The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Brian J.
Loasby *
The organisation of
capabilities [1]
Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization
Vol. 35, 1998, 139-160
Content
2. The Co-ordination of
economic activities
3.3 Technological capabilities
The division of labour
encourages the development of differentiated knowledge, and therefore of
distinctive capabilities, which are ‘knowledge how’ rather than ‘knowledge
that’ - a distinction akin to that between technology and science. The consequent problems of co-ordination may
be handled by access or control, which suggests a choice between markets or
firms; but market relationships must be managed, and
no person can know enough to control a complex firm. ‘Managing capabilities’ is itself a
capability, and must be limited by differences between knowledge bases, which
may be acute even when capabilities are closely complementary.
Before we analyse the organisation
of capabilities, it will be helpful to consider how we wish to interpret both
terms. We shall follow the traditional
practice of most economists by including within the scope of ‘organisation’ both formal structures and the distribution
of activities among independent agents; but we shall question the traditional
assumption which underlies general equilibrium and transaction cost theories,
that the function of economic organisation is to ensure
allocative efficiency, suggesting an
* Corresponding
author.
1.
This paper originated as a presentation to the EMOT Workshop on ‘Technology and
the Theory of the Firm: Social and Economic Perspectives, at the University of
Reading, 14-16 May 1995. The present
much-changed version has benefitted from comments at
the Workshop, and also from suggestions by Joan
Cantwell and three referees.
139
alternative
emphasis on the development and use of knowledge. This will lead to the interpretation of
‘capabilities’ as a particular kind of knowledge, and to an examination of the
consequences for economic analysis of that interpretation. By combining these conceptions of ‘organisation’ and ‘capabilities’ we shall define a
(non-exclusive) theme for economic analysis and empirical research as the study
of the frameworks which both enable and constrain the processes of endogenous
development - a study of the institutions of economic evolution.
2. The Co-ordination of economic activities
The way in which a problem is defined is likely to influence the kind
of solution that is proffered. This
principle is readily illustrated by reviewing some of the ways in which
economists have defined the problem of co-ordination, which for many is the
central theme of economics. The most
ambitious theory of economic co-ordination focuses on a general equilibrium of
activities which are already co-ordinated; but the
success of theorists in proving the existence, under somewhat restrictive
conditions, of such a general equilibrium, and in extending that proof to
encompass multiple locations, time periods, and states of the world, has not
been matched by success in demonstrating how that equilibrium might be brought
about. As Frank Hahn has frequently
reminded us, at least one half of the story is missing. That in the Arrow-Debreu
model markets open once only, and close before either production or exchange -
except exchange of contracts - begins, implies that the activities by which
co-ordination is achieved must take place outside a general equilibrium; and
this suggests that the continuing failure to provide a rigorous theory of
general equilibration is inherent in the general equilibrium method. This argument, which was suggested by Hayek
(1937), has been developed by Richardson (1960),[1990].
Since the continual need to adjust
patterns of co-ordination in response to change is what justifies the
centrality of co-ordination in economic theory (Hayek, 1945, p. 523), the
absence of any satisfactory theory of co-ordination processes might reasonably
be considered a serious defect
To remedy that defect we need to consider how co-ordination processes
are organised. Hayek (1937, p. 49) identified “the Division
of Knowledge [as] the really central problem of economics as a social
science’’ and looked to markets as the most effective institutions within which
the dispersed and incomplete knowledge of a multitude of individuals could be
brought into alignment. In the same
journal and the same year, Coase (1937) noted that
each of these individuals might need to acquire specific knowledge in order to
use any particular market effectively, and argued that formal organisations could sometimes do better than markets in
coping with a sequence of disequilibria which evoked the need for similar kinds
of knowledge. Much later, Williamson recognised that dispersed and incomplete knowledge
generated important obstacles to the achievement of incentive-compatibility, and
built transaction cost economics on that recognition.
Transaction cost economics currently provides the best developed means
of analysing the institutional structures within
which co-ordination processes may occur. Its advantage
over
agency theory, which rests on the same problem-definition, is its explicit
recognition of hierarchy: firms are not simply a special kind of market. Yet in its present form transaction cost
economics has three significant limitations: two of them will be considered here,
and the third in the following section. First, as with general equilibrium theory the
analytical objective is to model patterns of activities in which the strructures which ensure efficient co-ordination are
already in place, even though the sequence of precontractual
search, contract definition, and postcontractual
monitoring suggests a process orientation. Williamson’s (1975, p. 9) early reference to organisational arrangements within which “the future is
permitted to unfold” has not led him to consider the effects of such
arrangements - or of a series of market transactions - on the knowledge of
those involved, including their knowledge of each other, and the consequent
emergence of new ideas for economising on transaction
costs, which could not have been foreseen by boundedly
rational individuals; and the significance in his work of the “fundamental transformation”
between large and small numbers as transaction-specific assets are created lies
not in the transformation process but in its intelligent anticipation. “An embedding of a transaction in an ongoing
process of exchange is required to make TCE coherent’’ (Nooteboom,
1992, p. 285).
The second limitation is that Williamson’s insistence on opportunism
as a necessary condition for the emergence of formal organisation
entails a theoretical focus on the incentive problems which may result from
incomplete and dispersed knowledge, at the expense of the logically prior
problems which arise from the imperfections of knowledge, even in a state of
universal benevolence. The point is not
simply that, as Coase (1991) correctly believed,
these problems are sufficient to explain the creation of firms; it is that
asymmetric information, which is identified as the source of incentive
problems, is itself a solution to the fundamental limitations of each
individual’s capacity for knowledge. It
is only by encouraging people to specialise in the
acquisition of distinctive knowledge that we can increase the total amount of
knowledge that is available within society. Incentive problems are a very proper topic for
analysis; but the incentive problems on which transaction cost theory currently
relies are better regarded as part of the pathology of an effective system for
generating knowledge which is the foundation of economic progress. Evolutionary economists should not ignore the
fitness of pathogens; but we should not seek to cure the disease by killing the
patient This
paper will contain only incidental comments on incentives in order to focus on
the evolution and co-ordination of knowledge.
The charter for all subsequent economics is provided by Adam Smith’s
claim that the principal cause of increasing productivity is the division of labour, both within and between trades. This increasing productivity, which includes
new products as well as better methods of production, derives less from the
specialist use of natural aptitudes, which had long been recognised,
than from the development of new aptitudes as a consequence of specialisation (Smith, 1976b, pp. 28-30); and the course
and content of this development depends on the pattern of specialisation
and the ways in which individuals interpret their particular experiences. Smith
(1976b, p. 17) not only draws
141
attention to the stimulus that
is given by the division of labour to the invention
of machinery, but notes (pp. 20-21) that such machines may be invented by three
distinct kinds of specialists: workmen who conceive of ways of mechanising their own tasks, those who have developed machine-making
as a distinctive trade, and those “whose trade it is, not to do anything, but
to observe everything; and who, upon that account, are often capable of combining
together the powers of the most distant and dissimilar objects.’’ It is natural to expect from these three
different kinds of specialists three different kinds of interpretation, and
thus three different kinds of machinery, especially as technology has increased
in power and complexity.
Menger (1871) argued that instead of Smith’s
sequence in which the division of labour stimulates
the development of knowledge we should rather think of knowledge as directing
the division of labour; and indeed the effective use
of new technology often requires a restructuring of tasks, and sometimes a
reallocation of productive activities between firms, as has been demonstrated,
for example, by Langlois and Robertson (1995). Smith and Menger are
both right, for the causal sequence may be cumulative: ideas for a novel
division of labour create the conditions for
developing new knowledge, which may inspire a further division of labour. This process
of increasing return, which both Marshall (1920) and Young (1928) identified as
the basic principle of economic development, naturally encourages the
application of a part of the increase in productivity to the creation of new
capital, which, if effectively linked to technology and an appropriate division
of labour, generates further increases in
productivity.
