precious metals by inducing superficial
characteristics.
2. The true species-determining characteristics of
metals cannot be known, since they subsist beneath the level of sense. Since these specific differences are
unknown, it will be impossible to bring about the
13. James Otte, “The Life and Writings of Alfredus
Anglicus,” Viator, 1972, 3:275-291.
14. Avicennae de congelatione et conglutinatione
lapidum, ed. and trans. E. J. Holmyard and D. C. Mandeville (Paris:
Geuthner, 1927), pp. 1-11. Unfortunately, these editors have not
supplied a critical Latin text. I
have prepared a temporary working edition of the section known as Sciant
artifices (discussed below) in William Newman, “The Summa Perfectionis
and Late Medieval Alchemy,” 4 vols. (Ph.D. diss., Harvard Univ., 1986), Vol.
I, pp. 59-62.
427
transmutation of one metal into another, for the
alchemist cannot manipulate what he does not know.
Avicenna’ s argument may seem prima facie self-evident
to the modern reader, but the terms “species” and “specific difference” are
somewhat nuanced. Avicenna’s
terminology has a logical basis. When he used the term nauد,
rendered in Latin by Alfred of Sareshel as species, he meant above
all to refer to the group of characteristics defining a particular kind of
thing. To Avicenna there are six
such species among metals: gold, silver, copper, iron, tin, and lead. All six belong to the more general
genus of metals, which he informally defines as “malleable,” “fusible,”
“mineral” (that is to say “mined”) bodies. [15] Hence each type of metal shares the set of properties
that define the genus: anything that is a malleable, fusible body found in mines
will be a metal. But the metals are
not all identical: gold, silver, copper, iron, tin, and lead, while metals, also
have their own specific differences that make each of them belong to a
particular species. The thrust of
Avicenna’ s conclusion is that the specific differences that make metals fall
into different species are not such easily perceived properties as melting
point, malleability, specific gravity, and color. Instead, the specific differences are
really underlying and imperceptible: we cannot know them, and therefore we
cannot change them.
It may be tempting for the modern reader to view
Avicenna’s rejection of alchemy as a forward-looking event that foreshadowed the
weaning of chemistry from the “irrational” or “pseudoscientific” doctrines of
alchemy. A closer look will reveal,
however, that it was Avicenna, and not the alchemists, who held reactionary
views. Avicenna begins his attack
with the “self-evident” assertion that natural products are intrinsically
superior to their artificial counterparts and that the latter cannot possibly
match up to the naturally occurring exemplars of which they are copies. As two modern commentators on the De
congelatione have remarked, Avicenna would have been on the side of “the
general public [today], who usually imagine that synthetic indigo, for example,
is not veritable indigo, but only a very good imitation.” [16
Avicenna, though basing himself on an ancient prejudice,
in fact takes a considerably stronger position about the schism between natural
and artificial products than did Aristotle. In the Physics (2.8, 199a) the
latter allows art either to mimic nature or to carry some of her works to a
greater state of perfection than they would otherwise have: “One sort of art
perfects that which nature cannot complete, while another sort imitates nature.”
[17] One almost gets the impression that a personal
experience with alchemical counterfeiters led Avicenna to his disdain for human
art as expressed in the De congelatione. Whatever the
sources
15. Avicenna, De congelatione, pp. 32-33.
Nauد is an Arabic rendering of the Greek eidos, used by Aristotle
to denote either “species” or “form.” In the De congelatione Avicenna
uses the Latin species primarily to distinguish the individual types of
metal (such as lead and tin) from the genus of metals in general. See Ibrãhim Madkûr, L’organon
d’Aristote dans le monde Arabe: Ses traducions, ses etudes, et ses applications
(Etudes Musulmanes, 10) (Paris: Vrin, 1969), pp. 70, 299. For the term itself see Avicenna, De
congelatione, p. 24. My
discussion of this topic owes a debt to conversations with John Murdoch and A.
I. Sabra.
16. Holmyard and Mandeville, in Avicenna, De
congelatione, p. 41, n. 5.
17. Aristotle, De physico auditu, in
Aristotelis opera cum Averrois commentariis, Vol. IV (Venice, 1562), fol.
78r, col. 2: “Et omnino ars alia quidem perficit que natura non potest efficere,
alia vero imitatur.”
428
for his view, the universal proposition that art is
inferior to nature, coupled to the belief that natural species are
intransmutable, constituted an attack not on alchemy alone but on the totality
of technology and applied science. Avicenna’ s point was not merely that
human technology cannot outdo nature but that man cannot even hope to
imitate nature in a truly successful fashion. Avicenna thus first clothes the ancient
philosophical disdain for technology in the form of an “authoritative”
enunciation, then spells out the specific reasons for alchemy’s failure in terms
of Aristotelian natural philosophy. Later we shall find such varied claims as
the impotence of demons to work miracles and the inability of horticulturalists
to produce new breeds of plants supported by reference to Avicenna’s dictum that
alchemists cannot transmute species. The effects of the De congelatione
were by no means restricted to alchemy but served to crystallize an
antitechnological bias in many areas.
In response to Avicenna’s dictum that species are
intransmutable - which came to be referred to in abbreviated form by the incipit
Sciant artifices - the alchemists developed counterarguments
adopting a radical view of technology in which man assumed extraordinary power
over nature. Centuries before
Francis Bacon’s philosophy of nature with its Draconian decree to “put nature to
the rack,” we find protagonists of alchemy asserting that man’s ability to
transform the natural world is virtually unbounded. Their justification of human art was not
based on vague optimism, however; it was supported by practical observation,
analogical reasoning, and a Neoplatonizing
Aristotelianism.
One of the earliest sets of counterarguments to the De congelatione can be found in a pseudonymous Book of Hermes written in the first half of the thirteenth century or before. This work contains a series of elliptical attacks on alchemy, each with its matching rebuttal. The first argument, that metals are natural products and hence may not be replicated by artificial means, implicitly contains Avicenna’s axiom that natural products are always better than artificial ones. The author of Hermes rebuts this by saying that human technology frequently succeeds better than nature herself, since artificial verdigris, vitriol, zinc oxide, and sal ammoniac are all better than the naturally occurring forms, “which [anyone] who knows about minerals does not contradict.”
