The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Brian J. Loasby
Hypothesis
and Paradigm in the Theory of the Firm [1]
Economic Journal, 81 (324)
Dec.,
1971, 863-885.
Content
The Paradigm of Perfect Competition
Imperfect Competition or General
Equilibrium?
The Illusory Crisis and Its Consequences
Imperfect and Monopolistic Competition: One Theory or
Two?
THOUGH here
applied to a particular subject area, the arguments presented in this article
have a much wider significance. The
article begins with an emphasis on the kinds of abstraction which are necessary
in a study of complex systems, and an exposition, in the context of economics,
of the ideas developed by T. S. Kuhn to analyse
theoretical innovation in the physical sciences. [2] This apparatus is then
used to illuminate some critical developments in the theory of value, leading
up to an examination of the credentials of behavioural
theories of the firm. In the process, it
reveals some widespread misconceptions among economists about the nature of
economic science, and shows how these misconceptions have not only been
responsible for much confusion but have also critically influenced the development
of economic theory.
Logically, as
well as historically, the development of economics as an important and
distinctive discipline derives from the increasing extent and complexity of the
division of labour. It is true that an allocation problem exists
whenever an individual’s resources are not sufficient for the satisfaction of
all his wants; but although the economic problems of Robinson Crusoe are very
convenient for elucidating some features of the elementary analysis of choice,
they are scarcely adequate material for a major field of study. That material is to be found in the
interdependent choices which result from an elaborate division of labour - between individuals, between firms, between
regions and between countries.
Because
interdependence is its basis, economics is necessarily a study of systems;
because it is concerned with the allocation of resources by human beings, it is
a study of decision-making systems. (As
we shall see, this does not necessarily imply a study of the process of
decision-making; micro-economists have generally been concerned with
consequences rather than processes.) Economists
have therefore to cope with two intrinsic difficulties of system analysis - the
definition of system boundaries and the specification of system structure. On the one hand, all economic systems are
sub-systems - sub-systems both of larger economic systems (unless one is
explicitly dealing with the world economy) and also of more broadly defined
human and ecological systems; thus interdependencies transcend the bounds of
the
1. A version of this paper was
presented at the Annual Conference of the Association of University Teachers of
Economics at Canterbury on April 6, 1971.
2 T. S. Kuhn, The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1962).
system
being studied. On the other hand, some
abstraction from detail is essential, and this involves not only the omission
of variables, but also distortion of the relationships which are included. Thus the economist has no option but to
construct models which fall short - usually far short - of a complete
specification of the system which he wishes to analyse;
he must choose where to make his approximations, some of which must normally be
very drastic. It follows, first, that no
economic model can be finally judged by the resemblance between its
specification and the real-life system which it claims to represent; and,
second, that the choice of different specifications by different economists for
their models of the same system carries no presumption that one of them must be
in error. For these reasons, it is safer
to talk of the “sufficiency” of models than of their “realism.”
Though
approximations in both directions are necessary, economists tend either to
jettison detail in order to concentrate on major interactions, or to ignore
interdependencies in order to concentrate on relative detail. This, of course, is the basis of the
distinction between macro-economics and micro-economics. Macro-economics explores the system known as
the national economy, defined into such sectors as consumption, investment,
government expenditure and exports, each of which is a highly complex
sub-system. The export sector
necessarily implies interdependence with other national economies: this
interdependence may be handled very crudely - even ignored - or analysis may
concentrate, in international trade theory, on the intersections of these
national economy sets. Sometimes the
components of the national economy will be defined, for the purposes of input-output
analysis, as industry groups - which are not proper sub-sets of the major
sectors normally used in macro-economic analysis. Whatever the form of the macro-level analysis,
the sub-systems of which it is composed are treated very simply by the use of
assumptions which may be rejected in the analysis of the sub-systems
themselves. (For example, theoretical
international trade usually appears to be carried on under conditions of
universal perfect competition, while the industries analysed
in input-output analysis may operate with both constant marginal costs and
constant returns to scale.) But, because
of the fundamental difficulties of system analysis, such a conflict of
assumptions at different levels cannot invalidate the arguments which rest on
them.
Micro-economics,
on the other hand, simply assumes away some of the interdependencies which form
the subject-matter of macro-system analysis. But this obvious contrast with macro-economics
should not be allowed to obscure the fact that micro-economics makes its
sacrifices of detail too; and they can be very large. For, although it claims to include within its
scope the allocation of a firm’s internal resources, it regards the firm itself
as the basic decision-making unit. Since,
however, the greater part of resource allocation within industry is determined
nowadays by firms which are themselves decision-making systems, a third level
of analysis is possible, which is
864
likely
to require further sacrifice of interdependencies in order to explore the
details of sub-system behaviour. The economics of organisational
behaviour not only illuminates the affinities between
economics and organisation theory; it is a natural
extension of the scope of the subject, being characteristically concerned with
the relationship between structure and performance - the ways in which the
system being studied responds to and regulates choice.
This emphasis
on a systems study necessarily implies some qualifications to the view
sometimes expressed that economists should seek to emulate as closely as
possible the methodology of the experimental sciences. [1] Since this methodology
has traditionally rested on the isolation and manipulation of closely-specified
relationships, it presents difficulties for the economist, whose manipulation
must usually be statistical (possibly with the number of trials outside his
control), and who frequently cannot isolate the phenomena which he wishes to
study. But not only is narrow isolation
difficult; it is often inappropriate. For it is characteristic of system behaviour that it may not be explicable as a simple - or
even weighted - sum of separate effects. From this point of view, it is the contrast,
not the comparison, between economics and experimental science which is illuminating.
There are
greater similarities between economics and applied science, especially science
directed towards the development and operation of industrial processes. For these are systems too,
and systems normally too large to be modelled in
full. So the scientist is here
faced with a problem akin to that of the economist: to choose a degree of
abstraction in his experimentation which is drastic enough to simplify his
analysis and yet robust enough to give value to his conclusions. For such choices his academic training in
experimental method does not prepare him very well. “The transition from the laboratory to plant
implies a change of scale from what can, in most cases, be handled and
controlled manually by one scientist, to a system which is far outside the
capacity of one man, unaided by automation and instrumentation, to control. Many scientists, we find, have a very hazy
idea of the sort of problems that arise on transferring operations from
laboratory to plant.” [2] But awareness of such problems is
necessary if the laboratory experiments performed are to be those which are
most relevant.
However,
although the unrealistic assumptions of the economist may be fairly compared
with the artificial environment of the laboratory as a means of abstracting
from complex systems, yet it should not be overlooked that the
1. E.g., R. G. Lipsey, An Introduction to Positive Economics, Second
edition (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson,
1966), Chapter 1.
2. A. Baines, F. R. Bradbury and
C. W. Suckling, Research in the Chemical Industry (London: Elsevier,
1969), p. 165. Their example of filtration suggests some analogies in economic
policymaking.
character
of the abstraction is different. The
scientist abstracts from complexities towards the detail of real phenomena; the
economist tends to abstract from detail into terms which have only economic
meaning. [1]
There is a
further difficulty in the way of general reliance on experimental or
statistical-experimental method in economics. Not only may hypotheses be difficult to test,
or relate to system behaviour to which closely
restricted analysis is not appropriate; some economic hypotheses turn out not
to be hypotheses at all, but paradigms.