This approach to industrial organisation and
change takes us beyond transaction cost theory, and suggests some modification
of that theory. Few of those economists
who use transaction cost analysis in order to explain patterns of industrial organisation appreciate the implications of recognising that the need for transactions arises from specialisation: what Williamson calls “technological separability” is not a natural given but a human creation. Self-sufficiency entails no transaction costs,
since it entails no transactions; apart from an initial exchange of endowments,
there is no reason to incur transaction costs of any kind unless they
facilitate gains in productivity. It
follows that the summation of separately-computed production and transaction
costs, which Williamson has always acknowledged to be necessary, but which is
normally left as an exercise for the reader, is not enough; the choice between
transaction modes should reflect not just the relative costs of transacting,
but the relative gains in productivity and in productive knowledge which they
may be expected to make possible. Such
potential gains must always be conjectural; there can be no rational
expectations - in the strict sense of contemporary economics - about discovery.
But, because of Smith’s fundamental
principle, what we can expect is that different transaction modes are likely to
offer not only different prospects of discovery, but also prospects of
different kinds of discovery.
In their enquiries about the most efficient governance system for a
particular pattern of specialisation, embodying a
typical production function, economists too often neglect the historical
process by which increased transaction costs have been deliberately incurred to
make new patterns of specialisation viable, and
subsequently been justified by the increases in productive efficiency which
they have made possible. It is precisely
such a story of increased productivity, at some increase - often substantial -
in transaction or governance costs, that Chandler (1977, 1990) has offered us,
exemplifying Marshall’s
(1919, p. 181) observation that production and marketing are part
of a single process. All transaction
costs are knowledge costs, as is clear in Coase’s
(1937) original article, and so production, exchange, and governance are all
aspects of the growth of knowledge, the division of knowledge, and the use of
knowledge. By taking the transaction as
the unit of analysis the relationship between transaction modes and economic
development is kept out of focus; thus we should not be surprised that Chandler
(1992, p. 85) has identified this difference in the unit of analysis as a
serious limitation of transaction cost theory for his own analytical purposes.
To introduce our examination of capabilities, we turn to the third
limitation of transaction cost economics. In that theory, as in most other branches of
economics, knowledge is treated as information. We shall note, as worthy of separate treatment,
the convenient anomaly which exempts knowledge of productive possibilities from
the uncertainties which plague transactions, and which thereby helps to legitimise the independent treatment of production and transaction
costs. What is crucial to the present
analysis is that knowledge of productive possibilities is not enough; effective
performance depends not only on sensible decisions about what to do, but on the
availability of the skills that are required to do it. This is implicit in Smith’s theory of economic
progress. Before we can sensibly
consider the ways in which both the development and use of skills can be organised, we need to examine what it is that needs to be
co-ordinated.
In order to elucidate the concept of capabilities we shall make use of
Ryle’s distinction between ‘knowing that’ and ‘knowing
how.’ Ryle’s purpose
was to counter the traditional emphasis on the intellectual qualities of the
mind, and the accompanying conception of the mind as something quite different
from the bodily mechanisms which it controls; he asserted that “In ordinary
life… we are much more concerned with people’s competencies than with their
cognitive repertoires, with the operations than the truths that they learn” (Ryle, 1949, p. 28). What
people can do often matters more than what they can set down on paper. Moreover, the two are often very weakly connected.
“We learn how by practice, schooled indeed by criticism and example, but
often quite unaided by any lessons in the theory” (Ryle,
1949, p. 41), and even when we are consciously seeking to apply prescriptions
which are derived from theory “the intelligence involved in putting the
prescriptions into practice is not identical to that involved in intellectually
grasping the prescriptions’’ (Ryle, 1949, p. 49). Yet it is this practical kind of intelligence
which is crucial to the effective use of any skill which goes beyond mere
repetitive action.
The development and application of skills is not well represented by
economic models in which appropriate technologies are rationally chosen by
logical operations performed on well-defined information sets. Information sets are rarely adequate to characterise ‘knowledge how,’ which emerges from trial and
error within a system that is imperfectly
143
understood
rather than by logical deduction from a well-defined probability distribution. The modern concept of neural networks, in
which particular connections are reinforced, and others atrophy, as some
perceptions are classified together, and become more strongly linked with those
actions which are interpreted as achieving satisfactory responses, seems more
appropriate. It is worth noting that two
famous economists who took a particular interest in problems of knowledge
partly anticipated this psychological analysis. Hayek (1952) examined the problematic
relationship between the internal order which is developed within each human
brain and the external physical order which this internal order imperfectly and
sometimes misleadingly represents, and Marshall (1994, pp. 116-132) produced an
early conceptual model of a multi-level brain.
In Marshall’s, Hayek’s and modern artificial intelligence models, we
have systems by which phenomena are represented, and linkages constructed
between perceptions, actions and outcomes; but in none of these models are
there any processes available which could ensure that these representations are
correct, and that the linkages in the human brain correspond to the linkages
which actually operate in the environment. In Marshall’s model, the higher-level brain
has the capacity to represent the imagined consequences of contemplated
actions: but there is no suggestion that these expectations could be rational,
in the modern sense. Marshall’s “business
man endowed with genius” (1920, p. 406) is especially skillful in devising
experiments, but he cannot know in advance which products of his imagination
will be successful. As Smith (1980) knew,
patterns are invented and imposed on phenomena; and if cognition is an
evolutionary process, we should remember that evolutionary success requires no
more than a performance which is satisfactory in relation to rival cognitive
systems in the circumstances that have hitherto been experienced. As with scientific hypotheses, what matters is
always the next trial, and the result of that can never be guaranteed.
Ryle (1949, p. 46) reminds us that a skill is
“a disposition, but not a single-track disposition like a reflex or a habit. Its exercises are observances of rules or
canons or the application of criteria’’; and as Nelson and Winter
(1982, p. 84) observe, the effectiveness of a particular skill on a particular
occasion depends upon the particular combination of variables encountered on
that occasion. It is impossible to know
in advance what that combination will be, and whether it will lie within the
range of application of the skill. Furthermore, as Ryle
(1949, p. 59) points out, it is possible, and indeed common, to have partial knowledge
of how to do something, or knowledge of how to perform at a particular level;
but whether that level of performance will be good enough on the next occasion
depends on those - such as one’s customers - who make the judgement,
and on the alternatives which are then available to them. The establishment of Japanese-owned car plants
in the US and Britain has shown a number of component suppliers that their
capabilities were not of a satisfactory standard in the new environment. Capabilities are always conjectural.
Capabilities are the least definable kinds of productive resources. They are in large measure a by-product of past
activities, but what matters at any point of time is the range of future
activities which they make possible. What
gives this question its salience is the possibility of shaping capabilities,
and especially of configuring clusters of capabilities, in an attempt to make
some preparation for future events, which, though not predictable, may, as Lachmaim and Shackle insisted, be imagined. It is to Menger’s
(1871) credit that
he recognised,
if unemphatically, the variety of ways in which
people can accumulate reserves against an uncertain future; it is to the
discredit of the economics profession that so little attention has been given,
with some important exceptions, such as Hicks (1976), Leijonhufvud
(1973), Littlechild (1986), and above all Keynes
(1936), to the accumulation of reserves as an essential feature of economic
activity - essential because it is not at all clear how a modern economy could
function if its members were unable to draw on reserves of many different
kinds. Capabilities, each of which gives
the power to act effectively in a particular range of possible future
circumstances, are among the most important of such reserves, and the
development of such power is a major, though not always consciously intended,
function of formal education, and was included in the Ansoff
(1965) set of objectives for corporate strategy. It is hardly possible to discuss capabilities
sensibly without recognising that each bundle of
capabilities is oriented towards a range of possible futures, and that every
such orientation is a fallible conjecture. Shell use multiple
scenarios of possible futures in order to encourage their managers to consider
what orientations may be appropriate.