[18] Similarly, the horticulturist improves on nature by making successful graftings. We have here a sort of manifesto proclaiming the power of technology in general and chemical technology in particular. Interestingly, “Hermes” does not deny that art learns by mimicking nature: in order to eviscerate Avicenna’s proposition that art is weaker than nature, it is sufficient for him to point to the empirical fact that certain products have greater efficacy when prepared artificially.When the author of Hermes comes to Avicenna’s
assertion that species cannot be transmuted, he adopts the approach of logic: he
replies that the metals belong
18. Liber Hermetis, quoting from the partial
working edition in Newman, “The Summa perfectionis” (cit. n. 14), Vol. I,
pp. 63-67, on p. 65, 11. 36-40: “Sal vero viride et dragantum et thutia et sal
armoniacus et naturalia et artificialia sunt. Immo et artificialia naturalibus potiora
sunt, quod qui de mineriis sciunt non contradicunt.” The Liber Hermetis has never been
printed, or for that matter analyzed. I have found it in the following
l3th-l4th-century MSS: Cambridge, Trinity College 1400, fols. 131r-l33r; Oxford,
Bodleian Library (BL), Bodley 679, fols. 20r-2lr; London, British Museum (BM),
Add. 41486, fols. 218r-222r; Paris, Bibliothèque Nationale (BN), Latin (Lat.)
6514, fols. 135r- v; and in the following 14th-century MSS: London, BM, Sloane
1754, fols. 60r62r; Palermo, Biblioteca Communale, 4QqAl0, fol. 37v
(incomplete).
429
to a single definition, any metal being “a composite,
fusible, incombustible, ma!leable body.” [19] Logically, there is no compelling reason why this should
be called a genus rather than a species, since such differentiation is merely a
matter of degree (a genus is merely comprehended by a more general definition
than a species). In providing a
single definition for all the metals, the author of Hermes can therefore
argue that they all belong to a single “species,” and that the “species” of
which Avicenna speaks are by implication only “more specific species”
(species specialiores). Thus
The Book of Hermes does not need the transmutation of species. This purely logical approach to
undermining the Sciant artifices soon gave way in the West to a more
hylomorphic tendency. As we shall
see, Albertus Magnus - among others - took Avicenna’s species to mean a
form that “inheres” physically in the substance of a metal in order to determine
its particular set of characteristics. Although permissible within the framework
of Aristotelian philosophy (where eidos means either “species” or
“form”), Albert’s interpretation would have the effect of turning Avicenna’s
discussion of genera and species into an argument about matter and
form.
VINCENT OF BEAUVAIS, ALBERTUS
MAGNUS, AND ROGER BACON
The Book of Hermes, although it offered a
succinct and early defense of alchemy, does not seem to have been known to the
three Scholastic authors of the mid thirteenth century most concerned with
alchemy, Vincent of Beauvais, Albertus Magnus, and Roger Bacon. The works of these three authorities
provide a gauge of the degree of controversy alchemy aroused at that
time.
I will dispense with Vincent briefly, since he gives a rambling account of alchemy, devoid of originality. Vincent wrote his Speculum doctrinale and Speculum naturale between 1244 and 1250
. [20] Since these two works contain much the same material on alchemy and on mineralogy in general, I shall focus on the somewhat more orderly Speculum doctrinale. The Speculum doctrinale places alchemy among the mechanical arts. Alchemy, unlike the sciences per se, is merely useful from a practical point of view - to the metalworker, since it teaches “the examination, intermixture, separation, and transmutation” of the metals, and to the physician, because it aids in the isolation of healthy from harmful components, which “are often found mixed together in simple medicines.” Vincent adds that alchemy is descended from the “science of minerals” (ab illa parte naturalis philosophic que est de mineris) in the same way that agriculture is derived from the “science of plants.” To Vincent, therefore, alchemy “is properly the art of transmuting mineral bodies, such as metals and the like, from their own species to others.” [21]19. Ibid., p. 66, 11. 57-61: “De speciali vero
differentia cui dubium est metalla specialiter non differe, cum in una
diffinitione conveniant. Verbi
gratia, corpus compositum, in igne fusibile, non combustibile, sub malleo
extendibile.”
20. William A. Wallace, “Vincent of Beauvais,”
Dictionary of Scientific Biography, ed. Charles C. Gillispie, 16 vols.
(New York: Scribners, 1970-1980) (hereafter DSB), Vol. XIV, p.
35.
21. Vincent of Beauvais, Speculum doctrinale
(Venice, 1494), Book 11, Ch. 105: “Ad fabrilem quidem propter metallorum
examinationem, commixtionem, disgregationem, transmutationem. Ad medicinam
itidem propter substantiarum vel qualitatum salubrium a noxiis que frequenter
etiam in medicinis simplicibus permixte sunt separationem… Alkimia proprie est
ars transmutandi corpora mineralia a propriis speciebus ad alias, ut sunt
metalla et huiusmodi.”
430
So far, Vincent is reasonably consistent: he considers
alchemy to be a simple practical art, entirely devoid of theoretical content.
But the Speculum doctrinale
here begins to contradict itself, for the introductory passage is directly
followed by passages from alchemical writers giving long theoretical
descriptions of the generation of minerals from sulfur and mercury within the
earth. Clearly this is a
speculative sort of alchemy, not just a mechanical art. A parallel confusion reigns in Vincent’s
description of Avicenna’s attack on alchemy. He quotes Avicenna’s broadside without
giving his own point of view, then replies with an extract from pseudo-Avicenna
containing a number of garbled arguments in favor of alchemy. [22]
Vincent’s rather complacent and confused account of
alchemy is followed chronologically by the De mineralibus of Albertus
Magnus. Here we find a considerably
more coherent assessment. Between
1250 and 1254 Albert took on the task of writing a comprehensive study of
mineralogy as part of his endeavor to explain the totality of natural science. [23] Since Albert could find no Aristotelian book on minerals
to comment on, he had to turn to the texts of the
alchemists.
In the course of his investigation, Albert therefore felt the need to respond to the arguments of the De congelatione, which he knew to be a work of Avicenna’s. Albert begins his analysis of transmutation with an attack on previous authors who have proposed that all metals share one form, that of gold, in varying states of completion. Arguing from sense, he says that the metals appear to be “stable” (permanens); under normal circumstances they do not become other metals. Therefore they must each have their own substantial form by which they are “perfected.” Similarly, each metal has its own peculiar set of properties, so their accidents are not common. As a result, “the substances and specific form [species] [of different metals] must be different.”
[24]Given that Albert believes the metals to differ in their species, we might expect him to uphold the viewpoint of the De congelatione. This is not the case, however. In a special chapter he directly attacks the pronouncement Sciant artifices, where Avicenna had argued that alchemists could not transmute species. In this chapter it becomes clear that Albert has understood the Latin species to mean “specific form.” [25]
This substitution of “specific form” for “species” allows Albert to circumvent the Sciant artifices, since he can now draw on a well-defined Scholastic theory concerning the physical corruption of a preexistent form followed by the induction of a subsequent form. Thus Albert believes that species22. Ibid., Book 8, Chs. 42,
84.