A paradigm,
in the natural sciences as well as in economics, defines the type of
relationships to be investigated and the methods and abstractions to be
regarded as legitimate within a particular problem area. [2] Once such terms of reference are
generally accepted by practitioners within that area, research becomes “a
strenuous and devoted effort to force nature into the conceptual boxes supplied
by professional education.” [3]
(All
boxes are empty until the work of filling them begins.) A paradigm must therefore be both
comprehensive and open-ended; it leaves many problems to be solved and holds
out the prospect of successful solutions to those who formulate and test with
skill and care particular hypotheses consistent with the paradigm. For the natural scientist, at least,
therefore, it offers “a criterion for choosing problems that, while the
paradigm is taken for granted, can be assumed to have solutions.” [4] That such criteria are
indispensable for the natural scientist is emphasised
by P. B. Medawar, explaining “why scientists seem so
often to shirk the study of really fundamental or challenging problems... No scientist is admired for failing in the
attempt to solve problems that lie beyond his competence. The most he can hope for is the kindly
contempt earned by the Utopian politician. If politics is the art of the possible,
research is surely the art of the soluble. Both are immensely practical-minded affairs.” [5]
H. A. Simon
applies a similar argument more widely. “People (and rats) find the most
interest in situations that are neither completely strange nor entirely known -
where there is novelty to be explored, but where similarities and programs
remembered from past experience help guide the exploration. Nor does creativity flourish in completely
unstructured situations. The almost
unanimous testimony of creative artists and scientists is that the first task
is to impose limits on the situation if the limits are not already
1. Cf. R. M. Cyert
and E. Grunberg, “Assumption, Prediction and
Explanation in Economics,” in R. M. Cyert and J. G.
March, A Behavioural Theory of the Firm (Englewood
Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1963), pp. 301-2.
2. Kuhn, op. cit., pp.
10, 11.
3. Kuhn, op. cit., p. 5.
4. Kuhn, op. cit., p. 37.
5. P. B. Medawar,
The Art of the Soluble (London: Methuen,
1967), pp. 86-7.
866
given.”
[1]
It is the role of
the paradigm to provide such limitations to the agenda for inquiry.
Because a
paradigm defines a set - often a very large set - of possible hypotheses, but
makes no claims for the validity of any particular members of that set (some of
which, indeed, will be mutually exclusive alternatives), it follows that
paradigms, unlike the hypotheses to which they give rise, cannot be validated by
experimental or statistical methods.
Failure to recognise this distinction has led
to much unnecessary argument, of which the disputes over profit-maximisation provide a notorious example. For profit-maximisation
is not a hypothesis but a paradigm; and whereas a specific hypothesis embodying
some version of profit-maximisation can, in
principle, be tested, the paradigm of profit-maximisation
cannot. Only in long-period static
equilibrium with perfect knowledge is its formulation unique; and no such experimental
conditions can be found. One common form
of criticism is, in fact, a tribute to its virtue. With a little ingenuity, it is possible to
explain almost any kind of business behaviour as
profit-maximisation. The retort that, “if it can explain everything,
it explains nothing” would be conclusive against a loosely formulated
hypothesis; but it is precisely this ability to generate a variety of
hypotheses to explain, if not everything, yet a large body of important
phenomena, which is the essential virtue of a paradigm. Lipsey’s attempt to emphasise the testing of economic predictions suffers from
a similar confusion: the theory expounded in his text-book is necessarily a
paradigm, to which his proposed tests, being designed for hypotheses, cannot properly
be applied. [2]
The obverse
of a paradigm’s continued fertility is the continued existence of unsolved
problems. A paradigm which left no
issues unresolved would be useless as a guide to further work. Thus “a thousand difficulties do not make one
doubt” [3] concerning the acceptability of
a paradigm; on the contrary they offer a thousand opportunities for the
deployment of professional skill. Provided
that they are being steadily resolved, the existence of difficulties is a
symptom, not of a paradigm’s weakness, but of its continuing strength. This remains true even when some major
difficulties prove recalcitrant. For
example, attempts to explain the path of the moon by the application of
Newtonian theory failed consistently for sixty years; yet there were no serious
proposals for the rejection of Newtonian theory. What was in question was not the paradigm, but
the professional skill of the scientists who had failed to derive an
appropriate hypothesis from it; and, in the event, confidence in Newtonian
theory was justified. [4]
1. H. A. Simon, The Shape of Automation for Men and Management (New
York: Harper & Row, 1965), pp. 97-8.
2. Lipsey,
op. cit., e.g., Chapter 29.
3. J. H. Newman, Apologia Pro Vita Sua.
4. Kuhn, op. cit., pp.
39, 81.
It is not,
therefore, surprising, that a paradigm, once established, should prove
difficult to overthrow. Since its
continued usefulness depends on the double condition of unresolved problems and
good prospects of their eventual solution by the application of the paradigm,
there can be no unequivocal standard by which a paradigm can be judged to have
failed. Those who attack a paradigm may
simply be confessing their inability to use the tools of their trade as
effectively as their fellows. Even if
this is not an effective deterrent, to discard a well-established paradigm is
to discard an important part of one’s apparatus for recognising
and solving problems. Furthermore, since
a paradigm, like a management control system, provides the basis for selecting
both problems and the relevant variables to be investigated, it may condition
its users against even the perception of some of the more fundamental threats. An experiment in which subjects readily
identified as normal wrongly coloured playing cards
inserted into an otherwise normal pack provides some formal confirmation of the
common experience in, all manner of contexts that observations are “fitted to
one of the conceptual categories prepared by prior experience.” [1] A paradigm produces
intellectual tunnel vision.
Thus
something quite exceptional in the way of difficulties must become apparent
before an established paradigm can be seriously challenged. As Shackle says, “Theoretical advance can
spring only from theoretical crisis.” [2] In the natural sciences,
at least, the existence of a rival paradigm is a necessary condition for a
challenge - no paradigm which offers some answers is going to be abandoned
unless alternative answers are on offer. But it is certainly not sufficient. The clearest evidence for this statement is
provided by the anticipations of later major developments to be found, not in
the underworld of economics, but in the intendedly
definitive text of Marshall’s Principles.
[3] Until
the definitiveness of Marshall was challenged, these anticipations lay not only
undeveloped but often unnoticed.
Shackle’s own
explanation of the persistence of paradigms can be summarised
in his own words. “The chief service
rendered by a theory” - by which he clearly means a paradigm, not a hypothesis
– “is the setting of minds at rest. So
long as we have a satisfying conceptual structure, a model or a taxonomy which
provides for the filing of all facts in a scheme or order, we are absolved from
the tiresome labour of thought, and the uneasy
consciousness of mystery and a threatening unknown.” [4] This explanation is
1. Kuhn, op. cit., pp. 62-4;
the experiment is reported in J. S. Bruner and L. Postman, “On the Perception
of Incongruity: A Paradigm,” Journal of Personality, Vol. XVIII, 1949,
pp. 206-23.
