The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Edwin T. Layton
Science as a Form of Action:
The Role of the Engineering Sciences
Technology & Culture, 29 (1
January 1988, 82-97
Near the outset Michael
Fores tells us that his “Transformations and the Myth of ‘Engineering Science’”
is a philosophical paper (p. 64). Though
it is a strange philosophy, there is method in his animad-versions. The most fundamental assumption of Fores’s
philosophy is that there is only one valid form of cognition, empiricism. He believes that “human activity is constrained
to be continuingly empirical” (p. 81). This
leads him to see the world in terms of a division between “empiricism” versus
“science.” But at the heart of Fores’s
“empirical” philosophy there is a glaring contradiction. His own methodology is not, in fact, empirical
at all. He totally rejects the idea that
science can influence the way engineers do technology, asking “How can anyone
recognize a ‘scientific’ form of technical work?” (p. 67). I and the historians of technology Fores
associates with me have discussed numerous examples of precisely this. [1] Fores dismisses all this scholarship without
recourse to empirical facts; his procedure is to label such works as “myth” or
“magic.” He does not in a single case
show that we have got our facts wrong or that the data are contradicted by
better-established facts. Indeed, his
entire article is cast on a very abstract “philosophical” level that ignores or
is vague concerning the empirical realities it purportedly deals with.
The most striking example
of Fores’s rejection of empirical methods is his arbitrary classification of
much (possibly all) scientific theory as magic. Humans, he claims, find uncertainty difficult
to bear. He asserts that “magic is
indeed invoked whenever there is thought to be a good deal of risk involved”
(p. 80). He provides no evidence for
this but relies on Bronislaw Malinowski’s famous observations of the magical
practices of the Trobriand Islanders.
DR. LAYTON is professor of the history of technology
in the Department of Mechanical Engineering at the University of Minnesota.
1. See the list in Fores, n. 4. Elsewhere
he extends the list to others, including Donald Cardwell, David Channell, Carlo
Cipolla, Edward Constant, Eda Kranakis, A. E. Musson, Eric Robinson, Abbott P.
Usher, and Walter Vincenti. I feel
honored to be placed in such company.
82
Malinowski concluded that magic employs theory and has
certain similarities to science. [2] Fores then
makes a great conceptual leap: he turns Malinowski on his head and concludes
that the use of such concepts as “science,” “theory,” or “law” in a
technological context amounts to magic - a totemistic worship of science (p.
81). Indeed, he comes close to
repudiating science both as a form of action and as a form of cognition. He denies that there can ever be such a thing
as a “scientific activity” (p. 78). He
reduces the concept of “law of nature” to the weakest sort of metaphor. In dealing with Newton, he asserts: “Take
Newton’s laws of motion. The last thing
that inert bodies in motion need, to help them decide how to act, is the
panoply of articulated ‘law,’ with its parliaments, law schools, and juries”
(p. 78). Fores misrepresents
Malinowski’s position. Malinowski
concluded that magic is a pseudoscience, that magic and science may be easily
distinguished because “the spurious character of this pseudo-science is not
hard to detect.” The difference,
according to Malinowski, was that “The theories of knowledge are dictated by
logic, those of magic by the association of ideas under the influence of
desire.” [3]
I believe that Fores’s own
philosophy will not pass Malinowski’s test. His identification of scientific and
technological theory with magic is based on his wish to discredit science and
his association of it with magic. But
wish and association are not proof except in magic. Fores rejects many works of scholarship
without even a token effort to base his dismissals on empirical facts. He never cites a specific scientific theory or
law whose use constitutes magic. His reasoning
is therefore not empirical, except in name. If we apply Malinowski’s test to Fores’s
article, it would be classified as “pseudo-science” and “magic.” Clearly, Fores’s “empiricism” is a
metaphysical principle, not an epistemology.
I believe that the most
fundamental issue raised by Fores’s article is scholarship. The historians attacked by him are scholars
who practice a demanding empirical discipline. He shows no respect for empirical facts, nor
does he employ reason except in the most “intolerant” and “disorderly” manner. He does not treat evidence in a disciplined,
critical manner. His position depends
almost entirely on purely arbitrary assertion, unsupported by specific references
to the “observable world” (p. 65). Thus
he argues (in an imaginary confrontation of Newton with modern scholars) that:
2. Bronjslaw Malinowskj, Magic, Science and Religion (Garden
City, N.Y.: Anchor, 1954), pp. 79-87.
3. Ibid., p. 87.
“Newton is sure that he did not develop any
‘scientific method’ for all time. Nor
did he use ‘the mechanical philosophy,’ which implies the construction of a
particular type of record, except for a particular purpose - trying to make
sense of observations about the motion of inert bodies… (p. 79). I believe the “for all time” is an evasion. Eternal Truth is not the issue. The crucial question is whether there are valid
scientific methods that can be taught and employed in technology. Fores grants “methods” but apparently feels
these are invalid “in the absence of any single statement for specialist activity
of any type” (p. 71).