23. Robert Halleux, “Albert le grand et l’alchimie,”
Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Theologiques, 1982,
66(l):58.
24. Albertus Magnus: Book of Minerals,
trans. Dorothy Wyckoff (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1967), pp. 172—173. Here as elsewhere Wyckoff uses the
expression “specific form” for the Latin species. Wyckoff’s translation, however,
obscures the fact that Albert’s argument is motivated by the Sciant artifices
of Avicenna. Like Avicenna,
Albert uses the Latin term species rather than forma specifica,
though what he means is closer to the latter.
25. Ibid., pp. 177-179. For the original Latin see Albertus
Magnus, Mineralium libri quinque, in B. Alberti Magni . . .
opera omnia, ed. Auguste Borgnet, Vol. V (Paris, 1890), pp. 70-71. For further evidence that Albert
conflates species and forma specifica see the following passages:
“Experimenta autem alchimicorum graves duas nobis hic ingerunt dubitationes.
Videntur enim illi dicere quod sola
auri species est forma metallorum” (68a); and “Quod si forte concederetur quod
substantiam auri inducat, adhuc non est sufficiens probatio ad hoc quod non sit
nisi una species metallorum: quoniam calcinando et sublimando et distillando et
caeteris operationibus quibus elixir per matenam metallorum faciunt
penetrare, corrumpere potest species metallorum quae primitus infuerunt materiae
metallorum” (69a).
431
can indeed be transmuted, inasmuch as one specific form
can be destroyed and replaced by another.
Albert’s interpretation, however, slightly distorts Avicenna’s use of the Arabic term nauد, or species, in the De congelatione. By species Avicenna meant primarily a logical entity, in the same way that the term is contrasted to genus by logicians. In the De congelatione Avicenna does not speak of species as “inhering” in matter, or as being corrupted and induced. Instead, his species are above all abstract categories that existed in the Creator’s mind when he fashioned the natural world. To say that such logical species are transmutable would be fatuous indeed, since they represent the distinct underlying concepts by which God created separate metals
[26]At any rate, armed with his hylomorphic interpretation
of “species,” Albert says that honest alchemists act toward metals just as
physicians do toward their patients. [27] The alchemist first cleans and purifies the old metal,
just as a doctor employs emetics and diaphoretics to purge his patient. Then he strengthens the “elemental and
celestial powers” in the metal’s substance, apparently by adding druglike
components and observing astrological “judgments.” As a result, the purged metal receives a
new and better specific form from the celestial virtues of the stars. Hence the alchemist has not transmuted
any species: he has only removed one specific form and prepared the way for
another to be received.
Albert’s benign view of alchemy does not bear witness to
a heated debate on this subject. He
is not responding to any moderni but only to Avicenna and other Arabic
authors. The equanimity of his
tone, furthermore, seems to reflect a period in which alchemical transmutation
was not yet a genera! subject of irascible dispute. When we turn to Roger Bacon, the
atmosphere changes radically.
Roger wrote his Opus tertium around the year
1266, as a part of the trilogy also comprising his Opus maius and Opus
minus. The three books were
intended as an advertisement for reform, and as such they were sent by special
courier to Roger’s friend Clement IV. [28] In the Opus tertium Roger proposes that alchemy
should form the primary means of reforming Scholastic science. He asserts that alchemy teaches things of
which Aristotle was completely ignorant, such as the precise generation of
minerals, pigments, precious stones, and humors from the elements. Furthermore, since alchemy is the science
of the elements per se, while natural philosophy and medicine concern things
made out of the four elements, such as the four humors, alchemy is the most
basic of the sciences. Hence
Roger’s approbation of alchemy far exceeds that of Vincent or Albert: whereas
they see alchemy as primarily a practical art whose masters have provided
empirical examples for real philosophers to explain, he wants to make it the
wellspring of all medical and natural knowledge. Although modern historians have stressed
Roger’s mathematics (to the ultimate misfortune of the poor
friar),
26. Avicenna attacked specific transmutation in at least
one other text: the [HHC: Arabic not reproduced].. Georges C. Anawati
paraphrases it as follows: “Ce sont des absurdités [specific transmutation]; car
pour tout ce que Dieu a créé moyennant la force de la nature, l’imitation
artificielle est impossible; comme au contraire les productions artificielles et
scientifiques n’appartiennent d’aucune manière àla nature.” Anawati, “Avicenne et l’alchimie,” in
Oriente e Occidente nel Medioevo: Filosofia e scienze (Rome: Academia
Nazionale di Lincei, 1971), pp. 285-341, on pp. 300-301.
27. Albertus Magnus, Book of Minerals (cit.
n. 23), pp. 178-179.
28. A. C. Crombie and J. D. North, “Roger Bacon,” in
DSB, Vol. I, p. 378.
432
we must note that in the passage above he explicitly lauds alchemy as “greater than all the foregoing [sciences],” of which the science of mathematics was one. [
29]It is equally significant that Roger nowhere mentions the attack of the De congelatione in the three Opera addressed to Clement IV. Why, after all, should he have interjected the views of a doubting Thomas into his promotional broadsides? But Roger clearly knew the Sciant artifices from an early date, since he supported its point of view in his commentary of about 1245 on the pseudo-Aristotelian De plantis
. [30] There he universalizes the proposition that “species cannot be transmuted,” taking this supposedly Aristotelian view to apply to plants as well as metals. Clearly Roger underwent a serious change of mind between 1245 and the 1260s. If we examine his Communium naturalium of 1266, the reason for his new disregard of the Sciant artifices appears. Here he attacks its attribution to Aristotle. [31] Despite the view of “fools,” he says, the Sciant artifices is only a second-rate commentary by Alfred of Sareshel. By replacing the authority of Aristotle with that of Alfred, Roger makes it an easy matter to dismiss the proposition that species may not be transmuted. In the Communium naturalium Roger goes far beyond his predecessors in rejecting the theoretical validity of the Sciant artifices. Whereas Vincent chose to take no position, and Albert circumvented the issue by interpreting species to mean specific form, Roger simply says that the proposition “species cannot be transmuted” is not true.Furthermore, he adds that “fools” abuse the authority of
Aristotle by attributing this position to him, apparently in attacking alchemy.
Since Islamic authors did not
attribute the De congelatione to Aristotle, it follows that the fools to
whom Bacon refers must have been Latin fools. Albert’s dispute was limited to Arabs,
and Vincent found no need to take sides at all. It is therefore evident that the
alchemical debate had grown in magnitude since the 1240s and 1250s, when Vincent
and Albert were concerned with mineralogy. Further evidence is the great space given
to disputation in alchemical works written after 1250. One such work was written by a practicing
alchemist, probably in the last third of the thirteenth
century.