The immediate reason for this professional negligence among economists
is that the skills in which they are trained, and which are reinforced by the
system of formal and informal incentives to which they are subject, are
themselves oriented towards a range of possible future analyses which excludes
such problem-definitions. Within this
range models are fully specified: the information currently available to a
particular agent may be incomplete, but information sets cannot be. It can therefore never be rational to operate
inside the possibility frontier, as that can presently be specified, in order
to be able to respond quickly to threats or opportunities which cannot be
clearly identified - because what cannot be identified cannot be included in
the economist’s problem definition; strategy as a set of decision premises for
future choices, which to non-economists is an obviously sensible and useful
definition, must be replaced by a game-theoretic strategy of commitment to
conditional actions; and capabilities, which are reserves against contingencies
that are not predictable and therefore not contractible, must be replaced by
production functions.
Capabilities of the kind so far discussed are not sufficient for
business success. That depends, in
Penrose’s (1959, p. 31) phrase, on a firm’s productive opportunity, which
combines capabilities with the perception of a profitable use to which they can
be put; and as can frequently be observed, either perception or capability may
be missing. Productive opportunities,
too, are conjectures. However, although
knowledge, whether true or false, of an attractive market should be regarded as
‘knowledge that’ rather than ‘knowledge how,’ nevertheless the ability to seek
out relevant information or to draw inferences from newspaper reports,
conversations, political or social changes, or even price movements, is certainly
‘know-how’. “To know something is to be
able to understand and otherwise make sense of it” (Minlder,
1993, p. 520). ‘Knowledge that’ may be a
public good, but the capability of making sense of it, in any one of the ways
that are conceivable, is not. However,
like other capabilities, this is generally susceptible to analysis in terms of
experience and the patterns that have consciously or unconsciously been imposed
upon that experience. The alertness
which characterises each of Kirzner’s
(1973) entrepreneurs is a distinctive capability, and it is because
appropriately oriented capabilities are scarce in each local economic
environment that alertness is a source of
145
profit;
Casson’s (1982) entrepreneur is especially skilled at
interpreting the conjunction of different kinds of knowledge, which, as we have
seen, was the special trade of Smith’s ‘philosophers’.
In the most rigorous sciences, the reliability of the knowledge that
is produced depends on the skillful performance of particular operations (Ziman, 1978); and the particular operations which are
deemed to be appropriate within each science sets limits (which are not always
acknowledged by the scientists themselves) to the kinds of knowledge that can
be attained. If macroeconomic problems
are always to be studied by constructing models of rational expectations
equilibrium, the highest level of skill in such modelling
will never generate the kind of knowledge that is embedded in Keynes’ General
Theory: indeed, highly intelligent economists who practise
such skills are unable to make analytical sense of the concept of involuntary
unemployment, as Hahn and Solow (1995, p. 2) have
observed. In science as in business, we
can learn only by restricting our attention to particular skills or particular
topics; and we cannot know - though we may guess - what we might have learned
had we attended instead to other skills or other topics. (The importance of how we know
is examined in Loasby, 1998). Some constraints on learning are always
necessary; but their effects on society or an economic system can be mitigated,
partly through the effects of specialisation itself,
which fosters a diversity of constraint systems within which knowledge can be
developed - thus the distinctive advantages of economists’ and sociologists’ particular
ways of generating knowledge may offer mutual compensation for their
corresponding deficiencies - and partly by the tolerance of variety within each
specialised field. To bring these processes within the scope of
economic analysis, however, requires a substantial redefinition of the
constraints within which orthodox economists work; but, as often happens, the
redefinition of constraints reveals a productive opportunity.
Ryle’s distinction may be used to illuminate
the relationship between science and technology. The declarative content of science is ‘knowledge
that’ (remembering that what is treated as knowledge is a set of hypotheses
which have been not yet been refuted), and technology is ‘knowledge how’; so we
should not be surprised that science is rarely an adequate guide to the
development of the technology which it might seem to suggest, or even that the
technological implications of a scientific theory may not be recognised until long after the theory has become textbook
material. As Rosenberg (1994, p. 140-141)
points out, the magnitude of development costs, even when the development is
related to old science, provides an impressive indicator of this mismatch. A less public indicator is the number of
scientific problems that are first identified during the development process:
in a time of rapid technological change, technology may lead science as often
as the other way round (Rosenberg, 1994, p. 141) - not least in suggesting the
value of interdisciplinary research (Rosenberg, 1994, pp. 147-149).
We should not forget that each science has its own technology; good
research scientists know how to develop testable implications from hypotheses,
how to devise experiments which will effectively test them, and how to
interpret the results in a way which will foster the continuing process of
discovery - all within the evolving conventions of that
science.
(The implications of
such conventions for the knowledge that a science can produce are explored in Loasby, 1995.) Postgraduate training is probably of more
value in helping people to learn how to do a particular kind of science than in
transferring to them the substantive knowledge of science already done; and
Kuhn (1962, p. x) introduces his concept of paradigm as an exemplar of knowledge
how. But this knowledge how is directed
towards a different purpose from the knowledge of how to achieve technological
goals; indeed, it has effectively become what Smith called a distinct trade,
and an example of the division of labour which has
led to a remarkable development of specialised
skills.
This division of labour and skills is often
conveniently organised by a clear separation between
university and industrial science, which minimises
the operational conflict between very different concepts of what constitutes
good practice. But, like any organisational solution, and indeed any choice worth
considering, this has its opportunity costs. As a simple example, developed by Rosenberg
(1994, pp. 144-146), scientists become extremely skilfull
at achieving results in the conditions and on the scale of a laboratory, but rarely
give attention to the skills that are required to achieve equivalent results in
very different circumstances. The well-known
relationship between the volume and surface area of a reaction vessel, for
instance, means that exothermic reactions which pose no problem in a laboratory
may present formidable challenges to the design and operation of a commercial
plant; but there is no reason why most university research chemists should
develop any special skill in handling such challenges. Similarly, because the accumulated expertise
of economists in developing theories of rational choice has been directed
towards modelling various kinds of equilibria, in which no further choices are required, we
should not be surprised - though we may be embarrassed - to observe how limited
is the help that rational choice theory can give in making decisions, even to
rational choice theorists. The gap
between the knowledge of how to do research into chemistry and the knowledge of
how to develop new chemical technology has been filled by the emergence of a
whole new discipline of chemical engineering; the gap between the knowledge of
how to develop economic models of choice and the knowledge of how to make good
managerial decisions has been filled by that amorphous collection of
disciplines known as management studies, although (as we should expect) many of
its practitioners are more successfull in developing
skills in building theories for classroom exposition than skills in practical
decision making.
3.3.