2. G. L. S. Shackle, The Years of High Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1967), p. 288.
3. A convenient selection of
examples may be found in D. H. Robertson, “A Revolutionist’s Handbook,”
reprinted in Utility and All That and Other Essays (London, Allen and Unwin, 1952), pp. 66-80.
4. Shackle, op. cit., p.
288.
868
in part
misleading. To see why, it is necessary
to distinguish between unease and hard thought. Paradigms, far from avoiding the labour of thought, may call for both intense and protracted
effort if they are to be expressed in viable hypotheses. [1] Their virtue, in this
respect, lies in permitting that effort to be deployed within a well-defined
structure, instead of having to be applied to the definition of that structure;
they permit a concentration on short-run questions. But in academic work, as in business, long-run
questions, even if no more intellectually taxing, are much less comfortable,
because they tend to open up an unpalatable range of options. They require the managing director to consider
what business he should be in, or the academic the proper scope of his subject.
An acceptable paradigm affords
protection from such disturbing speculations.
“Theory... imposes a beautiful simplicity on the
unbearable multiplicity of fact, gives comfort in face of the unknown and unexperienced, stops the teasing of mystery and doubt
which, though salutory and life-preserving, is
uncomfortable, so that we seek by theory to sort out the justified from the
unjustified fear. Theories by their
nature and purpose, their role of administering to a ‘good state of mind,’ are
things to be held and cherished. Theories
are altered or discarded only when they fail us.” [2]
Intellectual retooling is
uncomfortable, as well as expensive.
This argument
needs to be taken just one stage further, in order to explain the tenacity with
which people cling to old paradigms even in crisis, and even when alternatives
are available. Often the new contender
is not a perfect substitute for the old: while offering solutions to some
difficulties which appear insoluble within the established paradigm, it may
offer inferior solutions to others; and, indeed, to some questions hitherto
satisfactorily handled it may offer no solution at all. For example, Lavoisier,
in offering a solution to the critical issues which the phlogiston theory
seemed unable to resolve, could provide no explanation whatever for the
similarities between metals, which phlogiston theory had readily accounted
for. [3]
Thus the
competition between paradigms turns not simply on their relative merits in
explaining certain important phenomena, but on judgments about which are the
important phenomena to explain. For
these judgments there are no generally acceptable criteria; indeed they cannot
be made without excursions into those regions of mystery and doubt from which
paradigms, once accepted, serve to protect us. A change of paradigm redefines the set of
relevant problems, and the criteria for selecting problems and evaluating
solutions: it changes to some degree - occasionally to a large degree - the
accepted definition of the scope of a subject. With its combination of the threatened
obsolescence of some established methodology,
1. Kuhn, op. cit., pp. 26, 30.
2. Shackle, op. cit., pp. 288-9.
3. Kuhn, op. cit., p. 147.
and the
posing of awkward, sometimes fundamental, questions about the nature of a
subject, a time of paradigm change is a time of upheaval that for many may be
more disturbing than exhilarating. A
subject in which paradigms are often not
firmly-established, like economics, offers much less security to its
practitioners than one, like chemistry, in which they are relatively secure. (Graduate chemists turning to economics for
the first time are liable to be disconcerted by this loss of security.) But even apparently-assured security can prove
illusory, as atomic physicists have painfully realised
in recent years.
Whether
economics (or any other social science) has yet succeeded in establishing any
paradigms as widely accepted, even for a short time, as those associated with
Copernicus, Newton or Lavoisier, may be doubted. Nevertheless,
the concept of paradigm change seems capable of extension to illuminate some
major innovations in economic theory. It
has, indeed, recently been effectively used by Axel Leijonhufvud
in his examination of the Keynesian revolution. [1]
Leijonhufvud
argues that the neo-classical synthesis has been achieved by forcing Keynes’
ideas within the traditional general equilibrium paradigm of a static system of
simultaneous equations; and that Keynes’ attempt to construct a new paradigm, emphasising processes and information flows within the
system, has been rejected, or even unrecognised. This argument will not be further considered
in this paper, except for drawing a later analogy with behavioural
theory; attention will be concentrated on micro-economics, beginning with the
emergence of the theory of the firm.
The Paradigm of
Perfect Competition
The Marshallian synthesis on the theory of value was
constructed with almost incredible care and subtlety; indeed some of the
sharpest minds of the twenties and thirties simply failed to appreciate what
Marshall had done, and construed his caution as hesitancy and his subtlety as
confusion. But Marshall was facing
methodological difficulties which could not be solved, only lived with. Shackle partially explains the situation.
“Marshall’s self-imposed endeavour was an intensely
difficult one. He sought to describe a
mechanism of evolution of the firm and industry; to derive the principles of
this mechanism from the detailed and wide observation of a segment of British
economic and social history,... and to make his
account of this observable productive evolution the vehicle of laws which
should be in some degree general and permanent.” [2]
Shackle
places the emphasis on the problem of explaining a great variety of specific
facts by a single body of theory - the achievement of a high level
1. Axel Leijonhufvud, On Keynesian Economics and the Economics
of Keynes (New York and London: Oxford University Press, 1968). I am indebted
to Professor A. D. Bain for drawing my attention to the significance of this
work.
2. Shackle, op. cit., p.
44.
870
of
abstraction without significant loss of sufficiency. This type of problem, as was pointed out
earlier, is characteristic of all science, though of peculiar difficulty in
this particular instance. But the way
Marshall tackled the problem evoked a difficulty of a special sort. The key lies in Shackle’s phrase “a mechanism
of evolution.” Mechanism suggests
mathematics; and it was not surprising that Marshall, a mathematician himself
should turn to mathematics for a formal exposition of “general and permanent
laws.” If a formal mathematical model was
to be produced, then the obvious - perhaps the only possible - body of theory
to use was the differential calculus, the value of which in economics had first
been effectively demonstrated by Cournot. But an analytical method based on differential
calculus, though the best available, was hardly ideal as a paradigm of growth
and change. Marshall consistently emphasised biological analogies, but there was simply no
“biological mathematics” adequate for his purpose; and so evolution had to be
explained in terms of static equilibrium. The use of a strictly timeless theory by one
who was so conscious of the importance of time represents a heroic - and highly
successful - use of abstraction; but only by the use of all Marshall’s care and
subtlety could it be made to appear convincing. It may, indeed, be judged too successful and
too convincing; for whereas Marshall was keenly aware that his mathematical
abstractions would lose sufficiency if pressed much further, some of his
successors, being young and bold, were less inhibited. By revealing the inherent contradictions
between the model and the real world, which Marshall had so skillfully
concealed, they helped to precipitate a crisis in value theory.
The
theoretical argument was forcefully summarised by Sraffa in his famous article of 1926, in which he demonstrated
that increasing and decreasing returns were both strictly incompatible with
other assumptions of the standard formal analysis, that the size of the firm
was therefore left indeterminate by this analysis, and that there was thus no
adequate justification for casting that analysis in terms of perfect
competition. [1] The
logic of Sraffa’s criticism and of his proposed
solution are worth examining. The key
sentences run as follows.