There are innumerable
statements concerning various specialist disciplines, particularly for
engineering. Though Fores is characteristically
vague, the literature on engineering work and “specialist activity” of all
sorts is so vast that it is difficult to imagine a topic that has been neglected.
For example, there is a useful survey by
Roger Mayne and Stephen Margolis entitled Introduction to Engineering. Interestingly enough, it contains a short
section on engineering science. [4]
Fores’s position requires
that he reject the idea that there are valid scientific methods that can be
taught. If he cannot do this, then it is
simply nonsense to claim (as he does) that engineers cannot be taught
scientific methods and cannot bring these scientific methods to the practice of
their profession, making science the model for a form of action. Fores then must argue that there is no genuine
method for doing science: “... it would be a miracle if there were an
identifiable, stereotypical, ‘scientific’ mode of human working. And indeed, for all the discussion of the
‘rationality of science,’ ‘induction,’ ‘scientific method,’ and so on set up to
provide some type of ‘law’ or ‘governing principle’ for successful scientists
to use, there has no more been a known, articulated ‘method for doing science’
than there has been an identifiable ‘cooking method’” (p. 70).
This is very puzzling
coming from an avowed empiricist. His denial
of an “identifiable” method of cooking provides a remarkable example of Fores’s
counterfactual “empiricism.” The
bookstores are filled with cookbooks that teach readers how to cook. And there are many other vehicles for teaching
cooking methods: classes, television programs, and newspaper columns, not to
mention the traditional education of children by their parents. Fores’s claim is simply nonsense. His “identifiable” is evidently synonymous
with “identifiable as a part of my metaphysical system.”
4. Roger Mayne and Stephen Margolis, Introduction
to Engineering (New York, 1982), pp. 20-21.
84
Fores’s rejection of the
possibility of teaching scientific methods (particularly to engineers) is as
puzzling as his denial of the existence of cooking methods. There are many books written by scientists and
by engineers for the use of students and practitioners in engineering which
teach scientific methods. Most of these
are concerned with specific experimental or theoretical methods - photoelastic
stress analysis, for example. But there
are certainly a number of useful general books on the design of experiments intended
for engineers. [5] The author of one of
the most widely used of these books, E. M. Bartee, comments that “the effective
planning of engineering experiments” combines the application “of the scientific
method and the methodology of engineering design.” [6] For someone with an engineering training to
ignore the large body of literature on teaching scientific methods to engineers
is truly astonishing. This indicates
that Fores’s own methods are not empirical but constitute the exposition of a
purely metaphysical “empiricism” with a highly problematic relation to the real
world of engineering practice.
Fores also ignores a large
body of empirical historical studies that contradict his thesis that technology
was not transformed under the influence of science. Fores is, I suspect, quite well aware of the
evidence that Watt, Smeaton, Charles de Borda, and many other engineers used
experiments, and that these experiments drew some inspiration from science. I believe that Fores is also aware that Watt
and other engineers also developed generalizations based on experiments (i.e.,
they developed theories). [7] But he
rejects the idea that the work of engineers such as Watt produced a scientific
transformation of technology.
In Fores’s world, how do we
account for the work of Sadi Carnot? He
was one of the founders of thermodynamics, but his analysis depended on the
existence of steam engines, notably Watt’s, in which the fall in temperature from
source to sink was made mani-
5. K. A. Brownless, Statistical Theory and
Methodology in Science and Engineering (New York, 1960), represents one
example of many; there are also old classics such as Sir Ronald A. Fisher, The
Design of Experiments (New York: Hafner ed., 1960).
6. E. M. Bartee, Engineering Experimental Design
Fundamentals (Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1968), p. vii.
7. For example, see Donald S. L. Cardwell, From Watt to Clausius: The
Rise of Thermodynamics in the Early Industrial Age (Ithaca, N.Y., 1971),
and Cardwell, “Some Factors in the Early Development of the Concepts of Power,
Work, and Energy,” British Journal of the History of Science 3 (1966-67):
209-24. (Fores’s rejection of Cardwell
is in his n. 60.) On the development of
a science for waterpower, see also Terry S. Reynolds, Stronger than a
Hundred Men (Baltimore, 1983), pp. 196-265, as well as Reynolds, “Scientific
Influences on Technology: The Case of the Overshot Waterwheel, 1752_1754,” Technology
and Culture 20 (April 1979): 270-95.
fest. Carnot’s
work was almost purely theoretical. Yet
he was an engineer and his theory was aimed at determining the limits of efficiency
of heat engines, a classical engineering problem. Carnot’s ideal cycle was eventually
incorporated in a body of theoretical and experimental knowledge about heat engines,
sometimes called “engineering thermodynamics.” This body of knowledge has come in time to
influence the design of all manner of heat engines. Fores’s philosophy makes it much more
difficult to understand facts such as these; it is not congruent with the realities
of engineering or its history.
I do not pretend to know
what Fores would do with the work of Kelvin, Maxwell, and similar figures whose
scientific theories can be shown to have influenced technological activity by
way of such figures as Oliver Heaviside, George Campbell, and Charles P. Steinmetz.