Technological capabilities
If technology cannot be developed in an orderly fashion from
scientific principles, it must be heavily reliant on trial and error, an incremental
process where the crucial questions at each stage are how to interpret the
latest results and what to do next. As
with Marshall’s (1920) principle of substitution, decisions are made at the
margins of knowledge rather than by marginal analysis. This process is likely to be costly in both
time and resources, and it is possible to spend a great deal of both without
apparently making much progress, except in discovering what not to do - though,
as the Duke of Wellington observed of his experiences as a subordinate officer
in an unsuccessful campaign, “that is always something.” The effective development of technology seems
147
to
depend less on linear logic than on identifying or imposing patterns and
connections; and experience with present products and processes often provides
better guidance than scientific principles. It is also much harder to transfer between organisations: even if it can be codified, the code which
makes sense to the codifiers may not make relevant sense to the recipients of
the message. Where knowledge how is
crucial, it is rarely an attractive proposition to try to develop a collection
of novel skills rapidly, because it is likely to be extremely difficult to
interpret and guide the learning process when many interrelated procedures are
being changed simultaneously (Teece et al., 1994, p.
17); if few or none of the component skills are well established within the organisation, there are too many degrees of freedom, and
codified science usually does little to reduce them. Schumpeter’s (1934) new combinations are not
combinations of new knowledge how; knowing how to manage the combination of
existing capabilities is novelty enough.
We would therefore expect to find that the division of labour between various trades has resulted in a number of
distinctive technologies, each embedded in a group of firms, that these
technologies change rather slowly, along trajectories which are localised to particular ways of organising
knowledge, and that the productive opportunities open to any business are quite
closely restricted by the technologies which it has acquired and the markets to
which that business knows how to direct them. Rapidly-developing fields are thus likely to
be dominated by those already expert in the relevant
technologies. But because knowledge how
is not reducible to logical sequences, but depends on a multitude of evolving
connections, we would still expect to find some variety between firms in the
way that they do things and rather more in the productive opportunities that
they perceive. We would also, of course,
expect firms to make mistakes, and the biggest mistakes would be expected when
they move into fields to which their technology is not applicable - especially
if they do not realise its inapplicability.
All this is what Patel and Pavitt (1995,
1997) did find in their investigation into technological competences in the
world’s largest firms. From an analysis
of the U.S. patenting record of more than 400 of the world’s most
technologically active firms, they conclude that large firms typically develop
skills in a cluster of technologies which is closely related to each firm’s
product range, that the set of technologies included in each firm’s cluster
changes only slowly, but that the specific emphasis within a cluster, and the
range of products to which it is applied, may differ between firms: because
each productive opportunity is a distinctive combination of technology and
vision there is some variety in patterns of diversification. (For a detailed study of
such variety, see Fransman, 1995.) The development of each firm’s capabilities is
path-dependent, but there is, in general, more than one path available from any
particular configuration.
In order to analyse the organisation
of capabilities it is necessary to avoid the top-down perspective of the
conventionally-defined allocation problem - what is to be produced, how, by
whom, and for whom - and to consider co-ordination from the point of view of
the individual, as Adam Smith did. Since
the productivity-enhancing division of labour, our
wants are provided through “the assistance and co-operation of many thousands”
(Smith, 1976b, p.23); but the
obverse of this beneficial interdependence is that “man has almost constant
occasion for the help of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to expect it
from their benevolence only” (Smith, 1976b, p. 26). Due to the common misinterpretation of Smith’s
analysis of society, it is worth noting that ‘benevolence’ is not irrelevant,
though Smith places much more weight on people’s sense of propriety, or the
desire to be worthy of the approval of others, which sometimes inspires help,
and more often curbs opportunism (Smith, 1976a). But benevolence and propriety together are not
enough; and the problem which Smith poses, of how an individual is to get
things done by others, focuses on individual efforts at co-ordination from
within. We need not only to know how to
do certain things for ourselves, but also how to get other things done for us; and
just as productive activities require direct capabilities, so transactions
depend on indirect capabilities.
Indirect capabilities are of two kinds: we may be able to get things
done for us either by gaining control of other
capabilities or by obtaining access to them. We shall soon discover that, like many other
apparently sharp distinctions, this highlights relatively distant points on a
continuum; nevertheless, as Ménard (1995) has argued,
the distinction is analytically invaluable, and this section is intended to
complement his work in ‘disentangling concepts.’ The obvious application of the distinction
within this paper is to the contrast between markets, which offer access, and
firms, which allow hierarchical control; and the immediate conclusion is that
control has substantial advantages, but is likely to be more costly than
access. We can access more than we can
control, and therefore should limit our attempts at control to those
capabilities which are both crucial and manageable. What might these be?
Every new example of the division of labour separates what has hitherto been joined; it therefore implies a need to provide some linkage to replace that which was previously embodied in the practitioners of this now-divided skill. Such linkages may be unnecessary, and even sometimes undesirable, if the division of labour allows the separated skills to be adapted to unrelated uses: no one would now advocate a closer integration between surgeons and barbers. But Marshall was surely right to accept the general rule, which he adopted from Herbert Spencer, that evolution tends to favour both greater specialisation and closer integration. Divided capabilities typically need to be used in clusters, or in closely-ordered sequences, if the improvements in each new sub-skill which follow this division are to be guided in compatible directions and effectively used. Formal organisations may be effective instruments for doing this, and, as Marshall saw, could provide an exosomatic equivalent to the multi-level brain which he attempted to represent by his ‘machine.’ Brains and firms are thus self-organising systems in which the development of well-honed skills releases time and energy for more complex problems, and in particular those which do not recur often enough to allow the appropriate connections to be selected and then reinforced by repeated trial and error. Both systems facilitate the development of capabilities and their reconfiguration to match a changing perception of needs; and this, it may be argued, was Coase’s ([1937] 1988, pp. 39-40) basic rationale for the firm.
149
Marshall’s multi-level model, and Babbage’s (1989, [1832]) Economy
of Manufactures, which Raifaelli (1995) argues
was a major influence on his thought, naturally led him to recognise
the potential advantages of large-scale organisations,
in which the employment of able subordinates promised the greatest opportunity
for the head of a firm “to keep his mind fresh and clear for thinking out the
most difficult and vital problems of his business; for studying the broader
movements of the markets, the yet undeveloped results of current events at home
and abroad” (Marshall, 1920, p. 284). But
Marshall also recognised that this opportunity might
not be taken: the energy and enterprise on which the founder of the business
drew to build it up is likely to decline as he grows older, and his successors
may have less of either. In addition, a
large business depends on initiative at many levels, for any capability may be
improved, modified, and applied in new ways; and by freeing himself from
detail, the head of the business necessarily deprives himself of much of the
specific knowledge which is needed to perceive what might be done and to see
that it is. Conventional principal-agent
models offer limited help in co-ordinating the growth
of knowledge, as Minkler (1993) has explained:
incentives certainly matter, but the problem to which they should be addressed
is not how to induce the agent to take that action which the agent already knows
will best serve the objectives of the principal, but how to encourage the agent
to recognise unspecified contingencies and to imagine
new actions. Agents may prefer the
security and ease of the familiar; and formal control systems tend to
discourage initiative, and therefore may destroy rather than develop
capabilities. It was because he saw the organisation of industry as the organisation
of a discovery process (including, we should not forget, that kind of discovery
process that we call the formation of character) that Marshall was less than
enthusiastic about large firms.