If diminishing returns arising from a ‘constant
factor’ are taken into consideration, it becomes necessary to extend the field
of investigation so as to examine the conditions of simultaneous equilibrium in
numerous industries: a well-known conception, whose complexity, however,
prevents it from bearing fruit, at least in the present state of our knowledge,
which does not permit of even much simpler schemata being applied to the study
of real situations. If we pass to
external economies, we find ourselves confronted by the same obstacle, and
there is also the impossibility of confining within statical
conditions the circumstances from which they originate.
1. P. Sraffa,
“The Laws of Returns under Competitive Conditions,” Economic Journal,
Vol. XXXVI 1926, reprinted in G. J. Stigler and K. E. Boulding
(eds.), Readings in Price Theory (London: Allen and Unwin,
1953), pp. 180-97.
It is necessary, therefore, to abandon the path of
free competition and turn in the opposite direction, namely towards monopoly. Here we find a well-defined theory in which
variations of cost connected with changes in the dimensions of the individual
undertaking play an important part.” [1]
These
sentences are perhaps so familiar that it will be easier to analyse
the argument if they are paraphrased. The
strict formal requirements of static partial equilibrium analysis do not permit
the conditions which are logically necessary for the existence of perfect
competition. Therefore something must
go. The cost conditions which make
perfect competition possible are indeed compatible with dynamic general
equilibrium; but general equilibrium is a much less usable paradigm than
partial equilibrium, and dynamic analysis is still more hopeless. On the other hand, the theory of monopoly
offers a readily-available alternative to perfect competition, while still
retaining all the usual conditions of static partial equilibrium.
Thus the
argument turns, not on the existence of perfect competition as a recognisable state of affairs, but on first, the internal
consistency, and second, the relative usefulness, of competing paradigms. It is important to take these two criteria, of
internal consistency and relative usefulness, separately; and it is convenient
to begin with the latter.
Imperfect
Competition or General Equilibrium?
Let us accept
for the moment Kaldor’s conclusion that “long-period
static equilibrium and perfect competition are incompatible assumptions.” [2] Marshall’s theory made
room for monopoly; the new theory had no room for perfect competition, as Joan
Robinson forcefully made clear. When we
see some situations approximating to perfect competition, but none, in
developed economies, approximating to long-period static equilibrium, what are
we to think of a choice of paradigm in which perfect competition becomes an
inadmissible market form? Surely the
answer is that the choice was soundly based on good scientific practice, which
exemplifies at this point the economic doctrine of opportunity cost. Usefulness, rather than immediate realism, is
the proper ground for choosing between paradigms. The cost of giving up static partial
equilibrium analysis, in terms of existing theory to be discarded, was far
higher than the cost of giving up perfect competition, and the gains, in terms
of alternative theory lying ready for exploitation, were far less.
That this is
the relevant basis for choice is confirmed by the reasoning of the most
distinguished economist who made the opposite choice, in favour
of general equilibrium theory - J. R. Hicks. He stood Sraffa’s
conclusion
1. Sraffa,
op. cit., p. 187.
2. N. Kaldor,
“The Equilibrium of the Firm,” Economic Journal, Vol. XLIV (1934); reprinted
in N. Kaldor, Essays on Value and Distribution (London:
Duckworth, 1969), p. 46.
872
on its
head: imperfect competition was incompatible with partial equilibrium, general
equilibrium was incompatible with anything other than perfect competition. The essentials of Hicks’ argument, too, are
worth quoting in his own words. [1]
It has to be recognised that
a general abandonment of the assumption of perfect competition, a universal
adoption of the assumption of monopoly, must have very destructive consequences
for economic theory. Under monopoly the
stability, conditions become indeterminate; and the basis on which economic
laws can be constructed is therefore shorn away…
It is, I believe, only possible to save anything from
this wreck - and it must be remembered that the threatened wreckage is that of
the greater part of general equilibrium theory - if we can assume that the
markets confronting most of the firms with which we shall be dealing do not
differ very greatly from perfectly competitive markets... At least, this
get-away seems well worth trying. We
must be aware, however, that we are taking a dangerous step, and probably
limiting to a serious extent the problems with which our subsequent analysis
will be fitted to deal. Personally,
however, I doubt if most of the problems we shall have to exclude for this
reason are capable of much useful analysis by the methods of economic theory.
No more than Sraffa, Kaldor, and the others
who argued the opposite case, does Hicks appeal to facts. Indeed, he admits that the facts may well be
against him. Neither party follows Beveridge’s prescription, endorsed by Lipsey,
to seek empirical verification. [2] And on this issue they
are right, and Beveridge and Lipsey
are wrong. For the argument is not about
hypotheses - concerning which Beveridge and Lipsey are of course quite correct
- but about the kinds of hypotheses and the kinds of data that might be presented
for verification; and here the empiricist’s prescription is not only
inappropriate but often impossible.
The readiness
with which Hicks is prepared to accept the exclusion of important problems from
consideration as the price of using the paradigm of perfect competition should
also be noted. The availability of a
paradigm is more relevant than the importance of a problem. Here again Hicks is following scientific
principles, as explained by Medawar. “Good scientists
study the most important problems they think they can solve. It is, after all, their professional business
to solve problems, not to grapple with them. The spectacle of a scientist locked in combat
with the forces of ignorance is not an inspiring one if in the outcome, the
scientist is routed.” [3] Economists
are perhaps in general readier than natural scientists to tackle ignorance with
inadequate weapons; but this readiness springs from inferior armament rather than
superior virtue. And it is, after all,
only relative; it would be difficult to maintain that the distribution of
economic effort
1. J. R. Hicks, Value and Capital (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1939), pp. 83-5.
2. Lipsey, op. cit., pp.
xi-xii, 3-18.
3. Medawar, op. cit., p.
7.
reflects
at all closely the importance of economic issues; much less difficult to relate
it to the availability of usable paradigms. Nor is this necessarily wrong, for it can be
argued that a discipline will make faster progress if its practitioners are
insulated from pressures to “choose problems because they urgently need
solution and without regard for the tools available to solve them.” [1]
The Illusory
Crisis and Its Consequences
So far we
have argued that, given the existence of a crisis in value theory, the solution
of abandoning perfect competition, though apparently odd, was justified. But we still have to ask, was there a real
theoretical crisis? If one accepts the
earlier argument about the significance of paradigms, and, particularly, the
argument about the degree of abstraction - in structure as well as in the
choice of variables - required to create a usable paradigm in a study of such
complex systems, the answer must surely be no. The theoretical crisis arose out of a
misconception about the nature of the subject, and therefore of the way it
should develop. Any usable model must be
a mis-specification of the reality to which it refers;
in economics this mis-specification must often be so
great as to show little apparent resemblance to that reality. To refine the abstractions in a workable
paradigm is often to refine away the reality that remains; consistency must
often be sacrificed in order to retain adequate sufficiency. When the conditions requisite for static
partial equilibrium analysis are carefully spelt out, as they were for example
by Kaldor in 1934, [2]
it should become obvious that long-period static equilibrium is formally
incompatible not merely with perfect competition, but with any of the
real-world phenomena which we habitually use it to explain. Not even the simplest curve shifting is logically
permissible: as Mrs. Robinson has sardonically observed, equilibrium is not a
position at which one can arrive; one must be in it already. [3]
Thus “a more
rigorous formulation of the conditions under which it is possible to make generalisations about the factors determining economic
equilibrium” [4] must be no more than a
subsidiary concern, since it is obvious that the conditions will never be met. What matters is how extensively they can be
violated without seriously impugning the result to which they lead. A strict regard for internal consistency in
economic theory is as likely to be a vice as a virtue.