[8] But if his metaphysical system can
absorb Newton’s mathematical physics, the second law of thermodynamics, and
even Levi-Strauss’s theory of totemism as properly empirical (p. 66), then it
should be able to properly sanitize even these figures and the scientific and
technological events with which they were connected. In this sense Fores is not disputing facts. His battle is one of words and metaphysical
categories, used in an arbitrary and subjective manner. As such his metaphysical system lies outside
the purview of any scholarly discipline, and particularly an empirical
discipline such as history of technology.
In Fores’s universe there
is a very fundamental dichotomy between rationalists and empiricists. He sees it as a sort of “sheep” and “goats”
division. Neither of these fundamental
categories is clearly defined. In the
case of me and my former student, David Channell, Fores imagines that the changes
we discuss fit into his simplistic dichotomy of “empiricism” versus “science.” In particular he imagines that: “They [Layton
and Channell] were both broadly in accord with Rankine’s isolation of two
separable modes of technical working, the first being ‘empirical... purely and
simply practical’ and the second being ‘scientific’” (p. 64). He returns at several points to this dichotomy
and his conviction that I believe that there was a simple change from
“empirical” to “scientific.”
There is ample evidence in
the papers of mine analyzed by Fores that I do not accept his simplistic
dichotomization of reality into an
8. James E. Brittain, “The Introduction of the Loading
Coil: George A. Campbell and Michael I. Pupin,” Technology and Culture 11
(January 1970): 36-57, and Ronald R. Kline, “Charles P. Steinmetz and the
Development of Electrical Engineering Science” (Ph.D. diss., University of
Wisconsin, 1983).
86
“empirical” before and an exclusively rational or
“scientific” after. I have argued a more
complex position: that empiricism and rationalism have been continuing elements
in a fruitful interaction of science and technology, though both the form and
their relative roles in science and technology have evolved over time. Fores never cites any evidence that I accept a
simple empirical/scientific dichotomy. At
some point after putting me into his two categories, he evidently became aware
of my explicit rejection of at least one of them, a rationalist “after” state
for engineering. He quotes me in another
context as saying, “to date, the complexities of [engineering] practice continue
to transcend theory” (p. 73). Fores was
evidently most reluctant to abandon the categories into which he feels
(apparently a priori) that I must fit. But
he tacitly reduced his claim to an “empirical” “before,” as in his statement,
“there is no good evidence to indicate that Layton’s ‘before’ mode is different
from that outlined by Channell as being ‘practical’ and ‘empirical’” (p. 77). Fores’s reference note, presumably his only
supporting evidence for this claim, is the statement in his note 59: “Channell
has acknowledged ‘helpful assistance’ from Layton at the beginning of his
article” (p. 77).
Fores has, however, ignored
an extensive statement by me in which I explicitly rejected his simplistic
“empiricism” as the “before” situation. He
claims that there is no good evidence for this, yet he cites the work in
question, my article “Technology as Knowledge,” three times in his paper. [9] In this article I argued that, “technology has
relied on rational principles and theoretical constructs since at least
classical antiquity. In more recent
times, these rational elements have been transformed into systematic bodies of
thought, that is, they have become sciences in some sense.” [10] I continue this line at some length, showing
that Alexandre Koyré had a somewhat similar view. I concluded with the statement that “earlier
craft rules and modern engineering science, however different, form a continuum.”
[11] The sort of technological rules I had in mind
for the earlier era were, for example, similar to the quasi-scientific methods
of medieval masons as reconstructed by Robert Mark and others. [12] Another familiar example of a rational, quasi-scientific
element in ear-
9. Layton, “Technology as Knowledge,” Technology and Culture 15
(January 1974):31-41. Fores’s citations
are in his notes 4, 5, and 8.
10. Layton, “Technology as Knowledge,” p. 39.
11. Ibid, p. 40.
12. Robert Mark, Experiments in Gothic Structure (Cambridge,
Mass., 1982), pp. 56, 119. See also
James S. Ackerman, “Ars Sine Scientia Nihil Est: Gothic Theory of Architecture
at the Cathedral of Milan,” Art Bulletin 26 (1949): 84-111.
lier technology would be the derivation of the
catapult rule by Hellenistic engineers. [13]
The existence of a
prototypical scientific rationality in technology has been demonstrated for the
Renaissance. Alexander Keller has shown
that Renaissance engineers developed mathematical theories to describe machines
and engineering. There is a strong implication
that Keller believes that the prior mathematization of engineering may have
influenced the subsequent development of mathematical descriptions of nature by
scientists from Galileo onward. [14] Thomas Settle
has shown that Ostilio Ricci, besides teaching geometry to Galileo, sometimes
practiced engineering, and he made a personal copy of Leon Battista Alberti’s Ludi
Matematici. It is quite likely that
it was Ricci who introduced Galileo to Alberti’s work, which appears to have
had a significant influence on Galileo’s experimental methods. [15] There are important ways in which the
scientific methods developed by Galileo and his successors built on prior
experimental and theoretical methods developed by engineers, such as Leonardo
da Vinci. [16]
There is much evidence that
the Scientific Revolution drew heavily from technology. This evidence needs a critical review. [17] A full exposition of this complex problem
would be out of place here. I have advocated
an interactive model of the relations of science and technology. I believe that technology made important
contributions to the methodologies of science prior to the Scientific
Revolution, just as technology has made extensive borrowings of methodology
since that time as part of a cycle in the two-way interactions between these
two great, symbiotically linked human agencies.