ALCHEMICAL DEBATE IN THE LATE
THIRTEENTH CENTURY: PAUL OF TARANTO
I have recently shown that Paul of Taranto, a thirteenth-century Franciscan, was the probable author of a famous alchemical text, the Summa perfectionis, spuriously attributed to the Arab Jãbir ibn Hayyãn
. [32] More pertinent to our present argument, however, is the defense of alchemy that Paul presents in another text, the Theorica et practica.29. Roger Bacon, Opus tertium, in Opera quaedam
hactenus inedita, ed. J. S. Brewer, Vol. I (London, 1859), pp.
39-40.
30. “Item, quarto Metheororum, ‘sciant artifices
alkimie species metallorum transmutari non posse,’ quare similiter nec species
plantarum”: Roger Bacon, Questiones supra de plantis, in Opera
hactenus inedita RogeriBaconi, ed. Robert Steele et al. (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1911-1940), Vol. XI (1932), ed. Steele and F. M. Delorme, p. 251; see
also p. 241.
31. Roger Bacon, Communium naturalium, in Opera
hactenus inedita, Vol. II (1911), ed. Steele, p.7.
32. See William Newman, “New Light on the Identity
of ‘Geber,’ “ Sudhoffs Archiv, 1985, 69:76-90; and Newman, “Genesis of
the Summa perfectionis” (cit. n. 12).
433
The Theorica et practica, as its title implies,
is a didactic work comprehending both the theoretical and the practical bases of
alchemy. It contains a long defense
of this discipline, in which Paul attempts to defuse the Sciant artifices
of pseudo-Aristotle. Paul
prefaces his specifically alchemical comments, however, with a general defense
of human art. He begins with a
proem, heavily dependent on the pseudo-Aristotelian Liber de causis, in
which he tries to justify the power of man over nature. He does this by identifying the Plotinian
hypostasis intellectus with the human intellect, a not-uncommon
conflation among thirteenth-century thinkers. Because nature is inferior and subject to
intellect, man must therefore be in a position to manipulate and rule nature.
Paul then proceeds to a special
chapter on the relation of art to nature (see Appendix). Since human intellect rules over nature,
he says, artisans such as “sculptors, painters, horticulturists and physicians”
have nature subjected to themselves “as matter and instrument.” Drawing on Aristotle’s Physics,
Book 2, Paul divides human art into two categories - that which generates an
“extrinsic” form, as in the case of painting and sculpting, and that which
terminates in an “intrinsic form,” such as medicine or agriculture. [33] Those arts that produce an intrinsic form use the
Aristotelian primary qualities - hot, cold, wet, and dry - as instruments. Arts inducing an extrinsic form rely on
secondary qualities, such as colors and tastes.
Arts such as agriculture and medicine that act on the
primary qualities can actually transmute substance, whereas sculpture, painting,
carpentry, and other arts that work only on secondary qualities can only induce
accidents into their subject. The
genuine physician, horticulturist, or alchemist, therefore, produces real
changes in essence and substance, because he manipulates the first qualities of
matter. False artisans, on the
other hand, produce only the appearance of change; they attack the symptom
rather than the cause. When Paul
comes to the Sciant artifices, he uses this bifurcation of the arts to
remove its force, saying, “We do not consider the opinion of Aristotle which he
writes at the end of the Meteorologica – “The alchemists should
know that species cannot be transmuted’ - to be true unless it be understood in
the foresaid way, [that is, as occurring] through purely artificial agents.” [34] In other words, the Sciant artifices holds only
if the artisan employs secondary, “artificial” qualities, since these do not
affect the substance of a given subject. Otherwise, if he uses primary qualities,
it is indeed possible to induce substantial change and thus to alter
species.
Paul of Taranto’s argument, although directed mainly
toward alchemy, is undeniably a justification of technology in general, since it
upholds the power of those arts capable of manipulating primary qualities to
induce real change in natural products. In other words, Paul consistently affirms
the power of man really to alter and improve natural products. At the same time, his reasoning
implicitly contains more than an apology for technical skill per se. By dividing the “arts” into two
categories he implicitly distinguishes between pure
technol-
33. Paul of Taranto, Theorica et practica, Paris,
BN, Lat. 7159, fols. Lr-55r, on fols. Lr-v, 2v, 11. 17-18. Since the Theorica et practica has
never been printed, quotations are from an edition I have prepared, available in
Newman, “The Summa perfectionis” (cit. n. 14), Vol. III, pp. 1-237. (See also the Appendix, for a partial
edition and translation and the other manuscripts.)
34. Paul of Taranto, Theorica et practica, fol.
4r, 11. 12-15: “Non putamus igitur esse verum verbum Aristotelis quod in fine
sui libri scribit in methauris – ‘Sciant artifices species se transmutare
non posse’ - nisi hoc predicto modo per pura artificialia
intelligatur.”
434
ogy (e.g., sculpting, painting, and carpentry) and
applied science (e.g., medicine, agriculture, and
alchemy).
The difference between these two categories hinges on the second argument of the Sciant artifices, where Avicenna, remarking that the differences between metals are not known, asks: “When the [specific] difference is not known, how will it be possible to know whether it is taken away or not or even how it could be taken away? Removal of the accidents within, however, such as taste, color, and weight, or at least their lessening, is not impossible, for reason is not opposed to this.”
[35] Avicenna’s argument relies on the impossibility of the artificer’s manipulating that which he cannot recognize, namely, the hidden essential differences that make one metal different from another. The theoretical part of Paul of Taranto’s Theorica et practica, therefore, is precisely an attempt to become acquainted with these essential principles of the different metals. These are perceived by means of tests performed in the laboratory or foundry. We know, for example, that metals contain sulfur for the following reason: when metallic ores are “calcined” - oxidized by intense heating - they give off a sulfurous, stinking smoke. [36] Some metals, however, contain more sulfur than others. Lead, for example, contains more sulfur than tin and of a more entrenched sort. Paul determines this from the fact that two calcinations of lead leave a yellow, sulfurous calx, while two such firings of tin leave a white calx, although the metal’s smoke is still yellow. [37]The presence of mercury in the metals is proved by
similar means. Mercury readily
forms an amalgam with gold, silver, copper, tin, or lead, simply by remaining in
intimate contact with any of the said metals. The medieval writers even claimed to be
able to amalgamate mercury with iron, though this claim was probably the result
of observational error on their part. As Paul says, this striking affinity
between quicksilver and the then-known metals “is due to a similarity of
substance.” [38] But he later describes a procedure by which mercury
subjected to
35. Avicenna, De congelatione, ed. Newman (cit. n.
14), pp. 61—62: [HHC: Latin not reproduced.]