Therefore
before deciding whether she took the “wrong turning” in writing The
Economics of Imperfect Competition instead of “abandoning static
1. Kuhn, op. cit., p.
163.
2. N. Kaldor,
“The Determinateness of Static Equilibrium,” Review of Economic Studies, February
1934; reprinted in Essays on Value and Distribution, pp. 13-33.
3. J. Robinson,
Collected Economic Papers, Vol. II (Oxford: Blackwell, 1966), p. 120.
4. Kaldor,
Essays, p. 13.
874
analysis
and trying to come to terms with Marshall’s theory of development,” Mrs.
Robinson ought first to have enquired a little more carefully whether any
turning was needed at all. Simply to
state that “the profound inconsistency between the static base and the dynamic
superstructure had become too obvious” just will not do. [1] Nor
will the more recent argument that “imperfect competition came in to explain
the fact, in the world around us, that more or less all plants were working
part time:” [2] the phenomena of short-run
general disequilibrium cannot be explained in terms of long-run partial
equilibrium.
Are we then,
as D. H. Robertson suggested, no more than half in jest, “to regard all that
has happened since (Marshall) in this field as a vast crime wave”? [3] Surely not; for two
reasons. The less important reason is
that the changing structure of industry did pose problems of fact which
appeared to reinforce the problems of theory; any commentary on the arguments
of the time which ignores the contemporary concern with these problems must
appear unfair to some of the protagonists of change, even though one may doubt
the completeness of their success in explaining the new structure by the new
theory. The more important reason is
that, as is likely to happen when a paradigm changes, the new theory redefined
the scope of this branch of economics. As
Shackle observes, “not only the answers, but the questions, were new. The whole notion of what value theory sought
to do and the way its aim should be accomplished had been changed... Primacy
had passed from the autonomously self-subsisting technical commodity to the
firm considered as a profit-maximising policymaker. [4]. The creation of the
theory of the firm brought the analysis of decision-making within the accepted
scope of the subject; it thus not only made possible the development of
managerial economics, but determined its characteristic virtues and defects.
Imperfect and Monopolistic
Competition: One Theory or Two?
The almost
simultaneous appearance of two full-length presentations of the new theory of
the firm by E. H. Chamberlin and Mrs. Robinson necessarily
raised the question whether it was indeed one theory or two. But the question was apparently soon disposed
of: although Chamberlin continued to insist, to the
end of his life, on the fundamental differences between the concepts of
monopolistic and of imperfect competition, very few economists of importance,
even among those most sympathetic to Chamberlin’s
formulation, took the claim seriously. [5] This was unfortunate,
because Chamberlin was quite right.
1. J. Robinson, Collected
Economic Papers, Vol. 1 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1951), pp. vii-viii.
2. J. Robinson, The Economics of Imperfect Competition, Second
Edition (London: Macmillan, 1969), p. vi.
3. Robertson, op. cit., p.
73.
4. Shackle, op. cit., p.
65.
5. Shackle, op. cit., p.
62.
The trouble
may be explained as a confusion between hypothesis and
theory. Much of the formal analysis,
notably the tangency solution which reconciles monopolistic discretion over
price with normal competitive profits, can indeed be regarded as common to
both. But these similarities can be
explained by the natural inclination to use and develop familiar tools of
analysis within the accepted framework of partial equilibrium and profit-maximisation; the function of the analysis, in relation to
both theoretical issues and their views of the world, is very different for the
two authors.
Imperfect
competition was created to escape from the dilemma propounded by Sraffa. Since rising
costs were excluded by the formal conditions of perfectly competitive partial
equilibrium (as well as apparently absent from many firms), and yet the method
of partial equilibrium analysis seemed indispensable, the only escape seemed to
lie in a falling demand curve for the individual firm. This falling demand curve was not an observed
fact, but - most compelling of arguments - a methodological necessity. As P. W. S. Andrews observed, “Seen from this
methodological point of view, Joan Robinson’s demand functions have no
analytical roots. Her demand curves fall
simply because she tells them to do so.” [1]
Indeed, she was inhibited from looking for
analytical roots by her concern to preserve the concept of the industry, which
led her to regard the products of competing firms as virtually identical in all
respects save the attitudes of individual customers towards them, and thus
eliminated any rational basis for the falling demand curves which her theory
required.
Such
abstractions may well be justified by the usefulness of the theoretical
structure which they make possible (and some such concept as the industry is
essential to partial equilibrium analysis); but there is a danger that inferences
about the real world may be drawn from theoretical assumptions, instead of the
reverse. And of course in this instance
such inferences were drawn, most conspicuously by Mrs. Robinson herself. For example, the section headed “Forms of
Competition” in her article “Imperfect Competition Revisited” lays overwhelming
emphasis on competitive waste. [2] In addition, the excess
capacity and unexhausted economies of scale which were presented as such
notable consequences of the theory were already explicit in the assumption of
falling costs on which it was founded. The
moral of imperfect competition is that potential economies of large-scale
production are frustrated by producers’ iniquity and consumers’ gullibility or
perversity; the situation therefore seems to demand, rather than permit,
“almost unlimited pushing around.” [3] But this is not the only
theory which fits the formal analysis.
1. P. W. S. Andrews, On
Competition in Economic Theory (London: Macmillan, 1964), p. 22.
2. J. Robinson, “Imperfect
Competition Revisited,” Economic Journal,
September 1953, reprinted in Collected Economic Papers, Vol. II (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1960), pp. 228-9.
3. Robertson, op. cit., p.
75.
876
Chamberlin, by contrast, started not with costs but with
demand, which reflected differences in consumers’ preferences and between
competitive products. His assumption of
uniform demand and cost curves is much more obviously a temporary expedient to
aid exposition than it is in Mrs. Robinson’s analysis, and the tangency equilibrium
is not presented as a general solution. Because products and consumers do differ, even
in equilibrium “some (or all) of the demand curves may lie at various distances
to the right of the point of tangency, leaving monopoly profits scattered
throughout the group - and throughout the price system.” [1] We
should therefore be much less surprised than even the sympathetic D. H.
Robertson to find Chamberlin speaking of his
equilibrium - monopoly profits and all - as a sort of ideal. [2]
If
economies of scale are frustrated in this paradigm, it is largely because the
alternative is to frustrate the need for variety which flows from “ differences
in tastes, desires, incomes, and locations of buyers, and differences in the
uses which they wish to make of commodities.” [2] But perhaps Chamberlin did not take his falling cost curves too
seriously. After all, they were a
methodological necessity, given a falling demand curve, for equilibrium with
normal profits, just as falling demand curves were a methodological necessity,
given falling costs, for Mrs. Robinson.