13. Barton C. Hacker, “Greek Catapults and Catapult Technology: Science,
Technology, and War in the Ancient World,” Technology and Culture 9
(January 1968): 34-50. See also Walter
G. Vincenti, “The Air-Propeller Tests of W. F. Durand and E. P. Lesley: A Case
Study in Technological Methodology,” Technology and Culture 20 (October
1979): 714.
14. Alex Keller, “Mathematicians, Mechanics and Experimental Machines in
Northern Italy in the Sixteenth Century,” in The Emergence of Science in
Western Europe, ed. M. P. Crossland (London, 1975), pp. 15-34, and “Pneumatics,
Automata and the Vacuum in the Work of Giambattista Aleoui,” British Journal
for the History of Science 3 (1967): 338-47. An example of “applied science” was described
by Keller in “Archimedean Hydrostatic Theorems and Salvage Operations in
16th-Century Venice,” Technology and Culture 12 (October 1971): 602-17.
15. Thomas B. Settle, “Ostilio Ricci, a Bridge between Alberti and
Galileo,” XII Congres d’Histoire des Sciences: Actes (Paris, 1968): 121-26.
See also Arnaldo Masotti, “Ostilio
Ricci,” Dictionary of Scientific Biography, 11: 405-6.
16. See, e.g., the suggestive article by Ladislao Reti, “II moto del
prioietti e del pendolo secondo Leonardo e Galileo,” Le Machine 1
(December 1968): 63-89.
17. Lynn White, jr., “Pumps and Pendula: Galileo and Technology,” in
Carlo L. Golino, ed., Galileo Reappraised (Berkeley and Los Angeles,
1966), pp. 96-110.
88
However, I do not think
that the use of the terms “empirical” and “scientific” to characterize two
historical epochs in technology is such a grave error as Fores would have us
believe. The systematic use of
scientific methods and results is a characteristic of much modern engineering. One has only to look at such fields as
transistors, integrated circuits, and lasers. [18] The empirical/scientific categories have
become conventional shorthand to distinguish rather complex changes. This is analogous to the term “Neolithic” to
describe a rather complex set of social changes, of which the most important
was not polished stone tools but rather the invention of agriculture. The use of a conventional shorthand is not
dangerous as long as we remember that it is only a useful label. This terminology does not necessarily carry
the metaphysical freight Fores imputes to it.
The inadequacies of these terms have caused me to avoid them, though I
am surprised that I did not slip into the common usage. It is very convenient, and we lack good,
short alternatives.
Fores often quotes me out
of context and distorts the meaning of what I have said. A particularly offensive example appears at
the very outset, where he presents a quote from me as an epigraph for his
paper. The quote is “obviously, much of
the impetus to modern engineering has... come from science.” The actual passage is part of a section in
which I argue that design is more fundamental to engineering than is science. This, then, presents a dilemma since American
engineers adopted a self-image of themselves as scientists (or applied
scientists); they have not accepted the self-image of “designer.” The quoted sentence then follows; the
“obviously” modifies the preceding reference to self-image, not the later
reference to the role of science in the development of engineering. If someone adopts a seemingly inappropriate
self-identification (say, “citizen of the world” where a national
identification might be expected) then the fact that he or she really is a
citizen of the world in some sense (e.g., as an employee of the United Nations)
is at least a partial explanation. Fores
in quoting my sentence left out the critical word “indeed” (where he duly
inserted three dots) that told the reader that the reference was to the
preceding discussion of self-image.
I do assume that science
has had an important influence on modern engineering, but I do not assume that
this is obvious. As I have pointed out
on many occasions, engineering achievements cannot,
18. Robert M. Warner, Jr., and B. L. Grung, Transistors. Fundamentals
for the Integrated-Circuit Engineer (New York, 1983), pp. 1-91, is particularly
useful as a historical survey because of Warner’s use of his recollections as a
participant in many of the events described. For the laser, the interplay of science and
engineering has been neatly outlined by Joan Lisa Bromberg, “Engineering
Knowledge in the Laser Field,” Technology and Culture 27 (October 1986):
798-818.
in general, be explained by an “applied science”
theory, and in many cases the influence of science has been subtle and
indirect; science has, for example, influenced the experimental and theoretical
methods employed by engineers, and, perhaps most profoundly, the institutional
structure and values of the engineering profession. [19] In general, the quote
of me is part of a statement that engineering is fundamentally design. [20]
That quote therefore has a
very different meaning than the one Fores imputes to it. His quotation implies that my statement is a
manifesto for the supremacy of science in shaping technology, and that this
position is “obvious” (e.g., p. 65). This is in fact a gross distortion of what I
said. Scholarship, as a disciplined
effort to discover the facts and interpret them correctly by nonsubjective
criteria, is evidently alien to Fores’s methodology.