36. Paul of Taranto, Theorica et practica (cit. n.
33), fol. 8r, 11. 20-24: [HHC: Latin not reproduced.] 37. Ibid.,
of lead, fol. 25r, 11. 24-30: [HHC: Latin not reproduced.] In
quotations from the original language (notes and Appendix), editorial deletions
are in square brackets and editorial interpola sections in angle brackets. (In
the translations interpolations are in square brackets.)
38. Ibid., fol. 7v, 1. 32 - fol. 8r, 1. 8:
[HHC: Latin not reproduced.]
435
the vapor of molten silver or lead is congealed per se
“without the admixture of any other.” [39] From the modern point of view, the product of this
experiment would again be an amalgam. To the alchemist, however, it appeared
that the hot, arid vapor of lead served to “dry out” the excess humidity of the
mercury, thus allowing it to become a full-blown metal. Hence Paul says that this procedure, by
which mercury is “independently” converted from a “spirit” to a metal, shows
better than any other demonstration that the “subtlety [of the substance] of the
metals” comes from mercury.
Paul supports these experimental demonstrations of the metals’ components by an attempt to explain the nature of the metallic principles, sulfur and mercury, in terms of the four primary qualities, hot, cold, wet, and dry. Without going into details, I will point out the thrust of his argument. By arriving at the composition of the two metallic principles in terms of the four qualities, then showing how the two principles can be manipulated to form the six known metals, Paul manages to satisfy Avicenna’s objection that the alchemist cannot manipulate that which he does not recognize. Using experimental demonstrations such as those described above and the philosophical framework provided by Aristotle’s De gencratione et corruptione and Meteorologica, Paul responds that properly educated alchemists really can recognize and manipulate the primary qualities directly. This ability to recognize qualities is precisely what distinguishes alchemists and physicians on the one hand from carpenters and painters on the other. The latter do not attempt to understand the nature of their material at its most fundamental level. They are technically skilled, but their work operates only on the level of appearance, not fundamental change. In other words they are scientifically uninformed artisans - pure technicians - whom Paul is careful to distinguish from those who derive their skill from a direct knowledge of the four Aristotelian qualities. I can think of no better term for the latter than applied scientist, a category already employed in this sense by Lynn Thorndike. [
40In effect, therefore, Paul has made a distinction
between the applied scientist, who understands and employs the true causes of
things, and the simple artisan, who works to produce an effect without true
knowledge of its causes. As
Avicenna said in the De congelatione, such an artisan cannot change
species, for if the specific difference - the cause of the species - is not
known, “how will it be possible to know whether it is taken away or not, or how
it could be taken away?” [41]
The applied scientist, according to Paul,
does understand the causes of species and can therefore change
them.
Of the three Scholastics examined earlier, only Roger
Bacon matches the pre-
39. Ibid., fol. 20v, 11. 12-17: [HHC: Latin
not reproduced.]
40. See the term applied science in Lynn
Thorndike, History of Magic and Experimental Science, 8 vols. (New York:
Columbia Univ. Press, 1923-1958), passim; e.g., in Vol. I, Ch. 5, of the
ancient mechanical engineering of Vitruvius and Hero of Alexandria; in Vol. II,
p. 81, of pseudo-Farabi’s scientia de naturis; and in Vol. II, p. 663, of
Roger Bacon’s Epistola de secretis operibus. Attempts like those made in these
works to apply philosophical or scientific principles for technological ends
must be distinguished from nonscientifically oriented craft traditions in which
no attempt to utilize scientific first principles is made.
41. Avicenna, De congelatione, ed. Newman (cit. n.
14), p. 61: [HHC: Latin not reproduced.]
436
mium put on technology, or rather applied science, by Paul of Taranto. It is possible, however, that the very success of such arguments as Paul’s and Roger’s led to the condemnation of their views. In the Theorica et practica Paul goes to the limit by insisting that “anything short of the animated and the soul itself can be made naturally from anything else with regard to elementary form… such as bodies composed of the four elements, as for example stones and metals.” [42] In other words, the powers of art are limited only by the human inability to make and infuse another soul. Roger Bacon, in a similar fit of hubris, goes so far as to say that alchemical gold, because it contains the four elements in an even better proportion than natural gold, can restore the human body to a condition of elemental equality like that of Adam and Eve and the resurrected at the end of time. Roger’s enthusiastic views may have contributed to his apparent imprisonment during the last fifteen years of his life.
[43]
ANTI-ALCHEMICAL SENTIMENT IN THE
LATE THIRTEENTH CENTURY AND THE RESULT OF THE DEBATE
What then was the opposite camp doing, while Paul and Roger were concocting their alchemical manifestos? The first direct counterattack by a Latin author that I have been able to locate is contained in a work by the Thomist Giles of Rome (Aegidius Romanus), written between 1286 and 1291
. [44] Before turning to Giles, however, it will be useful to summarize briefly the views of his teacher, Thomas Aquinas.Determining Thomas’s opinions on alchemy is not as straightforward a task as one might hope, since his genuine works were sometimes completed posthumously by others. This appears to have been the case with his commentary on the Meteorologica of Aristotle: the portions of the text that give a positive portrayal of alchemical transmutation were actually written by another author. The Summa theologiae, finished or broken off in 1272, refers several times to alchemy, but only in passing. [45] Fortunately, Thomas’s commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, probably written between 1252 and 1256, contains a revealing treatment of demonology in which alchemy - though not the main topic - is discussed.
[46]When commenting on Book 2 of the Sentences Thomas
asks “whether demons can induce a true corporeal effect into corporeal
matter.” He then lists five
authoritative opinions that deny the possibility of such demonic power. The last of
42. Paul of Taranto, Theorica etpractica (cit. n.
33), fol. 6v, 11. 18—20: [HHC: Latin not
reproduced.]
43. Roger
Bacon, In libro sex scientiarum…, in Opera hactenus inedita, Vol.
IX, ed. A. G. Little and E. Withington (1928), pp. 183-184. See also Thorndike’s comments in
History of Magic and Experimental Science (cit. n. 40), Vol. II, pp. 628
-629.
44. Aegidius Romanus, Quodlibeta revisa, correcta, et
vane illustrato, studio M. F. Petri Damasi de Coninck (Louvain, 1646), pp.
147-149 (= Quaestio 3, Quodlibeti 8, Membri
3).
45. Aquinas, In meteorologicorum continuatio,
in Opera (cit. n. 11), Vol. VII, p. 627, cols. 1 and 2; and Aquinas,
Summa theologiae, ibid., Vol. II, p. 623, cols. 2, 3; p. 873, cols. 1, 2.
See also Francesco Migliorino,
“Alchimia lecita c illecita nel Trecento: Oldrado da Ponte,” Quaderni
Medievali, 1981, 11(June):33.