The
distinction between imperfect and monopolistic competition is perhaps
especially marked in the area of managerial economics. The concepts of monopolistic competition harmonise readily with the emphasis in marketing theory on
the profit opportunities in offering distinctive consumer satisfactions, as
evaluated by the consumer. To the
marketer, as once to the economist, the customer buys, not a product, but the
expectation of benefits: the variety of ways to consumer satisfaction, and the
importance of consumer satisfaction, both submerged by the tendency of
imperfect competition theory to regard every means by which a firm may aim to
give added value as a wasteful device for bamboozling the ignorant customer,
are fundamental assumptions of monopolistic competition. In the current management jargon, imperfect
competition is producer-oriented, monopolistic competition is
consumer-oriented.
Furthermore,
monopolistic competition theory, though formulated in terms of static partial
equilibrium for the single-product firm, has adequate sufficiency to handle in
a modest way questions of product-line policy, new-product pricing, and the
exploitation of the product life cycle. Even
innovation can be treated in terms of competitive strategy - but not if one confuses
monopolistic with imperfect competition. B. R. Williams’ complaint against economists’
treatment of competitive pressure is justified, but his
1. E. H. Chamberlin,
The Theory of Monopolistic Competition (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1933), p. 113.
2. Robertson, ibid.
3. Chamberlin,
op. cit., p. 214.
877
explanation
is not quite right. “Whether, and in what
way, competition stimulates... innovation,” writes Williams:
is a problem foreign to static theory, though in fact
static theory has exercised a very strong influence on economists’ approach to
dynamic problems. Thus, examples of
product differentiation are generally drawn from the market for consumer goods
and stress brand differences in fields like cereals and cosmetics. When, however, we take examples such as
aircraft engines, electronics, man-made fibres, and
pharmaceuticals, we face the significant possibility that product
differentiations may not be ‘market imperfections’ in the static sense, but an
inevitable part of the process of man-made innovations required for the
efficient pursuit of economic growth. [1]
Of course
static theory is strictly inconsistent with change of any kind, even the
introduction of a different packet for an unchanged product. But once we reject the hobgoblin of
consistency, [2] we find comparative statics a useful method of handling change. The cause of the trouble is less the static
formulation of the models than the assumption of imperfect competition theory
that product differentiation produces waste, not progress. Novelty is undesirable because it impedes
mass-production. Monopolistic competition,
on the other hand, does allow us to ask whether mass-production may be
undesirable because it impedes novelty.
If
monopolistic competition is both so different and in some ways so superior to
imperfect competition, why have the two been treated as so nearly synonymous? Part of the explanation, as given before, is
that the central analysis appeared so similar that almost everyone assumed the
theories to be similar also. It is still
necessary to explain why the assimilated theory looks so distinctly Robinsonian; but that is easy. The theory of value was apparently in a state
of crisis, and Mrs. Robinson’s book appeared as the culmination of a painful
and difficult struggle to resolve it, in which many of the keenest economic
minds had publicly engaged. The urgency
and difficulty of that struggle made impossible the perception of Chamberlin’s work in any other way than as a solution to
the crisis. Its entirely different
origins, being neither a common concern nor well-publicised,
aroused no interest whatsoever. The
saddest part of this paradox is that, had there been no crisis, Chamberlin’s book would have received far less attention,
because it would have met no apparent need. The tragedy of Chamberlin’s
professional life is that if he had not spent so much of his time and energy
protesting the distinctiveness of his theory, he would probably have spent that
time and energy protesting its importance.
1. B. R. Williams, Technology,
Investment and Growth (London: Chapman & Hall, 1967), p. 83.
2. “A foolish consistency is the
hobgoblin of little minds, adored by little statesmen and philosophers and
divines.” R. W. Emerson, Essays.
878
By setting
out to show that “the analysis of the output and price of a single commodity
can be conducted by a technique based upon the study of individual decisions,” [1] Mrs. Robinson for the first time appeared to
bring decision-making by the competitive firm within the ambit of empirical
economic research. That the definition
of such an important new field failed to precipitate a flood of investigations,
as one would expect in the experimental sciences, was probably largely due to
the feeling that research was unnecessary since facts could apparently be
deduced from purely geometrical arguments. There certainly do not seem to have been any
immediate doubts that the new theory offered an adequate description - or
prescription: it was not always clear which - of actual business behaviour. Thus the
report of the first serious investigation (the Oxford inquiry) [2] that businesses did not behave in this way
inevitably caused some consternation; the paradigm has been in a kind of crisis
ever since.
Many typical
features of a paradigm crisis have been visible. There has been no general agreement on the
terms of reference for the debate, nor indeed on the precise scope of paradigm
under attack. Nor has the attack been
well co-ordinated: P. W. S. Andrews, the only
economist to develop both a full-scale critique and an alternative paradigm,
published the two halves of his argument fifteen years apart, and in the wrong
sequence for maximum effect. [3] On
the opposing side, many of the successful revolutionaries, quite properly,
turned conservative to protect the newly-established paradigm; and their defence owed little to empirical evidence about firms’
pricing behaviour.
Such
disregard for empirical evidence, it was argued earlier, is generally
appropriate in a conflict of paradigms; and it is particularly appropriate in
this instance. For Mrs. Robinson’s
theory was based not, as she claimed, on “the study of individual decisions,”
but on the conditions of individual equilibrium, just as perfect competition
had been; and both perfect and imperfect competition are empty of predictions
about the ways in which firms actually fix prices. Andrews saw more clearly than most that the
dispute turned on questions not of behaviour but of
structure: whether the model should assume atomistic competition or oligopoly,
and whether it should be formulated in terms of equilibrium. Part of Andrews’ critique offers a remarkable
parallel to Sraffa’s earlier argument; whereas Sraffa had shown that a strict interpretation of the
conditions of long-period static partial equilibrium virtually excluded
increasing costs for the individual firm. Andrews now argued that these conditions also
excluded falling demand
1. J. Robinson, The Economics of Imperfect Competition (London:
Macmillan, 1933), p. 15.
2. R. L. Hall and C. J. Hitch,
“Price Theory and Business Behaviour,” Oxford
Economic Papers, No. 2, 1939.
3. P. W. S.
Andrews, Manufacturing Business (London: Macmillan, 1949), and On
Competition in Economic Theory (London: Macmillan, 1964).
curves
for the individual firm. [1] Thus
we reach the final condemnation of long-period static partial equilibrium: it
is incompatible first, with perfect competition, second, with real-world
phenomena, and finally, even with itself.
This
rejection of equilibrium theory did not worry Andrews, who had previously
developed an alternative paradigm, in which a “steady state” of uniform prices
is determined by competition within an industry, and each firm’s market share
depends on dynamic considerations of goodwill; but, as he acknowledged, it
worried other people. [2] For it is the concept of equilibrium which is
at the heart of the crisis; and the abandonment of equilibrium is a much more
fundamental change than that implied by the creation of the theory of the firm,
which was developed, in accordance with Sraffa’s
advice, precisely in order to preserve the static equilibrium method of
analysis. Micro-economists need a theory
of the firm; and for some purposes the marginalist
equilibrium theory is the best theory we have.