Fores does raise one
fundamental point that deserves further discussion. This is his criticism of comments by me that
discuss the engineering sciences in terms of “ends” and “goals.” [21] Fores attacks my use of the word
“teleological” (p. 69). The context was
my contrast between the empirical and goal-directed science developed by engineers
and the rationalistic view of science expressed by Alexandre Koyré. I noted that for Koyre the chief result of the
Scientific Revolution was the description of reality in terms of a world of
precision, free of all “considerations based upon value-concepts, such as
perfection, harmony, meaning, and aim.” [22] It was in this
context that I char-
19. See my “Mirror-Image Twins: The Communities of Science and
Technology in 19th-Century America,” Technology and Culture 12 (October
1971): 562-80.
20. See my “American Ideologies of Science and Engineering,” Technology
and Culture 17 (October 1976): 696.
21. ”Transformations,” p. 69. The
reference is to my statement that “basic science aims at knowing; it
seeks generality and exactitude, even at the price of a good deal of
idealization. But engineering science
serves the needs of practice, even when this involves loss of generality and
acceptance of approximate solutions.”
(“Scientific Technology, 1845-1900: The Hydraulic Turbine and the
Origins of American Industrial Research,” Technology and Culture 20
[January 1979]: 88.)
22. Alexandre Koyrh, From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe (New
York: Harper Torchbooks, 1958), p. 4. Koyré
held that “This scientific and philosophical revolution - ... can be described
roughly as bringing forth the destruction of the Cosmos, that is, the
disappearance... of the conception of the world as a finite closed, and hierarchically
ordered whole, ... [and] the discarding by scientific thought of all considerations
based upon value-concepts, such as perfection, harmony, meaning, and aim… (p.
4). Earlier in the same work he referred
to “the replacement of the teleological and organismic pattern of thinking and
explanation by the mechanical and causal pattern… (p.v). Koyre described the change in essentially the
same words elsewhere, e.g., in his Metaphysics and Measurement (London,
1968), pp. 19-20, passim, and in his Etudes Galiléennes (Paris, 1966),
pp. 1-4.
90
acterized engineering science as “teleological.” I do not apologize for this; unlike the
science sketched by Koyre, engineering science does have “aims.” This is true not only for the engineering
sciences but for all of those sciences that practice, such as medicine and agriculture. [23] The specific terminology served to emphasize
the contrast between the empiricism and instrumentalism of the engineering sciences
and the rationalism attributed to the basic sciences by Koyré. [24]
One of the things that
distinguishes the engineering sciences from the basic sciences is precisely their
“aim” of assisting in the design of manmade devices or systems. The engineering sciences are instruments for
implementing goals through the design process. In particular, the questions of purpose and
goal are an integral part of discussions of engineering sciences as of
technology generally. Friedrich Rapp has
argued that “the engineering sciences possess a prescriptive character,”
and “... the engineering sciences.. - provide mere hypothetical imperatives;
they explain how to proceed toward the achievement of a certain goal. Yet, by their very nature they cannot provide
any information as to what should be achieved... To make the step from theory
to practice is to proceed from an understanding of the anticipated
consequences... This step is rational only if, in addition to the theoretical
knowledge, the intended goal is also stipulated.” [25]
Herbert Simon has argued
that there are a body of sciences associated with practice, which he terms the
“sciences of the artificial.” [26] He very
properly emphasizes the close association of engineering science with
engineering design. He argues for
engineering that: “We speak of engineering as concerned with ‘synthesis,’ while
science is concerned with ‘analysis.’ Synthetic...
and more specifically, prospective artificial objects having desired properties
- are the central objective of engineering activity and skill. The engineer is concerned with how things ought
to be - ought to be, that is, in order to attain goals, and to function.”
[27]
Simon concludes that sciences of the
artificial, such as “engineering science,” have certain characteris-
23. Herbert A. Simon, The Sciences of the Artificial (Cambridge,
Mass., 1969), pp. 5-6, where goal direction is taken as a fundamental,
intrinsic property of “sciences of the artificial.”
24. Koyre held that “I do believe that science is primarily theory and
not the gathering of ‘facts’” (Metaphysics and Measurement, p. 18 n).
25. Friedrich Rapp, Analytical Philosophy of Technology, Boston
Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 63 (Dordrecht, 1981), pp. 58-59.
26. Simon, The Sciences of the Artificial, pp. 3-13, passim.
27. Ibid., p. 5.
tics that distinguish them from natural sciences. These include characterization in terms of
functions, goals, and adaptation. Also,
the artifacts the engineering sciences are concerned with are properly discussed
in terms of “imperatives” as well as descriptive terms. That is, they are concerned with what ought to
be, not with what is.