46. Thomas Aquinas, In quatuor libros
sententiarum, in Aquinas, Opera, Vol. I, p. 145, cols. 1-3. On the probable date of composition see
William 0. Wallace and James Weisheipl, “Thomas Aquinas,” in The New Catholic
Encyclopedia, Vol. XIV, p. 104.
437
these is the Sciant artifices: “Demons cannot work except through the method of art. But art cannot give a substantial form, whence it is said in the chapter on minerals that the authors of alchemy should know that species cannot be transformed. Therefore neither can demons induce substantial forms.”
[47Thomas next defines legitimate art as a procedure that
merely joins passive natural products to active natural powers in order to
produce a required effect. A good
example, Thomas says, is the lighting of a fire. The artisan conjoins the form of fire
(the natural agent) and the wood (the passive material) in order to draw forth
the effect of fire. Demons act in
the same way: they “cannot produce new effects by creation,” like God himself;
they can only apply natural agents to natural patients. When demons appear to raise the dead or
perform other supernatural acts, they are acting by means of illusion only; the
effects of such illusion are false and ephemeral.
Thomas returns to alchemy at the end of this
distinction, in order to buttress his earlier comments.
Art by its own power cannot confer a substantial form, but it can do this by means of a natural agent, as is clear in the following [hoc], that the form of fire is produced in logs through art. There are some substantial forms, however, which art cannot induce by any means, since it cannot find the proper active and passive subjects. Even in these art can produce a similitude, as when alchemists produce something similar to gold as to exterior accidents. But it is still not true gold, since the substantial form of gold is not [induced] by the heat of fire - which alchemists use - but by the heat of the sun in a determinate place where the mineral power flourishes. Hence such [alchemical] gold does not operate according to the species [of real gold], and the same is true for the other things that they [alchemists] make. [
48]Thus it is impossible for the alchemist to join the form
of a precious metal to the substance of a base one in the way that the form of
fire is joined to wood, because this must be done deep within the earth, where
the mineral power or virtus is subjected to a special strengthening.
For the same reason, Thomas adds,
“the other things that they [alchemists] make” must also be deficient when
compared with their naturally occurring counterparts. Thomas therefore rejects not only the
alchemical creation of metals but the artificial synthesis of any chemical
product. Such “alchemical”
substances as ammonium chloride produced by the destructive decomposition of
hair, or copper acetate made with vinegar left in a copper flask, are implicitly
rejected as “fake” because they were not generated in the bowels of the earth,
“where the mineral power flourishes.” A form of this
47. Aquinas, In quatuor libros sententiarum, p.
145, col. 1: : [HHC: Latin not reproduced.] The text used by Busa
contains a manifest error: numeris should be corrected to
mineris.
48. Ibid: [HHC: Latin not
reproduced.]
438
argument had already been rebutted by the Book of Hermes, where the pseudonymous author relied on the empirical testing of artificial reagents to confirm their equivalence to the natural forms. Furthermore, the Book of Hermes used the artificial incubation of chicks to disprove directly the necessity of a special virtus loci (a power linked to a certain place)
. [49]In the work of Giles of Rome these rather incidental comments of Thomas are fleshed out to become a full-fledged attack on alchemy. Like Thomas, Giles relies on the Sciant artifices and the argument that the generation of metals requires a specific virtus loci, a mineralizing power found only deep within the earth. Similarly, Giles, like Thomas, does not consider alchemy in the context of natural philosophy - although he too wrote commentaries on De generatione et corruptione and the Meteorologica - but in his Quodlibeta, a treatise concerned primarily with theology. Furthermore, the question “whether man can make gold” belongs to the subsection of the Quodlibeta devoted to the subject of man, and here man is being treated “in relation to his art,” not “in relation to nature.” [50]
Giles’s quaestio actually contains two questions: first, “whether man can make true gold by art,” and second, “given that he can make gold, whether it be permissible to sell such gold.” Relying on the Sciant artifices, Giles paraphrases Avicenna’s argument that nature is better than art, saying that art is only a principle of artificial things, whereas gold is not artificial but natural. [
51]Then Giles introduces the argument of the virtus
loci. Admitting that some
creatures, such as the bees generated spontaneously from dead cattle, do not
need a specific place of generation but only a “material principle” (putrefying
matter), he argues that other things, such as wine made from grapes, need both
this material principle and a specific place of generation, for wine is produced
only “in the depth of the grape” (in ventre vitis). Similarly, Giles says, “it is also
believable” that metals must be generated deep within the
earth.
The second question, “given that man can make gold,
whether it is permissible to sell such gold,” Giles refuses to entertain
seriously, since he is unequivocally convinced that artificial gold cannot be
made. At this point he reveals the
true nature of his argument, saying that even if gold that would withstand the
assayer’s test of cupellation could be made, it would still not be legal tender,
since it would not have all the medical properties of natural gold. [52] It follows that such a product would not be real gold,
despite the assayer’s judgment. No
doubt Giles would have said the same even if such artificial gold had the same
specific weight as natural gold, for to him, mineral gold and artificial gold
can never be the same, regardless of their properties. Like Avicenna, Giles has adopted the
immutable principle that artificial products can never be the same as their
natural models.
The last three decades of the thirteenth century
witnessed an increasingly hostile attitude by religious authorities toward
alchemy that culminated eventually in the denunciation Contra alchymistas,
written by the well-known inquisitor Nicholas Eymeric in 1396. Giles’s attack was preceded, for example,
by a number
49. Liber Hermetis (cit. n. 18), p. 66: “Loci
oppositio cassatur quia sicut cx ovo in ventre animalis nascitur, sic etsi sub
mamilla vel in fumario ponitur, animalis nascetur.”
50. Aegidius Romanus, Quodlibeta (cit. n. 44), p.
147.