How, then, is
the paradigm defended? Andrews’
critique, though in its own terms irrefutable, is unacceptable; it has
therefore apparently been ignored. Perhaps economists have learned to be less impressed
by revelations of inconsistency in their theoretical assumptions, and accept
that Andrews’ criticisms are no more valid than were Sraffa’s.
Expositions and explanations of business
behaviour which conflict with micro-equilibrium
theory, however, have met with vigorous onslaughts, in which the terms of the
argument, as is usual in controversies over paradigms, have been defined in a
way that comes near to ensuring success. Equilibrium theory is justified by assuming
its validity. Rationality is equated
with profit maximisation, which in static equilibrium
implies mathematically the equality of marginal cost and marginal revenue;
therefore any business observed violating the theory is behaving irrationally,
and any alternative theory must assume irrationality, which, as we all know,
makes theorising impossible - unless, of course, it
be the consumer irrationality which is the not-quite-explicit basis of
imperfect competition. Even Cohen and Cyert, who might be expected to be particularly sensitive
to this issue, discuss decision-making by marginal analysis as if this were synonymous
with rationality. [3] Andrews’ own theory has inevitably come in for
particularly harsh treatment, and it has unfortunately been too easy to assume
that the obscurity of his style reflects confusion in his thought; but the
standard accusation that he is rejecting profit-maximisation,
rather than equilibrium (which persists even in Silberston’s
recent survey) [4] simply indicates the
confusion of his critics.
Nevertheless,
some progress has been made. The
exercise of construing reported business behaviour in
terms of accepted theory has revealed much
1 Andrews, On Competition, pp. 73-80.
2 Andrews, op. cit., pp. 90-93.
3. K.J. Cohen & R. M. Cyert, Theory of the Firm (New Jersey:
Prentice-Hall, 1965), Chapter 3.
4. A. Silberston,
“Surveys of Applied Economics: Price Behaviour of
Firms,” Economic Journal, September,
1970. Professor Andrews’ death this year has deprived the profession of a
widely-underrated, because misunderstood, economist.
880
more
clearly than before the level of abstraction involved in that theory. One result is that micro-economists now have a
somewhat better appreciation of the nature of their subject. Another is that the partial withdrawal of
pretensions to describe the processes of decision-making by the use of the
theory of the firm has facilitated the emergence of a very different paradigm
for that purpose.
The logical
justification for a separate paradigm of organisational
decision-making was clearly set out for any one to see in Coase’s
article “The Nature of the Firm.” [1] This article was
presented as a skilful and wholly satisfying resolution of a very awkward
anomaly in the theory of the firm - its failure, until that time, to account
for the existence of firms at all in a specialised
exchange economy. In explaining the
allocation of economic decision-making between the market and a directing
authority by applying marginal analysis to the cost of each kind of decision-process,
Coase significantly reinforced the marginalist paradigm. But in basing his argument on the premise that
decision-making within firms was different from decisions in the market, he
excluded any detailed study of decision-making within firms from the fields of
application of that paradigm. The theory
of the firm might still be used as a highly-abstract model for predicting the
overall results of the decisions of individual firms; but since bringing a
decision within a firm implied, by definition, a rejection of the market mechanism,
it now had a very limited sufficiency as a working model of the decision-making
process.
The failure
to notice this obvious implication of Coase’s work
has resulted in much unnecessary expenditure of ink, time and temper. But though it may be thought unfortunate, it
is not at all surprising that the article should be interpreted solely in terms
of the paradigm which it employed, and that a new paradigm of business behaviour should have been created with small help from
economists. That paradigm emerged
primarily from concern with two organisational
problems. On the one hand there was the
question of organisational relationships, which was
attracting increasing attention (primarily in the United States) from some
psychologists and sociologists. On the
other hand there was the need (implied in Coase’s
analysis) for selective attention to problems and for economy in the search for
solutions, which long remained the pragmatic concern of accountants
establishing management control systems.
At first
quite distinct, gradually these two areas of inquiry began to overlap, as
increasing attention was given to behavioural aspects
of control systems, and the inter-relationships of management structure and
manage-
1. R. H. Coase, “The Nature
of the Firm,” Economica, N S 1937;
reprinted in Readings in Price Theory, pp. 331-51.
ment perception were more deeply explored. The major credit for evolving a new paradigm
of organisational decision-making must go to H. A.
Simon; and perhaps Simon’s critical contribution was the introduction of the
concepts of limited knowledge and bounded rationality into his explanation of organisational cohesion, which made the identification of
occasions for decision as crucial for him as for the designers of control
systems. The new paradigm was introduced
to economics by the work of Cyert and March.
Yet its
impact has been very slight. To anyone
accepting the argument hitherto, this should not be surprising. The failure to visualise
economics explicitly as a systems study, and the dominance of market paradigms,
conditioned economists to think of the firm as a basic element rather than as
an economic system worthy of study in its own right. The widespread contempt exhibited by
economists for accounting (the more scandalous for not being recognised as a scandal) prevented them from appreciating
either the real difficulties or the practical importance of management control.
Above all, the criteria employed in the
existing paradigm were inevitably used in judging between it and the new; and
on those criteria behavioural theory does rather
badly. It has no answer to the questions
of efficiency or stability as those questions are traditionally posed. It has no use for traditional basic concepts: optimisation has no usable meaning; economists’ heavy
investment in calculus becomes redundant; equilibrium is not defined; and there
are no general analytical solutions.
But the
characteristics of one paradigm should not be used as the criteria by which a
rival is judged. It is more helpful to
compare the abstractions and the methods of analysis which are legitimised by each, the kinds of answer which each can
give, and the questions which each permits to be asked. The critical distinction, which is a condition
of all the others, is that between the definition of positions of rest and the specification
of an ongoing process. (This is very
like the distinction which Leijonhufvud regards as
critical to an understanding of Keynes’ thought.) [1] As a consequence, instead
of a defined goal, we have a defined origin. Thus, for example, a firm’s history and
financial position become elements of the analysis, whereas in
micro-equilibrium theory they are quite properly excluded as irrelevant. (Silberston’s criticism
of standard theories of the firm on this score is misplaced.) [2]
Such a shift
of focus, from destination to origin, has been a central feature of some major
paradigm changes in other fields. It
was, indeed, precisely such a shift, in the study of falling bodies, which gave
rise to the concept of
1. Axel Leijonhufvud,
Keynes and the Classics (London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 1969),
p. 29.
2.
Silberston, op. cit., p. 525.