One might think of the
engineering sciences as intrinsically objective but operating within a
value-laden context. The engineering sciences
were created to serve certain generalized goals. Specific values appear in the design context,
where people make decisions about building or not building artifacts having
particular attributes and certain anticipated negative side effects in order to
achieve a specific goal deemed to be beneficial. The decisive proof of the presence of value
choices in all engineering design was provided, ironically, by the efforts of
systems engineers to objectify design. They found that to do this they had to specify
weighing coefficients for each system characteristic. In short, they proved that all design is, in
principle, impregnated with values. [28]
Professions link bodies of
knowledge to forms of action. The characteristic
identification of bodies of knowledge as forms (i.e., patterns) of action is
quite widespread in space and time. It
is not a peculiarity of Anglo-Saxon usage. Aristotle defined art (including our
“technology”) in terms of a combination of knowledge and action. He held that “since architecture is an art and
is essentially a reasoned state of capacity to make... art is identical
with a state of capacity to make, involving a true course of reasoning.” [29] In one of my papers analyzed by Fores I quote
the medieval churchman, Hugh of Saint Victor, as holding that “mechanics is a
form of knowledge which must embrace the methods of production of all things.” [30] So for the venerable medieval thinker
mechanics was both a body of knowledge and a form or pattern for action. In a strict sense, it is, of course, the
practitioners who both know and act. But
this strictness verges on pedantry; the original statements led to no
confusion.
The scientific professions
such as medicine provide models of the relations of professions to collections
of sciences. The term “engineering
science” is exactly parallel with the term “medical science” or “agricultural
science.” That is, professions cultivate
bodies of knowledge, and some of these may be properly termed sciences.
28. Thomas T. Woodson, Introduction to Engineering Design (New
York, 1966), pp. 204-5.
29. Richard McKeon, ed, Introduction to Aristotle (New York,
1947), p. 427.
30. “Technology as Knowledge” (n. 9 above), p. 33.
92
Fores seeks to discredit
the engineering sciences, particularly in the version of this concept developed
by W. J. M. Rankine, by associating them with ideology and interest-group
behavior. All professions develop
ideologies. [31] I believe that
all have, at some time or another, attempted to exploit the possession of a
body of esoteric knowledge for selfish or ideological reasons. [32] But the misuse (for example) of medical
science by the medical profession at certain times and places does not
invalidate medical science. Fores’s
argument is simply another version of the old ad hominem fallacy. He reaches the startling conclusion that only
Britain had professions in the mid-19th century (p. 72). He sees Rankine’s use of the term “engineering
science” as an Anglo-Saxon cultural aberration and denounces those who use the
term as “parochial” (p. 76). The fact
that the sociology of professions differs from country to country does not
invalidate the idea that professions exist. Germany has had professions, including
engineering, now and in the 19th century as well. [33]
A key element in the
successful professional strategy of German engineers has been the control of
admission by a diploma, based on a demanding curriculum that included a large
amount of scientific material. In the
19th and early 20th centuries German engineering education was more scientific,
and particularly more oriented to scientific theory, than was that of the
United States. [34]
This strongly
theoretical and scientific bias in German engineering training was, in part, a
heritage of the French polytechnic schools. Along with this highly scientific tradition in
engineering education, the Germans also imported the idea of “engineering
science.” [35]
Max Becker edited
the five-volume Handbuch der Ingenieur-Wissenschaft, which went
31. Howard Becker and James W. Carper, “The Development of
Identification with an Occupation,” American Journal of Sociology 61
(January 1956): 289-98.
32. Jeffrey Berlant, Profession and Monopoly (Berkeley and Los
Angeles, 1975).
33. K. H. Ludwig, Technik, Ingenieure und Gesellschaft, Festschrift
zum 100 Jahrigen Bestehen des VDI (Düsseldorf, 1981); J. F. Volrad Denekde,
Die Freien Berufe (Stuttgart, 1956); and Stanley Hutton and Peter
Lawrence, German Engineers: The Anatomy of a Profession (Oxford, 1981),
which has an extensive bibliography of the literature (pp. 144-48).
34. John R. Freeman, ed., Hydraulic Laboratory Practice (New
York, 1929), provides an illuminating concrete case in point. Freeman was one of those who grafted the more
scientifically advanced German engineering education and engineering research
onto American engineering education and research. Though nominally a translation of a German
book, Freeman had been instrumental in putting the work together with the aim
of transferring the more scientific German technology to American engineering. He was aided by the cooperation of a number of
German engineers and by the Verein Deutscher Ingenieure.