51. Ibid.
52. Ibid., p. 149.
439
of interdictions issued by the religious orders; the Dominicans alone propounded condemnations of alchemy in 1272, 1287, 1289, and 1323. The movement to prohibit alchemy was given papal authority in 1317, when John XXII issued his well-known bull “Spondent quas non exhibent,” - after he had held a public disputation between alchemists and their detractors, according to Eymeric. This papal document is directed specifically against alchemists who employ their artificial gold for counterfeiting; it was motivated by purely fiscal reasons, for the debasement of coin by counterfeiters, alchemical or otherwise, presented a serious problem to the medieval commonwealth. It thus contains little theoretical justification. Nonetheless, the bull does say that the alchemists feign “that which is not in the nature of things,” indicating that John did not believe alchemical transmutation to be physically possible
. [53]What was the reason for this great backlash against
alchemy that seems to have begun around the time Paul of Taranto was writing his
Theorica et practica? We
have already suggested that the alchemical proponents were themselves in part
responsible, by arrogating too much power to the claims of their art. Yet deeper causes were at work. These are evident even in a well-known
consilium by the consistorial advocate Oldrado da Ponte, probably written
in the first decade of the fourteenth century. Oldrado’s consilium in fact
includes passages in support of alchemy. The opening contains a quotation from the
ninth- or tenth-century Canon Episcopi, a document intended to prohibit
belief in witches, who, according to certain old pagan beliefs, could assume
monstrous shapes. [54] First Oldrado quotes the part of the Canon Episcopi
he intends to refute: “[It seems] that the art of alchemy should be
prohibited, because the Canon Episcopi, question 26, 1, says that
‘whoever believes that anything created [creaturam] can be either mutated
or transferred into another species or into another similitude, except by the
creator Himself, is an infidel, and worse than a pagan.’” [55] It is peculiar that Oldrado should have
taken a document that originally had no concern with alchemy to apply directly
to that art. Is it possible that
others, seeing a similarity of language between the Canon Episcopi and
the De congelatione, had preempted him in this regard? If one inspects the passage above without
respect to its original context, it could indeed seem to be a sort of official
decree of the message propounded by the Sciant artifices. The passage explicitly states that
only God himself can transmute species, and that anyone who believes otherwise
is not a Christian.
Oldrado’s response to the Canon Episcopi is also
revealing. Instead of replying that
this edict has nothing to do with alchemy, he answers in the following manner:
“[Alchemists] do not say that one species is mutated into another (as is imputed
to them), because this is not possible. But they say that one species of metal
(such as gold) can be produced from another species of metal (such as tin).” [56] Oldrado’s rebuttal does not maintain that specific
transmutation is possi-
53. Halleux, Textes aichimiques (cit. n. 8), pp.
124, 126-127, 126 n. 30; C. Narbey, “Le moine Roger Bacon, et le mouvement
scientifique au XIIIe siècle,” Revue des Questions Historiques, 1884,
35: 157; and Migliorino, “Alchimia” (cit. n. 45), p. 16, n. 32 (on
Eymeric).
54. Norman Cohn, Europe’s Inner Demons: An Enquiry
Inspired by the Great Witch Hunt (London: Chatto, Heinemann, for Sussex
Univ. Press, 1975), pp. 210-211.
55. Oldrado da Ponte, Consilium 74, de sortilegia,
num. I, in Fanianus, De iure artis alchemiae (cit. n. 3), p.
211.
56. Ibid.
440
ble; he points out instead that the species of the metal is not transmuted, but only the metal itself. The origin of this strange-sounding claim was probably a late thirteenth-century alchemical work ascribed spuriously to Roger Bacon, the Breve breviarium. It is quite likely that the author of the Breve breviarium originated this defense himself, as it seems to be developed at greater length here than in any other medieval alchemical text. By claiming that the species of the metals are not transmuted, but only the metals themselves, the Breve breviarium means that the group of characteristics that make silver silver (its argenteity) and gold gold (its aureity) do not change if an individual piece of silver is transmuted into an individual piece of gold
. [57] Gold will still be defined, for example, as a “yellow, soft, malleable, fusible, heavy, body,” and silver as a “white, soft, malleable, fusible body, of moderate weight.” Nonetheless, an individual piece of silver can be physically transmuted so that its matter will conform to the definition of gold. Hence, the physical characteristics of the individual piece of silver will have been changed to the degree that they now belong to the species of gold.Oldrado’ s consilium, although taking the same
approach as the Breve breviarium, differs from that text in its
motivation. While the Breve
breviarium’s argument seems to be directed solely against the De
congelatione, Oldrado is responding to the Canon Episcopi, which
explicitly said that only God could transmute species. Oldrado’ s response is therefore intended
to bear the onus of doctrinal correctness, whereas the Breve breviarium’s -
at least overtly - is not. We
have already seen Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome treat alchemy in a
theological context, where Thomas even mentioned alchemists in the same breath
as demons. Like Thomas and Giles,
Oldrado sees alchemy in a theological light, while the defenders of alchemy had
focused merely on its naturalistic implications. This growing tendency to theologize the
issue of alchemy, I propose, provides the main reason for the increased number
of condemnations tendered against it during the late thirteenth and fourteenth
centuries. We should not forget
that Innocent III and Gregory IX had already established the papal Inquisition
in the first half of the thirteenth century, and that by the second half that
dreaded institution was “fully organized.” [58] Oldrado’s need to answer to the Canon Episcopi
was not necessarily an anomaly: it may well have reflected the obsession
with heterodoxy that had begun with the Albigensian Crusade and eventually
resulted in the witch hunts of the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries.
Despite the efforts of Giles, John XXII, and later
Nicholas Eymeric, Latin alchemy could not be wiped out by proclamation or other
official means. The
57. Pseudo-Roger Bacon, Breve breviarium, in
Sanioris medicinae magistri D. Rogeri Baconis Angli de arte chymiae scripta
(Frankfurt, 1603), pp. 123-126, on pp. 125-126: [HHC: Latin not
reproduced.] The text of the Breve breviarium exists in fragmentary form
in a manuscript that, according to oral communication from M.-Th. d’Alverny,
derives from the late 13th century (MS Paris, BN, Lat. 6514, fols. 126-129).
The inauthenticity of the
ascription seems assured by the text’s dependence on Albertus Magnus’s De
mineralibus for the theory that sulfur and other reagents contain a
three-fold humidity (pp. 110, 165, etc.). For a description of this theory, and
Albert’s source, see Newman, “The Summa perfectionis” (cit. n. 14), Vol.
III, pp. vii-xi.
58. Cohn, Europe’s Demons (cit. n. 54), p.
24.
441
vision of human power in the realm of technology raised by the Book of Hermes, Roger Bacon, and Paul of Taranto was too seductive to be repressed for long. The role of Hermetic literature in the message of such propagandists for the “dignity of man” as Pico della Mirandola is now well documented. Alchemy’s place in shaping the reformatory vision of Paracelsus (d. 1541) cannot be overstated. The same may be said for the “archimage” of the sixteenth century, Cornelius Agrippa von Nettesheim, while the technological apologist John Dee, whose Mathematicall Preface of 1570 demonstrated the practical application of Euclid’s Elements, was heavily indebted to the corpus of Roger Bacon, including a number of spuriously attributed alchemical works. [
5959. Frances Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic
Tradition (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1964); Walter Pagel,
Paracelsus: An Introduction to Philosophical Medicine in the Era of the
Renaissance (Basel: Karger, 1958); William Newman, “Thomas Vaughan as an
Interpreter of Agrippa von Nctteshcim,” Ambix, 1982, 29:125—140; Nicholas
Clulee, “John Dee’s Mathematics and the Grading of Compound Qualities,”
Ambix, 1971, 18:178—211; and Clulcc, “Astrology, Magic, and Optics:
Facets of John Dee’s Early Natural Philosophy,” Renaissance Quarterly,
1977, 30:632-680. Both articles
by Clulee give ample witness to the heavy influence of Roger Bacon. Dee also owned a [number of important alchemical manuscripts, such as
Oxford, BL, Digby 119, and Glasgow, Hunterian 253. Of the manuscripts listed in Dorothea
Walcy Singer, Catalogue of Latin and Alchemical Manuscripts in Great Britain
and Ireland (Brussels: Maurice Lamertin, 1928), at least one contains works
ascribed to Bacon with notes by Dee: London, BM, Sloane 2327, fols. 30r-v and
36r-38r.]