In firms of any size, organisation shapes
and constrains the growth of capabilities: in Penrose’s (1959, p. 149)
definition, a firm is “a pool of resources the utilisation
of which is organised in an administrative
framework.” The framework specifies what
people are expected to notice and what to ignore, the range of activities which
they are expected to perform and the criteria by which their performance will
be judged. That is why organisational design is important. But it is not only formal organisation
which matters. Informal organisation may reinforce, counteract, or complicate the
effects of formal organisation; what is certain is
that it contributes substantially to the framework within which capabilities
are developed and used. (That is
strikingly true of the economics profession, but no less strikingly false of
almost all economic analysis, in which personal connections are subject to
indictment for restraint of trade.) Indeed,
knowing how to appease the formal and informal expectations of other organisation members is an important skill for anyone who
wishes to become an effective organisation member -
as is sometimes the ability to circumvent, or even possibly subvert, these
expectations.
Partly by deliberate prescription, but primarily through the evolution of custom and practice (which, if integrated by a clear, if tacit, framework of connecting principles, merits description as a corporate culture) members of an organisation develop the indirect capabilities - the knowledge of how to get certain things done - which are necessary for them to use their own capabilities effectively. In most organisations they also eventually resign themselves to the absence of some desirable capabilities: there are some things which they find impossible to get done. That is a pathology of any strong culture. (Sometimes they leave the organisation in order to get them done: this is a common origin
of new entrepreneurial businesses.) It is this network of indirect capabilities,
much more than hierarchy and fiat, which allows a firm to co-ordinate a range
of operations at lower cost than would be entailed by market transactions. The reduction in cost may be particularly
great if intrafirm relationships foster the
development of sympathetic understanding within and between departments. People come to know who they can rely on.
If one looks within an organisation, one
finds that the detailed integration of activities depends on access rather than
control, though the underlying pattern (which may be partly illusory) of control
may be an important facilitator of access, especially for newcomers to an organisation. No
single individual, and no board of directors, can know how to do what any
sizable firm can do; nor can they even know how to get it done except in the
sense of encouraging others, by deeds as well as words, to use their own
capabilities in ways which only the individual knows are appropriate. The knowledge of how to do whatever it is that
an organisation can do is distributed among the
direct and indirect capabilities of its members, and, as Winter (1991, p. 185)
has pointed out, is accessible only through that combined membership. It cannot be planned according to conventional
notions of allocative efficiency. It is through multiple access
to a distributed network that a firm is able to solve problems of complexity
that cannot be fully understood by any single individual.
Hayek’s analysis of cognitive psychology led him to the conclusion
that “any apparatus of classification must possess a structure of a higher
degree of complexity than is possessed by the objects which it classifies”
(Hayek, 1952, p. 185); it is thus not surprising that the division of labour, by permitting the development of a complex
structure of capabilities that would be unattainable by anyone practising the undivided activities, requires processes of integration
which are beyond the conscious control of any person. The administrative structure of a firm may be
thought of as such an ‘apparatus of classification,’ which cannot therefore be
fully represented by a model in the brain of the CEO. (The CEO may nevertheless make a decisive
contribution to the success of a business, both because of the crucial decisions
which no one else can make and by influencing the development and use of the
company network.) That these
capabilities, as Ryle emphasises,
are the product of intelligent processes which differ substantially from those
normally associated with theoretical or factual knowledge, and which are
therefore often difficult to represent in a way which would make them amenable
to formal analysis, reinforces Hayek’s argument
We should not overlook the contribution of decomposability to the effective management of elaborate systems, which has been rightly emphasised by Simon; but it may reasonably be urged that Simon has underrated the importance of knowing how to achieve results without the conscious use even of boundedly rational procedures. Knowledge-in-use “is embedded in the social practices of a particular community” (Boehm, 1994, p. 162); a firm is one of the most important communities in which such knowledge can be embedded. It is a social institution for enhancing capabilities rather than reducing transaction costs; indeed its effectiveness in enhancing capabilities may justify an increase in transaction costs, as, we noted earlier, Chandler has demonstrated. We should, however, observe that a firm’s operation as a social institution, by encouraging both ‘moral sentiments’ and the acceptance of decision premises which
151
reflect
organisational rather than individual objectives, may
also be extremely effective in reducing the costs of intra-company transactions.
The role of the entrepreneur in developing
such social institutions is explored by Witt (1998).
Since Marshall, as Raffaelli (1995) has
shown, had his own psychological theory in mind in explaining how organisation aids the growth of knowledge, it is not
surprising that he recognised the importance of
developing appropriate relationships within a business, nor that he insisted
that this development must evolve over a long time. A nexus of contracts cannot deliver what
Marshall expected business firms to deliver; to be fair, economists who propound
contractual theories of the firm expect it to deliver very little of what
Marshall thought was important.
Both direct and indirect capabilities develop through specialisation. Indirect capabilities reduce the costs of
particular transactions - which, let us recall, are costs of imperfect knowledge
- by embodying knowledge of particular circumstances and particular
relationships; their evolution is guided by individual intelligence and the
selection processes of a particular knowledge community. Governance is a particular category of ‘knowledge
how,’ and most effectively developed within a limited range; and a firm is a specialised system, with direct and indirect capabilities
which have been derived from a particular pattern of experience and which are
oriented towards a particular, if ill-defined, set of possibilities. Coase ([1937] 1988,
p. 45) noted that the costs of governance “will increase with an increase .in
the dissimilarity of transactions,” and devoted two paragraphs of his paper (Coase, 1972) to the proposition that “the costs of
organizing an activity within any given firm depend on what other activities
the firm is engaged in,” concluding that firms will differ in the range of
their activities (Coase, [1972] 1988, pp. 63-64). He goes on to observe that analyses of the
optimum size of firm and of economies of scale do not address this issue; we
may now add that the contribution of transaction cost theory is restricted by
its focus on the make-or-buy decision which is a consequence of defining the
problem in terms of the compatibility of incentives, and ignoring the
compatibility of skills.
It is therefore clearly not sensible to attempt to manage an economy
as one enormous firm; it is not even sensible to extend a firm into areas of
activity that require capabilities which are significantly different from those
already developed, and so it is not surprising that firms so often develop a
product portfolio which depends on a range of related skills (Teece et al., 1994). However, this principle (an example of ‘knowledge
that’) is not always easy to put into practice; that requires the skill (or ‘knowledge
how’) to recognise what differences are significant -
and perhaps the vision to recognise what apparently
significant differences might be made compatible. But because capabilities are developed through
practice their limits are rarely investigated, except by accident; and
capabilities are always conjectural. There
have been many examples of companies expanding, by takeover or internal growth,
into areas to which they believed their capabilities were readily applicable,
only to find that they were wrong. Some
of the most spectacular instances have been provided by financial institutions,
whose specialist skills in appraising investment projects proved to be
inapplicable to many of the projects which they initiated themselves.
Though some of these failures are more reprehensible than others, we should recognise that a substantial degree of trial and error is unavoidable, and if the economy is to be
regarded
as a selection environment for firms we should also consider each firm as a
selection environment in which various combinations of capabilities are tested.
Research departments are primarily
selection environments in which most of the effort is devoted to falsifying
hypotheses about the profitability of conjectured new products or processes, in
order to avoid the costs of falsification by the market. The selection environment within each firm is
the product of its own evolved capabilities; what new combinations can be
effectively managed depends on the particular skills of management that have
already been developed. Every extension
of indirect capabilities facilitates further extensions of a similar kind
(where similarity is effectively defined by the firm’s own evolution); it also
impedes extensions of a dissimilar kind (where dissimilarity is likewise
defined). The obverse of capability is
incapability; indeed it is easy to understand why Patel and Pavitt
(1995, p. 27) claim that given a profile of a firm’s technological
competencies, “we shall probably be able to predict what it does not make.’’
Firms within a relatively homogenous
technological, market, and social environment will resemble each other in many
ways, but not in all: their productive opportunities, and thus their range of
products, will still be differentiated, though much less so than in firms from
diverse technological, market, or social environments.
Dissimilar clusters of capabilities are therefore linked by markets. However, in order to understand these
linkages, we need to go well beyond the formal conception of a market as a set
of supply and demand correspondences. If
we consider markets from the perspective of those who use them, both
individuals and firms, we can see that they provide access to capabilities
which have been developed by other people and other firms. Without such access, as Smith realised, and the consequent ability to command other
people’s labour, specialisation
is dangerous. (It is thus easy to see
why Smith was attracted by the possibility of a ‘labour-commanded’
theory of value.) Since microeconomists typically think implicitly of a vertically
integrated firm selling directly to a consumer, they equally typically fail to recognise that firms require access to capabilities also,
and not only in labour markets. All firms depend on the capabilities of their
suppliers, and every firm which is not a retailer depends on the capabilities
of those who provide its links to the final consumer. If we conceptualise
markets as a means of providing access to capabilities, we shall recognise that the provision of access is a capability too;
and markets differ in the scope and quality of the capabilities to which they
give access. There are transaction costs
of using markets, but a developed market is a means of reducing the costs of
individual transactions. But how, and by
whom, are markets developed?
Hayek (1948, p. 97) pertinently observed that “the function of competition is here precisely to teach us who will serve us well: which grocer or travel agency, which department store or hotel, which doctor or solicitor, we can expect to provide the most satisfactory solution for whatever particular personal problem we may have to face.” Hayek correctly identified the issue as that of discovering how to gain access to relevant capabilities which are controlled by other people, and implicitly showed how the competitive process serves to reduce the transaction costs faced by the buyer; but his
153
examples
deflect our attention from the producers’ interests in discovering who will
serve them well, and also in discovering who are likely to be good customers
for what they have to sell. Marshall
(1919, p. 274) recognised that all those who wished
to make use of markets, whether as buyers or sellers, would benefit from the
development of market institutions which would reduce the costs of individual
transactions, but also that the incentive to bear the costs of developing such
institutions would be strongest for those who expected to make the greatest use
of markets: merchants and (especially) manufacturers. Casson explored the
obstacles to trade which face anyone trying to develop a new business; and his
discussion of the methods of reducing or removing these obstacles led him to
conclude that “the set-up cost of a market organisation
is likely to be quite high compared with its recurrent costs” (Casson, 1982, p. 179). It is often possible to reduce substantially
the cost of individual transactions, and thus enhance the indirect capabilities
which are provided by a particular market, through appropriate investment.
Marshall was uniquely aware of this, and pointed to the need for every
firm to build up what he revealingly called its external organisation
(Marshall, 1920, p. 458). This external organisation was more than a means of developing a special
market, within which a firm might expect to be able to sell more easily -
though rarely at a lower price - to those who could reduce their own
transaction costs by becoming its customers; it was also a means of acquiring
knowledge on which to base “experiments… to see whether some new method, or
combination of methods, will be more efficient than the old” (Marshall, 1920,
p. 406), or to create “new wants by showing people something which they had
never thought of having before” (Marshall, 1920, p. 280). This knowledge cannot be attained by anonymous
contracting, which economists have extolled as the means to efficiency; it
requires the development of continuing relationships, in which voice is
preferred to exit. Even if the
supplier’s knowledge is effectively packaged in the good or service which is
supplied, so that the user does not need to know how its effects are produced -
as is true of many consumer products - the user still needs to know enough
about the supplier to support a judgement that the
desired effects will indeed be produced; reputations are important, and can
only be established at some cost and over sometime. Thus even in the case which comes closest to
the standard model of exchange, suppliers need to make irreversible investments
(and thus cannot afford to sell at marginal cost, as Marshall well knew and as Casson (1982) makes clear in his analysis of the
market-making entrepreneur). To acquire
the knowledge with which to make improvements, greater investment is required;
but it is not sensible to economise on transaction
costs if that means forgoing benefits which exceed those costs.
Markets allow firms to gain access to other firms’ capabilities, but
only if they are prepared to make appropriate investments, and to develop their
external as well as their internal organisation. We should therefore extend Winter’s
observation to say that the knowledge required to make and sell any firm’s products
resides in the structure of direct and indirect capabilities within that firm,
supplemented by the structure of indirect capabilities that connect it with
other firms. There are notable
differences of practice in the extent to which firms seek to develop and use
such indirect capabilities.
One of the most significant of Patel and Pavitt’s (1995) findings is the magnitude of the commitment of the world’s largest firms to the continuous development of their capabilities in technologies which lie outside the distinctive core of their business. This
may be explained by a
combination of three factors: first, parts of these background technologies are
so closely complementary that they need to be actively managed within the
business - they are indeed core, though not distinctive; second, the boundary
of each firm’s core is not well-defined, and liable to change over time, and so
these background technologies provide reserves against uncertainty by enhancing
the firm’s capacity to absorb additional skills, and third, firms need to
understand technologies which they do not themselves intend to practice if they
are to make the best use of the capabilities of those firms that do practice
those technologies - in other words, they are developing indirect capabilities.
Some of Philips’ suppliers are reported
to have complained (personal communication) that Philips does not know how to
make the best use of their capabilities. This third reason, which reflects Ryle’s perception (cited earlier) that “the intelligence
involved in putting the prescriptions into practice is not identical to that
involved in intellectually grasping the prescriptions,” illuminates one aspect
of the ‘second face’ of research and development to which Cohen and Levinthal (1989) have drawn attention: the capability of
making productive sense of other firms’ technologies.
We shall observe another aspect of this second face if we follow
Marshall in extending this network further to include connections with firms
who are business rivals, but who, for that very reason, are also potentially
valuable sources of knowledge, because, unlike perfectly competitive firms,
they do things a little differently - but in ways that are easy to understand. Marshall was particularly impressed by the
enhancement of capabilities which he observed in his visits to industrial districts,
in which “inventions and improvements in machinery, in processes and the
general organisation of the business have their
merits promptly discussed: if one man starts up a new idea, it is taken up by
others and combined with suggestions of their own; and thus it becomes the
source of further new ideas” (Marshall, 1920, p. 271). The importance of industrial districts as
networks of capabilities has recently been emphasised
by Becattini (1990) and other Italian economists, and
Porter (1990) has offered a similar argument at a national level. (As a matter of scientific
record, acknowledgement should also be made of Klein’s (1977) anticipation of
Porter’s central theme).
From an Austrian perspective we may think of such networks as structures of complementary capitals, recalling that it is the differences between firms in the same trade that cause them to be complementary in developing the capabilities of the industry to which they belong. The two faces of R&D - the development of a firm’s own technology and the attempt to understand and learn from the technology being developed by others - reinforce this complementary structure. Complementarity in the generation of production possibilities may then be transformed into substitution in the production of goods. As in a scientific community, specialisation, competition, and communication within a framework of connecting principles constitute an effective structure for the generation of knowledge - in this case primarily of knowledge how, which cannot be learnt without doing; people need their rivals’ contributions in order to compete with them. No one person, or group of persons can control such a structure without drastically restricting the range of capabilities within it; it is the virtue of such a system that it produces results which no one had specifically intended. We should not, however, forget that even in networks the obverse of capability is incapability; the pathology of networks, especially of industrial districts, has often been exhibited.
155
If we think of markets as institutions embodying firms’ knowledge of
how to get things done and how to improve their own productive opportunities,
and as forms of organisation embodying a great deal
of investment, then we shall not feel the need for a distinctive explanation of
those interfirm relationships which involve close
co-operation. Such relationships appear
as anomalies in both market and transaction cost theory, but the anomalies
dissolve in our present perspective; the density of the network connecting one
firm to its collaborators and competitors is a matter of degree. One might perhaps be inclined to distinguish a
bartering of ‘knowledge how’ that seems to approach what sociologists call a
‘gift exchange’ from price-mediated transactions; but the careful valuation of
the exchanges of technology between ICI and Du Pont
under their Patents and Processes Agreement was an ex post reckoning that grossly understated the benefits which both
parties derived from their access to each other’s capabilities, not least in
helping to improve their own and in sustaining their confidence that critical
problems, such as the resistance of important synthetic fibres
to dyes, were soluble (Hounshell and Smith, 1988, pp.
203-205).
It may nevertheless be worth noting why one of the standard results of
transaction cost analysis, that asset-specificity entails exposure to
opportunism in a market relationship and therefore requires the internalisation of that relationship, does not necessarily
inhibit the formation of dense networks. The reason was spelt out by Richardson (1972)
even before this result became standard; it is that activities that are closely
complementary may require capabilities with very different knowledge bases,
which are therefore liable to be very difficult, as Coase
(1937) suspected, to integrate successfully within a formal organisation
- especially if those knowledge bases are difficult to analyse
or even to express; and if this is so, protection against opportunism through
vertical integration exacts an unacceptable cost in efficiency. Moreover, the protection may be illusory, for
how can one control what one does not understand?
The advantages of specialisation result from focus, as Smith well knew: knowledge develops through differentiation. The development of a specialised skill depends on a variety of experience, but a variety which can be encompassed within a network of connections. As Ryle’s discussion of ‘knowing how’ and Marshall’s and Hayek’s psychological models all make clear, these skills form patterns rather than logically-derived structures; and if they are partially codified, the codification rests on assumptions some of which are unstated because they are unrecognised. Thus, if a firm seeks to internalise a particular complementary skill which is dissimilar, not only may it be faced with management problems which it does not understand (and often, as apparently with Barings, and Sony’s purchase of Columbia, which it does not know that it does not understand) but it may find that this complementary skill, once divorced from the variety of experience within its own specialist field, ceases to develop and soon becomes a source of competitive disadvantage. Many firms encourage their suppliers to serve other customers in the belief that they will thereby learn how to become better suppliers than they could ever be by restricting their experiences to a single customer. But if we begin our analysis, not with a perfectly competitive ideal and an emphasis on fully-specified contracts but with necessarily limited direct capabilities and the consequent need to know
how to get things done by other
people, then we might recognise the possibility of
building relationships to manage closely complementary capabilities, and indeed
the substantial advantages in many circumstances of doing so.
These advantages are most obvious if we think, not of reducing
transaction costs, but of increasing net benefits, and especially of increasing
net benefits through the development of new skills, new methods, and new
products (Zajac and Olsen, 1993). Often this is best achieved through
interactive shaping by members of different organisations
with distinctive but closely complementary knowledge bases; and the advantages
may justify increased costs of governance, and even new forms of organisation, in which members of one business may
effectively work for another (as e.g. logistics specialists manage the
distribution systems of supermarket chains) while preserving the
distinctiveness on which their capabilities depend. The increased costs may result less from the
need to safeguard against opportunism, which may be attenuated by the
development of the moral sentiments which Smith (1976a) thought so important
within compact communities, than from the need to recognise,
and sustain, the differences, sometimes startling, between the ways of thinking
within different specialisms.
The cost of producing a good or service is not defined by a publicly-accessible
production funnction, but depends on the capabilities
of the particular people who produce it; and the costs of a particular
transaction mode likewise depend on the particular people who are using that mode.
These capabilities are endogenous, and
should be analysed in the context of change: response
to change, preparation for change, and the generation of change. They result from specialisation,
and need to be co-ordinated, but in ways which do not
inhibit their continuing development; thus the capability of managing co-ordination
while fostering learning, as in the management of joint ventures, is worth
particular attention. But since
capability is know-how, manifested in action, and accumulated rather than the
product of logical analysis, it does not fit comfortably into conventional
economic theory. The training of
economists does not foster the skills which are necessary to handle the concept
of capabilities. It is presumably no
accident that the two economists who began to develop such skills, Marshall and
Hayek, did so by enquiring into cognitive psychology,
nor that their applications, to the organisation of
industry and social institutions respectively, attracted little attention from
economists. It is also presumably no
accident that both Marshall and Hayek gave their
applications an evolutionary turn, nor that the seminal modern study of
capabilities is set in the context of An Evolutionary Theory of Economic
Change (Nelson and Winter, 1982).
The organisation of capabilities is the organisation of systems for generating and testing new and improved skills. These systems are the institutions of economic evolution, which requires specialisation, but not uniformity within each specialism. There may at any time be ‘one best way’ of achieving a particular kind of result, but to train everyone within a specialism in that ‘best way’ would be a recipe for disaster. (Fortunately, there are always a few who escape or resist such framing.) Diversity is necessarily a system property, and it requires the absence of control; for control frustrates
157
the
development of capabilities to which one might later wish to have access. That is the fundamental argument against
central planning, an argument which was, not surprisingly, invisible to those
economists who sought to define allocative efficiency
on the assumption that all attainable knowledge was already available, without
even, as Hayek (1937) observed, asking to whom it might be available. Thus the co-ordination problems generated by
the division of labour were to be solved by ignoring
the reasons for the division of labour. Marshall’s continued preference for small
businesses, despite the advantages which, following Babbage, he recognised might be achieved by operating on a large scale,
rested substantially (though not solely) on the importance of maintaining the
sources of diversity. “Each man’s
actions are influenced by his special opportunities and resources, as well as
by his temperament and his associations” (Marshall, 1920, pp. 355-356); and
outsiders escaped the tyranny of conventional assumptions (Marshall, 1920, p. 197).
Just as direct capabilities change over time, given the appropriate
environment, so do indirect capabilities; people discover different and better
ways of getting things done. Thus the organisation of capabilities in any sector of the economy
is liable to change, often, as Langlois and Robertson
(1995) have shown, as a consequence of capabilities developed within that
pattern of organisation; there is no fundamental
reason for believing that any industry is permanently best fitted to any
particular organisational form. However, to explain, and perhaps occasionally
to predict, such changes, it is necessary to go beyond such factors as
economies of scale and transaction costs. It may also be necessary to go beyond
conventional economic methods of analysis. To improve our understanding of capabilities
we may need to develop new capabilities, and also new ways of organising those capabilities.
Ansoff, H. Igor, 1965.
Corporate Strategy, McGraw-Hill, New York.
Babbage, Charles, [1832], 1989. Economy
of manufactures and machinery. In: The
Works of Charles Babbage, vol. VIII, Pickeling, London.
Becattini, Giacomo, 1990. The Marshallian industrial district as a socio-economic notion
In: Pyke, Frank, Sengenberger,
Werner, Becattini, Giacomo
(eds.), Industrial Disticts and Inter-firm Co-operation,
ILO, Geneva.
Boehni, Stephan, 1994. Hayek and knowledge: Some question
marks. In: Colonna, Marina, Hagemann Harald, Hamouda, Omar F. (eds.),
Capitalism, Socialism and Knowledge: The
Economics of FA. Hayek, vol.
II, Edward Elgar, Aldershot.
Casson, Mark, 1982. The
Entrepreneur: An Economic Theory, Martin Robertson, Oxford.
Chandler, Alfred D., 1977.
The Visible Hand, Harvard University
Press, Cambridge, MA.
Chandler, Alfred D., 1990.
Scale and Scope, Harvard University
Press, Cambridge, MA.
Chandler, Alfred D., 1992. Orgrnsational capabilities and the
theory of the firm. Journal of Economic
Perspectives 6(3), 79-100.
Coase, Ronald H., 1937. The nature of the
firm. Economica
NS(4), 386-405. Reprinted in: Ronald
H. Coase, 1988, The Firm The Market, and The Law, University
of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp. 33-55.
Coase, Ronald H., 1972. Industrial organization: a proposal
for research. In: Fuchs, Victor R. (ed.), Policy
Issues and Research Opportunities in Industrial Organization, National
Bureau of Economic Research, New York. Reprinted in: Ronald
H. Coase, 1988, The
Firm, The Market and The Law, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp.
57-74.
Coase, Ronald H., 1991. The
nature of the firm: Influence. In: Williamson, Oliver E., Winter,
Sidney G. (Eds.), The Nature of The Firm: Origins, Evolution, and Development,
Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford, pp. 61-74.
Cohen, Wesley
M., Levanthal, Daniel A., 1989. Innovation and
learning: The two faces of R and D. Economic
Journal 99, 569-596.
Fransman, Martin, 1995.
Japan’s Computer and Communication
Industry, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Hahn, Frank
H., Solow, Robert M., 1955. A Critical Essay On Modern Macroeconomic
Theory, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA and London.
Hayek, Friedrich
A., 1937. Economics and knowledge. Economica NS(4),
33-54.
Hayek, Friedrich
A., 1945. The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review 35, 519-530.
Hayek, Friedrich
A., 1948. The meaning of competition In: Individualism
and Economic Order, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp. 92-106.
Hayek, Friedrich
A., 1952. The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into
the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology, Routledge,
London.
Hicks, John R., 1976. Some
questions of time in economics. In: Tang, Anthony M., Westfield, Fred M.,
Worley, James S. (eds.) Evolution,
Welfare and Time in Economics, Lexington Books, Lexington, MA, pp. 135-151.
Reprinted in: Hicks, John R., 1982, Collected Essays on Economic Theory,
vol., II, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 282-300.
Hounshell, David A., Smith,
John K., 1988. Science and Corporate
Strategy: Du Pont R&D, 1902-1980, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Keynes, J.
Maynard, 1936. The
General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money, Macmillan, London.
Kirzner, Israel M., 1973.
Competition and
Entrepreneurship, Chicago University Press, Chicago.
Klein, Burton H., 1977.
Dynamic Economics,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA.
Kuhn, Thomas S.,
1962. The Structure of
Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Langlois, Richard N., Robertson, Pain L., 1995.
Firms,
Markets and Economic Change, Rutledge, London.
Leijonhufvud, Axel, 1973. Effective demand failures, Swedish
Economic Journal March. Reprinted in Leijonhufvud,
Axel, 1981, Information and Co-ordination,
Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford. pp. 103-129.
Littlechild, Stephen C.,
1986. Three Types of Market Process. In: Langlois, Richard N. (ed.), 1986, Economics as a Process:
Essays in the New Institutional Economics, Cambridge University Press, Camblidge, pp. 27-39.
Loasby, Brian J., 1995. Acceptable explanations. In: Dow, Sheila C., Hillard, John (Eds.), Keynes,
Knowledge and Uncertainty, Edward Elgar, Aldershot.
Loasby, Brian J., 1998. How
do we know? In: Boehm, Stephan, Frowen, Stephen F., Pheby, John (eds)
Economics as the Art of Thought: Essays
in Memory of G. L. S. Shackle, Rutledge, London.
Marshau, Alfred, 1919.
Industry and Trade, Macmillan,
London.
Marshau, Alfred, 1920. Principles of Economics, 8th edn.,
Macmillan, London.
Marshau, Alfred, 1994. Ye
machine. Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology, Archival Supplement 4, 116-132.
Ménard, Claude, 1995. Markets as institutions or institutions as markets? Disentangling some
fundamental concepts. Journal of Economic
Behaviour and Organization 23, 161-182.
Menger, Carl, 1871 [1950]. Principles
of Economics. Translated by James Dingwall, and Bert F. Hoselitz,
Free Press, Glencoe, IL.
Minkler, Alanson P., 1993.
The problem with dispersed knowledge: Firms in theory and practice. Kyklos 46, 562-587.
Nelson,
Richard R., Winter, Sidney G., 1982. An Evolutionary Theory Of
Economic Change, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Nooteboom, Bait, 1992. Towards a dynamic theory of transactions. Journal of Evolutionary
Economics 2, 281-299.
Patel, Pari, Pavitt, Keith, 1995. Technological competences in the world’s
largest films: Characteristics, constraints and scope for managerial choice,
IIASA Working Paper, 95-66.
Patel, Pari, Pavitt, Keith, 1997. The
technological competences of the world’s largest firms: Complex and
path-dependent, but not much variety, Research
Policy 26, 141-56.
159
Penrose, Edith
T., 1959. The Theory of The Growth of The Firm, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 2nd edn. (1995), Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Porter,
Michael E., 1990. The
Competitive Advantage of Nations, Macmillan, London.
Raffaelli, Tiziano, 1995. The principles
of organization: A forgotten chapter of Marshallian
economics. Presented to European Conference On the History of Economics,
Rotterdam, 10-11 February 1995.
Richardson,
George B., 1960, [1990]. Information
and Investment, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Richardson,
George B., 1972. The organisation
of industry. Economic Journal 82, 883-896. Reprinted
in: Richardson, George B., 1990. Information and Investment, 2nd edn., Oxford
University Press, Oxford 224-242.
Rosenberg,
Nathan, 1994. Exploring
the Black Box: Technology, Economics, and History, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Ryle, Gilbert, 1949.
The Concept of Mind,
Hutchinson, London.
Schumpeter,
Joseph A., 1934. The
Theory of Economic Development, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Smith, Adam, !976a. The Theory of
Moral Sentiments, Raphael, David D., Macfie, Alec
L. (eds.), Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Smith, Adam, !976b. An Inquiry
into The Nature and Causes of The Wealth of Nations, Campbell, Roy H.,
Skinner, Andrew S. (eds.), 2 vols., Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Smith, Adam,
1980. The principles which lead and direct philosophical enquiries: illustrated
by the history of astronomy. In: Wightman, William PD. (ed.), Essays On Philosophical Subjects (1795),
Oxford University Press, Oxford 33-105.
Teece, D.J., Rumelt, R., Dosi, G., Winter, S.G., 1994. Understanding corporate coherence:
Theory and Mdence. Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organization
23, 1-30.
Winter, Sidney
G., 199!. On Coase,
Competence, and the Corporation.In: Williamson, Oliver
E., Winter, Sidney G. (Eds.), The Nature of the Firm: Origins, Evolution, and Development, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, pp. 179-195.
Williamson,
Oliver E., 1975. Markets and Hierarchies:
Analysis and Anti-trust Implications, Free Press, New York.
Witt, Ulrich,
1998. Imagination and
leadership - The neglected dimension of an (evolutionary) theory of the firm.
Presented to EMOT Workshop On Technology and the Theory of
the Firm, University of Reading.
Young, Allyn G., 1928. Increasing returns and
economic progress, Economic Journal
38, 523-542.
Zajac, Edward J., Olsen,
Cyrus P., 1993. From transaction cost to transaction value analysis: Implications
for the study of interorganizational strategies. Journal of Management Studies 30, 131-145.
Ziman, John M., 1978. Reliable Knowledge, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
160