35. Rapp, Analytical Philosophy of Technology (n. 25 above), pp.
91-92.
through several editions from 1856 to 1883. [36] A new edition edited by Leo von Willman
appeared in five volumes from 1904 to 1920 with the title
Handbuch der
Ingenieurwissenschaften.[37] Friedrich Rapp has discussed the history of
the engineering sciences in the 19th century with emphasis on German
developments. [38]
This brings us to the
central contention of Fores, that there is no “well-named” thing called the
“engineering sciences.” These sciences
are sometimes termed the “applied sciences.” I prefer the term “engineering science” for
several reasons. The term “applied science”
derives from the now-discredited theory that technology is nothing more than
the application of the basic sciences. Of
course, one can say that the term “applied” can be taken to mean those sciences
whose function is that of technological application. But a difficulty remains. A fundamental contention of the applied
science theory was that the basic sciences did all the thinking and did it in a
nondirected or “pure” manner. But, as I
and others have shown in numerous case studies and examples, engineers
sometimes do basic research as well as applied research. [39] Similarly, science may be applied directly to
technology. I have never denied its
reality and the importance of the direct application of science to technology. Thus the term “the applied sciences” leads to
semantic monstrosities such as “applied applied science” and “basic applied
science,” as well as “applied basic science.” The medical profession again pro-
36. Max Becker, ed., Handbuch der Ingenzeur-Wissenschaft (Leipzig,
1856-6 1). Other editions appeared in
1856-58, 1861-73, 1861-70, 1863-73, and 1863-83. (For a publication history, see National
Union Catalog of Pre-1956 Imprints, vol. 42, p. 411.)
37. Leo von Willman, ed., Handbuch der Ingenieurwissenschaften, 5
vols. (Leipzig, 1904-20).
38. Friedrich Rapp, “Die Forschung in der Technik (bzw. Technologie) des
19 Jahrhunderts,” in Studien zur Wissenschaftstheorie des 19 Jahrhunderts, ed.
A. Diemer (Meisenheim, 1978), pp. 189-224, esp. the “Ingenieurwissenschaften”
(pp. 200-216) which includes notice of the scientific work of such German
engineers as F. Retenbacher, K. Karmarsch, F. Reuleaux, L. Lewicki, J.
Braunschinger, as well as enumerations of the foundation of engineering
research laboratories. This list could
easily be very greatly extended. See
also Kurt KOppel, “Die Entwicklung der Ingenieurwissenschaften,” Verein
Deutscher Ingenieure Zeitschrift 103 (August 1961): 1145-53.
39. “Mirror-Image Twins” (n. 19 above), pp. 572-77, and “The Conditions
of Technological Development,” in Science, Technology and Society. A
Cross-Disciplinary Perspective, ed. Ina Spiegel-Rosig and Derek J. de Solla
Price (London and Beverly Hills, 1977), pp. 210-11. See also Vincenti, “The Air-Propeller Tests”
(n. 13 above), pp. 712-51, and the same author’s “Control-Volume Analysis: A
Difference in Thinking between Engineering and Physics,” Technology and
Culture 23 (April 1982): 145-74. And
also see Eda Fowlks Kranakis, “The French Connection: Giffard’s Injector and
the Nature of Heat,” Technology and Culture 23 [January 1982): 3-38.
94
vides a helpful analogy. The medical sciences were established long
before William Whewell, in a stunning act of ideological imperialism, renamed
“natural philosophy” as “science.” The
medical sciences, therefore, have avoided linguistic serfdom. We have no problems with the term “medical
science,” and we can (in principle) speak of both basic and applied (i.e., “clinical”)
medical sciences without too much fear of contradiction or semantic confusion.
The term “engineering
science” and its plural are by no means uncommon. One source of the modern historical usage of
the term “engineering science” was the well-known history of civil engineering
of Hans Straub that appeared first in German in 1949 and was translated into
English in 1952. [40] Straub
emphasized the vital role of both the basic and engineering sciences in the
evolution of civil engineering. James
Kip Finch may have been the first English-speaking historian of technology to
follow Straub’s example in using the term “engineering science.” He, like Straub, traced this term back to
Bernard Forest de Belidor’s La Science des Ingenieurs, published in 1729.
[41]
“Engineering science” has
received official recognition on various occasions. In America an influential committee on
engineering education in 1955 called for education for engineers in both
“basic” and “engineering sciences.” The
committee followed what it termed “common practice” in dividing the engineering
sciences into six major fields: mechanics of solids (including statics,
dynamics, and strength of materials), fluid mechanics, thermodynamics, transfer
and rate mechanisms (including heat, mass, and momentum transfer), electrical
theory (including fields, circuits, and electronics), and the nature and
properties of materials. [42]
There are,
however, other lists that, while generally congruent, differ in many
particulars, including the number and classification of engineering sciences
and subfields. [43] The term
“engineering science” continues in fairly common usage. There are a number of engineering books and
journals with “engineering science” as part of their title; one of these,
Basic
Equations
40. Hans Straub, A History of Civil Engineering, trans. E.
Rockwell (London, 1952), pp. 21, 61, 65,67, 105, passim. The original edition was Die Geschichte
derBauingenieurkunst (Basel, 1949).
41. James Kip Finch, “Engineering and Science: A Historical Review and
Appraisal,” Technology and Culture 2 (Fall 1961): 323-25.