882
instantaneous, as distinct from
average, speed, [1] and thus in due course
led to the development of differential calculus, which the equivalent shift in
the theory of the firm now threatens to dethrone. It was precisely such a shift in the study of
evolution which made Darwin’s ideas so disturbing; and it is apparently this
absence of finality which most disturbs some critics of behavioural
theory - not surprisingly, because it leaves us exposed forever to the “mystery
and doubt” from which, as Shackle observes, we seek protection in theory. [2]
But exposure
brings greater freedom. A process with
no definable end does not lend itself to optimisation
techniques of analysis, and so there is no pressure to build only optimising models. Instead,
therefore, of being confined to studying the response of a system to changes in
its parameters, one can develop a model in which these parameters become
variables, and which therefore may initiate the changes to which it later
responds. There is no need for the
system to be dominated by negative feedback, as must necessarily be assumed - albeit
unconsciously - in equilibrium models: the “cobweb theorem,” for instance, so
anomalous in traditional micro-theory, fits easily into this type of analysis.
Another gain
of freedom is in the handling of uncertainty. It is now possible to admit that in our world
uncertainty is often a euphemism for ignorance, which cannot often be
adequately represented by the use of certainty equivalents. It is the unknown, rather than the uncertain,
which leads to the behaviour that Cyert
and March categorise as uncertainty-avoidance, [3] and to the emphasis on flexibility as an
objective in corporate strategy. [4] It is
the unknown, rather than the uncertain, which makes satisficing
rational. Satisficing
is not equivalent to what Baumol and Quant call
“optimally imperfect decision-making,” [5]
not because it is “constrained maximisation with only
constraints and no maximisation,” [6] but because it is embedded in a paradigm in
which optimality has no definable meaning. Vickers’ model of long-run profit-maximisation, for example, relies on a series of conceptual
production, investment and financing plans, of a precision which is irrational
(which does not mean non-optimal) within the assumptions of the behavioural paradigm. [7]
Where there
is neither finality nor optimality, there can hardly be general determinate
solutions. It is the abandonment of the
search for such solutions
1. Kuhn, op. cit., pp.
123-4.
2. Shackle, op. cit., pp.
288-9.
3. Cyert
and March, op. cit., pp. 118—20.
4. H. I. Ansoff,
Corporate Strategy (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1965), Chapter 4.
5. “which requires that the
marginal cost of additional information gathering or more refined calculation
be equal to its marginal (expected) gross yield.” W. J. Baumol and R.
E. Quant, “Rules of Thumb and Optimally Imperfect Decisions,” American
Economic Review, March 1964, p. 23.
6. Ibid., p. 24.
7. D. Vickers, The Theory of the Firm: Production, Capital and Finance (New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1968).
that
permits the use of behavioural variables in the way
which gives behavioural theory its name. A fully determinate solution requires the behaviour, at least of relevant aggregates, to be fully
constrained by the system. But if
constraints are obligatory, objectives are optional, and the dilemma of
micro-equilibrium theory is to reconcile the element of choice in the assumptions
with the absence of choice in the results. This dilemma is brilliantly resolved in the
theory of perfect competition, which combines completely independent decisions
into a fully-determined system. Although
normally employed in the exposition, the assumption of profit maximisation is redundant in this theory, at least in the
long-run version: the behavioural assumptions are
almost irrelevant, as a wide range of plausible assumptions all lead to the
same result. Every objective turns out
to be a constraint. The theory of
imperfect competition with normal profits shares this highly desirable
attribute; thus as long as free entry can be assumed, the behaviour
of firms cannot affect the long-run equilibrium solution, and is not therefore
a sensible subject for research. Within
these limits, pricing behaviour is irrelevant to
price theory. This essential point is
thoroughly obscured in Silberston’s survey - not
least effectively in its title.
The
introduction of elements of monopoly destroys this happy conjuncture, for, in
the absence of a perfect capital market and effective shareholder control of
management, monopoly profits represent an area of discretion. Profit-maximisation
does now become a necessary assumption for the unique determination of price
and output; but for precisely the same reason, it is not the inevitable
assumption: Baumol [1]
and Williamson [2] have proferred plausible alternatives. If product differentiation is also allowed,
one has a conceptual framework with very few general properties, but
potentially rich in highly-specific hypotheses: in short, what economists call
an empty model.
It does not,
however, follow that elements of monopoly are necessary to behavioural
theory, as seems to be generally believed (even by Cyert
and March). [3] There
is no reason why behavioural theory should not be
applied to a firm which is a determined profit-seeker in a highly-competitive
industry; it is not another version of monopoly or oligopoly theory, but a
different paradigm, embodying a much lower degree of abstraction. Let us take three of the features which are
normally regarded as evidence of some degree of monopoly. First, no organisation
which delegates decision-making can avoid multiple objectives; and even if its
objective function is well-defined, to distribute its components among managers
in such a way as to produce organisationally-optimal
decisions is hardly conceivable. Second,
the need to allocate responsibility for sub-objectives, together with partial
ignorance, makes the definition of objectives in terms of target levels,
1 W. J. Baumol, Business Behaviour,
Value and Growth (New York: Macmillan, 1959).
2. 0. E. Williamson, The Economics of Discretionary Behaviour:
Managerial Objectives in a Theory of the Firm (Chicago: Markham Publishing
Co., 1967).
3.
E.g., Silberston, op. cit., p. 536.
884
which
are more often derived from experience than from optimising
procedures, a rational policy. Third,
there are many items of “managed costs,” which, by definition, represent an
area of discretion, but which also enter as arguments into the profit function
in ways which are often very poorly understood. In an equilibrium model, expenditures on such
items as advertising, research, management training and management information
and control systems, would appear as elements of long-run cost, each with an
appropriate pay-off (no doubt including a stochastic term); but if neither
equilibrium nor pay-offs can be specified, then these costs are most plausibly
treated as discretionary, even apparently slack, payments: they are certainly
likely to be cut in a cash squeeze - which might be non-optimal behaviour, if optimal behaviour
could be defined.
The purpose
of the previous section has been to demonstrate how different is the behavioural paradigm from
any of the micro-equilibrium paradigms discussed earlier. It was not intended to demonstrate its
superiority - indeed an important part of the argument of this paper has been
that it is hard to find criteria for judging between paradigms that are not
products of the paradigms themselves: rationality for example, apparently so
objective, is in fact very heavily paradigm-dependent. Indeed, observant readers will have noticed
that, like Kuhn’s view of scientific progress, the development of the theory of
the firm, as presented in this article, falls entirely within the behavioural paradigm: problemistic
search is evoked by a disparity between aspiration and the apparent performance
of existing theories, and neither equilibrium nor optimality have any part to
play in explaining the course of events.
If the new
paradigm were to replace the old, much would be lost. But if it were to be finally rejected by
economists, perhaps even more would be lost. For there are many areas of interest and
issues of public policy in which the new has the advantage - for example, in
questions of efficiency in the popular sense, and in analysing
the character and the timing of responses to new situations (such as the
introduction of S.E.T.). Fortunately,
this is not, as it has sometimes been presented, a conflict for the title of
the theory of the firm. For the most
part, these paradigms operate at different system levels: once the effort has
been made to view both of them with equal bias, there is nothing but an
excessive and unscientific regard for consistency to prevent both being used,
either separately or together as convenient, until the emergence of a new
crisis and the rise of a new challenger. Perhaps next time, given a rather better
appreciation of what is happening, the process will be rather less wasteful of
time and energy; though it can never be either easy or comfortable.
BRIAN J. LOASBY
University of Stirling.
885