HHC: [bracketed] displayed
on page 427 of original.
APPENDIX: TEXT OF PAUL OF
TARANTO’S DISCUSSION OF THE TYPES OF HUMAN TECHNOLOGY
[HHC: Latin not reproduced.]
442
My purpose in this essay has not been to prove the
continued influence of alchemy on the development of applied science and
technology throughout the Scientific Revolution, but merely to show that here,
in these obscure treatises of the thirteenth century, a propagandistic
literature of technological development was born. During this innovative period, alchemical
writers and their allies produced a literary corpus that was among the earliest
in Latin to promote actively the doctrine that art can equal or outdo the
products of nature, even if human art is learned by imitating natural processes.
Similarly, these alchemical
propagandists - or at least the bolder among them - did not shy away from the
conclusion that man can even change the order of the natural world by altering
the species of those products. This
technological dream, however premature, was to have a lasting effect on the
direction taken by Western culture.
APPENDIX:
TRANSLATION
Which natural things are called
the matter of intellect
or art, and which are called the
instruments of art
Therefore, since natural things are appropriated by art
so that new forms be impressed in them through artifice, the natural things that
are transmuted and receive the forms are themselves called the matter of
intellect or art. But the entities
by whose mediation or action these forms are impressed into that which receives
them are called the instruments of art. Yet the work of art is restricted to a
form of double genus as follows: sometimes [it is restricted] to an accidental,
extrinsic form, as in the art of painting, sculpting, house building, and the
like, and this form is properly called a “form of art”; and sometimes the work
of art is restricted to a substantial, intrinsic form, as in agriculture and
medicine, and this form is called a “form of nature.” But this distinction arises from the
different way of taking nature as instrument, for since an instrument is of the
genus of “active things,” but an active thing with regard to nature is some
virtue of it [i.e. nature], it is necessary that nature be said to be taken
through some virtue of itself, since it is the instrument of operation under
art. And since the virtue of nature
that is to be taken [2v] can exist in two manners, it therefore happens on
account of it [the virtue] that the form of the other subjected nature [i.e.,
nature as matter] exists in the two said manners. For every virtue in nature is
a certain quality. But certain
natural qualities - which are the natural differences in the four first simple
bodies, namely, the elements - are called “primary.�� And these forms are those four principle
qualities [sufficing] for all the works of nature, namely, hot, cold, dry, and
wet, which are in the second species of quality, which is called “natural
capacity.” [a] The
other natural qualities are called secondary qualities, namely,
those
a. The second “species of quality” (potencia
naturalis) belongs to a fourfold division of qualities that is derived
ultimately from Aristotle, Categories 8b26-10a16.
443
[HHC: Latin not reproduced.]
444
caused by the first, such as white, black, sweet,
bitter, hard, soft, sharp, dull, which are in the third and fourth species of
quality, through their ability to produce an affection, [b] and through
[their having] figure [and shape]. [c] Therefore, when art takes as instrument a
virtue of nature that is of the genus of secondary qualities, such as color is
held [to be] in pictures, or the figure of an angle, or the hardness of a knife,
or pickax, in sculptures and carvings or the like, then it is necessary that an
accidental form is extrinsically induced. The reason is as follows: art and
artificer [in this case] are extrinsically related to the passive thing, nature,
on which they act. But the foresaid
secondary qualities do not of themselves properly act on any nature except
accidentally, for of themselves they properly act on sense alone, through their
own species, according to the spiritual and intentional being that they have,
and not according to their natural being, except accidentally. For color moves the sight according to
the intentional being that it has in the perspicuum, [d] and not
according to the natural being that it has in the matter of nature; and flavor
qua flavor moves the sense and not nature of itself, from a similar cause, nor
does flavor nourish, but food and drink, namely, some substance that [3r] has
flavor. Whence flavor does not act
on nature except through something else - namely, hot, cold, dry, and wet -
which are in the flavorful thing. And none of the secondary qualities can
act on the nature and essence of anything else, except through the primary
qualities. Therefore, since art and
artificer are [in this case] external to the passive things and the nature that
is taken as instrument is not of itself transmutative of substance, nor are
these accidents [transmutative] per se but per accidens, art will
only be able to lead its work as far as an external accidental form. But when art takes as an instrument the
virtue of nature which is of the said first qualities, the work must extend as
far as substance or substantial things, since hot, cold, dry, and wet are as it
were the hands of nature and her principal virtues, through which nature
transmutes and makes all things that come into being. Art, then, properly acts only by moving,
directing, aiding, and ruling, but not by making. But nature herself behaves by moving,
making, [and] causing, about which Aristotle intimates, in De generatione et
corruptione, the distinction of the moving, whose [role] is to infuse the
form of motion, and of the making, whose [role] is to infuse the form of the
thing through the form of motion. Hence it is, therefore, that in medicine
art is limited to the form of nature that is the disposition of a complexion
within, and similarly in agriculture, as it is [in the case of] the seed and
fruit that are not had except by cultivation, as in gardens, and in graftings of
trees, and in similar agricultural matters. But since these men take up natural
agents themselves as instrument, and not only the material and passive accidents
of nature - for the agriculturist takes as instrument earth, water, air, heat,
and seeds, and the doctor likewise the virtues of drugs - therefore [3v] such
men make essential [changes] and not only accidental ones, [although] through
the virtue and operation of nature. And since nature in all things makes, and
art only administers, joins, and rules, the effect must surely be attributed to
nature rather than to art, or to nature under art.
b. I have translated per passibilem qualitatem as
“through their ability to produce an affection.” See Roy I. Deferrari et al., A Lexicon
of Thomas Aquinas (Baltimore: John D. Lucas, 1948), under “Passibilis” and
“Qualitas.”
c. “See Aristotle, Categories,
l0all-16.
d. The perspicuum is the transparent medium
postulated by Aristotle in De sensu et sensilibus (Venice, 1572), p.
8.
445