42. “Report of the Committee on Evaluation of Engineering Education,” Proceedings
of the American Society for Engineering Education 63 (1955-56): 37.
43. James H. Potter, ed., Handbook of the Engineering Sciences, 2
vols. (Princeton, N.J., 1967)
of Engineering Science, is one of those outline-type texts used by students to
cram for exams. [44]
The engineering sciences
have been known in Britain since Rankine’s time. In the post-World War II era they took on a greater
role in engineering education. At
Cambridge University the postwar curriculum increasingly emphasized work in
these sciences. The term “engineering
science” was not unknown there. One of the
Cambridge engineering faculty members, Dr. J. A. Shercliffe, accepted a chair
in “engineering science” at another British university. [45]
One can deny the separate
existence of engineering sciences by an appeal to a “one science” doctrine. The idea that there is only one science has
been endorsed by Louis Pasteur, the National Science Board, and others. [46] At one level, there can be no objection to
this usage. It is perfectly consistent
for some purposes to say that all the sciences are one, and for other purposes
to emphasize the differences among the sciences. If we wish to examine the totality of all
things utilizing scientific methods then we can lump all the sciences together.
For other purposes we may wish to divide
sciences in functional terms: that is, distinguish between the basic sciences on
the one hand and the technological sciences on the other. [47] The latter category includes not only the
engineering sciences but medical sciences and a complex set of agricultural
sciences as well.
But Fores argues that the
sciences are “one” in a metaphysical sense, and they cannot be separated into
basic and engineering sciences. This
rests on a platonic view of science and indeed of knowledge. He assumes that there is one and only one
category into which an entity (like gold) can fit (p. 70). This makes “science” and all of its
subcategories into platonic forms. From
my point of view the most fundamental issue is that knowledge is best seen as
existing in the minds of people, not as abstract platonic forms existing in
some ideal realm. Thinking of knowledge
as something that exists only in the minds of humans serves to emphasize its
social dimen-
44. William F. Hughes, Basic Equations of Engineering Science (New
York, 1964), is part of Schaum’s Outline Series published by McGraw-Hill.
45. T. J. N. Hilken, Engineering at Cambridge University, 1783-1965 (Cambridge,
1967), pp. 199-254. There are
enumerations of engineering sciences in notes on pages 218, 220, 222, and
passim. Shercliffe was appointed
professor of engineering science at the University of Warwick.
46. National Science Foundation, Only One Science: Twelfth Annual
Report of the National Science Board (Washington, D.C., 1981); the “one
science” quote from Pasteur is on both the title page and the first page. The NSF title may have been a reply to powerful
lobbying for additional funding on the part of the engineering sciences.
47. Layton, “The Conditions of Technological Development” (n. 39 above).
96
sions, including the vital purposive elements in the
engineering sciences, and their link with the moral imperatives of engineering
design. It is from this perspective that
we can look at the values and purposes that are associated with knowledge. This is, as has been argued a necessary part
of understanding the history of technology. From the position taken by Fores, and on this
issue by Koyré also, science is unchanging and divorced from society. From this perspective one might make at best
a “statics” of history of technology and of science. But for historical “dynamics” knowledge must
be seen in its full context. Here too
Fores’s philosophy is not helpful in gaining an understanding of social
dimensions involved in the history of technology.
Fores explicitly includes
in his one science artificial things such as electric circuits and synthetic
chemicals. He also denies that the form
of the engineering sciences is different than the natural sciences. The engineering sciences consist primarily of
statements about human artifacts. They
are tailored to meet the needs of practical designers, and form follows
function here as in biology. For example,
electrical engineering science is not identical with electrical physics. Ronald Kline has recently done a study of the
rise of electrical engineering science. [48] It is a
complex and fascinating story. And it is
clear from this and many other studies that formal differences between
engineering sciences and corresponding basic sciences are a matter of empirically
verifiable fact.
The platonic “one science”
view, as a metaphysical proposition, cannot be refuted. But Pasteur, who may have believed in “one science,”
also believed in adopting fruitful hypotheses.
He was attacked because the medical establishment, unwilling to accept
his results, rejected them as “theory.” I believe that Pasteur’s reply also has
relevance to some of the broader issues raised by Fores against me, so in
conclusion I will quote Pasteur at some length:
You wish to upset what you call my theory, apparently
in order to defend another; allow me to tell you by what signs these theories
are recognized: the characteristic of erroneous theories is the impossibility
of ever foreseeing new facts; whenever such a fact is discovered, those theories
have to be grafted with further hypotheses in order to account for them. True theories, on the contrary, are the
expressions of actual facts and are characterized by being able to predict new
facts, a natural consequence of those already known. In a word, the characteristic of a true theory
is its fruitfulness. [49]
48. Kline, “Charles P. Steinmetz” (n. 8 above).
49. Quoted in René Vallery-Radot, The Life of Pasteur (New York:
Dover, 1960), p. 243.
97
The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy