The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
James R. Jacob, Margaret C.
Jacob
The Anglican Origins of Modern
Science:
The Metaphysical Foundations of
the Whig Constitution
June 1980, 251-267
Content
II – Religious Ideology & Matter
Theory
III – The Newtonian vs Radical
Enlightnment HHC – titling added |
A NEW DIMENSION HAS BEEN ADDED in
the last decade or so to conventional accounts of the Scientific Revolution.
It is now clear that ideological
and social factors proved crucial in the development of science in
seventeenth-century
Crucial to this process was an
intellectual transformation within Anglicanism which began at mid-century and
continued throughout much of
*PhD Program in History, The
Our thanks are due to Professor
Randolph Trumbach for suggesting that we write this paper and for suggesting its
title; to Dr. Steven Shapin for helping to focus our attention on the main
theme, the relation of matter theory to ideology; to Professor Melvin Richter
and Micha Richter for suggesting an improvement in the quality of the argument;
and to the participants of two conferences “The Development of British Political
Thought 1500-1700,” held at the Folger Shakespeare Library, April 13-14, 1979,
and “Science, Pseudoscience and Society,” sponsored by the Calgary Institute for
the Humanities, May 10-12, 1979.
1. Christopher Hill, The Century
of Revolution 1601-1714 (London: Nelson, 1961); the articles by S. F. Mason,
H. F. Kearney, Christopher Hill, T. K. Rabb, Barbara Shapiro, and Margaret
Espinasse that first appeared in Past & Present, collected since in
Charles Webster, ed., The Intellectual Revolution of the Seventeenth Century
(London/Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974), pp. 197—316, 347368; P. M.
Rattansi, “The Social Interpretation of Science in the Seventeenth Century,” in
Peter Mathias, ed., Science and Society 1600-1900 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1972), pp. 1-32; Margaret C. Jacob, The Newtonians and the
English Revolution 1689-1720 (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1976);
and J. R. Jacob, Robert Boyle and the English Revolution (New York: Burt
Franklin, 1977).
kind of science: once again it will
become clear that religious factors proved central to the origins of modern
science. When new evidence is
brought to bear on that perennial question of the relationship between science
and religion, a new general thesis emerges concerning the origins of modern
science. And once perceived, the
Anglican origins of modern science add an entirely new dimension to the history
of English constitutional development.
We are not accustomed to thinking of
English science as being indebted to Anglicanism. Robert Merton has taught us to think
rather of its Puritan origins, and Charles Webster’s recent monument to
scholarship, The Great Instauration, while defining Puritanism much more
narrowly than Merton did, gives new life to Merton’s thesis.
[2]
Webster argues that a major step in the development of
English science occurred between 1640 and 1660, and that the motivation for this
science came essentially from Puritanism (understood as reformist religion
generally, from liberal Anglicans through Presbyterians and Independents to
certain sectaries) and specifically from Puritan millenarianism.
[3]
Webster supports his argument with
a wealth of detail and his case is convincing as far as it goes. But Webster’s is not the last word on the
subject, because his work raises a vital question which he never addresses: what
happened in the course of the seventeenth century to the reformist science
unleashed by the Puritan millennial vision? According to Webster, the Puritan natural
philosophers practiced their science in the 1640s and 1650s, but their reforming
aims came to an end with the failure of the Revolution and the restoration of
the monarchy and established church in 1660. This is not to say that the Puritan
savants, Samuel Hartlib and his circle, were without permanent influence. The Royal Society and the Royal College
of Physicians appropriated many of their ideas and projects and indeed some of
their personnel - Robert Boyle and William Petty, for example. Webster acknowledges this, but he equally
maintains that the old motivation was dead: science had ceased to be dedicated
to building
Webster’s interpretation rests upon
the assumption that an almost Manichaean contrast existed between the social
aims of Puritan science and the pursuit of organized science after 1660. But history is rarely, if ever, so tidy,
and Webster’s assumed dichotomy does not stand up under the evidence. Missing in his account is an awareness of
the dialectic of the Revolution itself - the fact that it was one thing in1640 -
1641and had become quite another by the 1650s.
Since he presents an essentially
one-dimensional revolution Webster creates an impossible quandary: there is
simply no way of getting from his Puritan scientists of millennial persuasion to
the science of Newton and the Newtonians, to what he calls that “quite
different, alien ideology” out of which modern science, that is Newtonian
science, evolved. [5] That Newton and many of his associates were also
millenarians, that they shared an intensely religious and social vision of
science, that they held to distinct political positions - albeit different from
the millenarian, religious and political interests of Puritan scientists during
the 1640s - all this is still not enough to
2. Robert K. Merton, Science,
Technology and Society in Seventeenth-Century
3. Webster, Great
4. ibid., Ch.
6.
5. ibid., p.
250.
252
enable Webster to see the link
between his science and theirs.
What follows reveals the existence
of that link and examines its character. The story takes up with the rupture that
occurs in the ranks of reforming scientists and savants in the course of the
mid-century turmoil. One group, led
by Boyle, John Wilkins, John Wallis, Walter Charleton, John Evelyn, Christopher
Wren and others, continued to advocate and engage in the organized pursuit of
experimental science. [6] But they dissociated this project from
any radical reform of church, state, the economy or society. They did not cease entirely to be
reformers, but couched their reforming sentiments in vague terms of improving
man’s health and estate through science. When they did become more specific, it
was, for example, to indicate the ways by which experimental science might be
deployed to increase production, especially food production, and commerce. [7]
But these reforms would progress without altering the
existing social arrangements in the direction of greater leveling or
redistribution of authority. This
is not to discount these reforming aims, but to indicate that they would not
democratize politics and society.
As if to symbolize this approach to
reform, many in this group left revolutionary
In this regard the conservative
reformers consciously distanced themselves from the radicals who saw in science
a powerful tool for promoting religious, political, and social revolution. Science, as they understood it, could
justify democracy in church and state; it might also be used to extend popular
education in schools and universities and to build a new society that would be
more just and rational. [10]
In reaction conservative reformers
did more than retreat to
6. Robert Boyle, Some
Considerations Touching the Usefulness of Experimental Natural Philosophy,
Pt. 1(1663) and Pt. 11(1671). Both parts were written during the l650s:
see R. S. Westfall, “Unpublished Boyle Papers Relating to Scientific Method,”
Annals of Science, 1956, 12:65, and Thomas Birch, ed., The
Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, 6 vols.
(
7. Jacob, Boyle, pp. 141-143,
and Royal Society of London, Letter Book Supplement, A-B Copy, John Beale, pp.
348, 382, 389-390, 403-410.
8. Allen G. Debus, ed., Science
and Education in the Seventeenth Century: The Webster- Ward Debate (London:
Macdonald, 1970); Henry Stubbe, A Light Shining Out of Darkness (London,
1659), which was “answered by H. F. [Henry Ferne?] but never printed,” according
to Anthony à Wood, The History and Antiquities of the University of Oxford,
3 vols. (Oxford, 1792-1796), Vol. III, p. 695; for the conservative reaction
to Stubbe’s attack on conventional religion and the universities: Anthony a
Wood, Athenae Oxoniensis, ed. P. Bliss, 4 vols. (London, 1813-1820), Vol.
III, p. 1069. See also: Sundry
Things from Several Hands Concerning the University of Oxford (London,
1659), and Charles Webster, “William Dell and the Idea of University,” in
Changing Perspectives in the History of Science, ed. Mikulâ Teich and
Robert Young (London: Heinemann, 1973), pp. 110-126.
10. J. R. Jacob and M. C. Jacob,
“Scientists and Society: The Saints Preserved,” Journal of European Studies,
1971, 1:87-90; and J. R. Jacob and M. C. Jacob, “Seventeenth Century Science
and Religion: The State of the Argument,” History of Science, 1976, 14:
200-201.
10. Christopher Hill, The World
Turned Upside Down (London: Temple Smith, 1972),
253
tation of the social hierarchy and
answered the radicals by rendering their social views untrue in terms of the
conservative metaphysics. In other
words, a conservative matter theory was constructed which “outlawed” radicalism
from the universe. We shall argue
that this new metaphysics, produced for ideological reasons by conservative
reformers in their dialogue with the radicals, had a profound effect upon the
development of modern science. By
examining the social process by which this new matter theory developed, we shall
establish the connection of which Webster’s thesis cannot take account, the
connection between reforming Puritan science in the 1640s and 1650s and the
development of theoretical science - especially mathematical physics and
astronomy after the Restoration, most importantly in the work and achievement of
Isaac Newton. There is a clear,
straight line running between the conservative reformers of the mid-century
revolution and the Newtonian synthesis, and this line allows us to chart “the
Anglican origins of modern science.”
Let us also be clear that this is
not another restatement of the Merton thesis. He, like Webster, took no account of the
dialectics of the Puritan revolution and the resulting dialogue between
conservatives and radicals. More to
the point, Merton did not address himself to the connections between Puritanism
and scientific theory but only to those between Puritanism and scientific
practice. [11] Yet it is
only on the level of the former connections between religious ideology and
matter theory that we can trace the social genesis of the conceptual revolution
that culminated in the Newtonian synthesis, the hallmark of the Scientific
Revolution. To this process we now
turn.
***
II – Religious Ideology & Matter
Theory
True, the Revolution did unleash
Puritan reformism, and this impulse was translated by Hartlib’s group into a
melioristic scientific enterprise. But the Revolution unleashed more than
that. From the mid-1640s and up to
the moment the king was restored,
The radical sects supported their
attacks on church and state with an antinomian theology deriving from the
Reformation revival of ancient heresies. In its most extreme form - in the hands
of Digger Gerrard Winstanley for instance - this ideology ended in mortalism and
a pantheistic materialism that, denying the distinction between Creator and
creation, asserted that divinity lay not in a transcendent supernatural realm
but in the here and now, the world of man and nature.
[13] Important in the present context is that
a fundamental belief of all radicals was that
11. “M. D. King, “Reason, Tradition
and the Progressiveness of Science,” History and Theory, 1970,
10:5-21.
12. Hill, World Upside Down. The notion of turning the world
upside down was a popular commonplace. See Peter Burke, Popular Culture in
Early Modern
13. Hill, World Upside Down,
pp. 112, 114, 150, 176, 318-319; Christopher Hill, ed., Winstanley: The
Law of Freedom and Other Writings (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973), pp. 42-59.
For Winstanley as theist and
pantheist as against Hill’s Winstanley as pantheist only, see Lotte Mulligan,
John Graham, and Judith Richards, “Winstanley: A Case for the Man as He Said He
Was,” Journal of Ecclesiastical History, 1977, 28:57
-75.
254
the holy spirit was directly
accessible to or even in man; the rigid dualism between matter and spirit, the
fallen world and the perfect God, of orthodox Christianity was at least blurred,
if not altogether obliterated. [14]
The spread and tenacity of this
“enthusiasm” (to use the pejorative that lumped all radicals under one
categorical umbrella) alarmed more conservative thinkers, including those who
had participated in the scientific movement sponsored by reformist Puritans.
In other words, there is a
discernible and crucial difference between the reformism of the Hartlibians, of
Boyle, Benjamin Worsley, and Petty, and the radicalism of Seekers, True
Levellers, Fifth Monarchists, Ranters, and Quakers. Both groups, reformists and radicals
alike, belonged to the revolution, but by 1650 the revolution of the radicals
had left the reformists far behind.
The radical sectaries were drawn to
alchemy, astrology, and number mysticism because these occult sciences fitted
their conception of a vitalistic or in some extreme cases even pantheistic
universe alive with spirit. According to the radicals, if man could
learn to read nature, he could master it and hence attain to perfect wisdom and
its attendant blessings. The
reformation of the world would be complete and men could then enjoy a millennial
paradise on earth. [15] In the early 1640s Puritan reformers like Boyle had also
adopted a millennial scheme based upon notions of the reformation of the world
and of knowledge which were derived from the works of Francis Bacon and Jan
Comenius. Expectation ran high in
the heady early years of the Revolution, and the Puritan philosophers even
developed an intense interest in the occult sciences as keys to the mastery of
nature. [16] But in the late 1640s the reformers retreated from this
extreme position, as the radical sectaries appropriated it to their own purposes
and spun out the heretical and subversive implications of occult science and its
vitalistic conception of the universe. [17
During the 1650s the reformers -
Boyle, Walter Charleton, and others - modified their philosophy in the face of
the radical threat: in the place of the now discredited occultism they adopted
what Boyle called the corpuscular philosophy. This amounted to a Christianized
Epicurean atomism treated as a hypothesis to be tested by experiment. The corpuscularians held with Epicurus
that the world was made up of lifeless atoms colliding in the vacuum of space.
But the Puritan philosophers
departed from Epicurus by denying that the world as we know it was the product
of a long succession of random atomic collisions. Rather they held that a providential God
was responsible for all motion in the universe. He determined the paths the atoms took
and hence maintained the order of the universe. [18] Not only was this a workable scientific hypothesis
capable of being refined and elaborated by a Baconian program of experiment, it
was also an attractive candidate for adoption because it was applicable to
social issues.
14. Geoffrey Nuttall, The Holy
Spirit in Puritan Faith and Experience (Oxford: B. Blackwell, 1946);
15. Hill, World Upside Down,
16. Rattansi, “Social Interpretation
of Science,” p. 20.
17. ibid., pp. 20-23; P. M.
Rattansi, “Paracelsus and the Puritan Revolution,” Ambix, 1964,
18. Boas, Robert Boyle and
Seventeenth-Century Chemistry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958);
Robert H. Kargon, Atomism in
This Christianized corpuscular and
experimental philosophy allowed the Puritan scientists to escape the taint of
heresy associated with the occultism and animism of the radical sectaries. More important, it allowed the reformers
to attack the radicals. The idea
that matter is moved mechanically by the will and according to the intelligence
of a supernatural God upheld the orthodox Christian dualism of matter and spirit
in the face of the radicals’ animism, their belief that all matter was endowed
with soul and that spirit was immanent in nature. [19] Nor was this merely a victory against false theological
doctrine; it also had religious and political ramifications. The vitalistic or pantheistic idea of
nature provided the metaphysical grounds for an attack on traditional authority
in church and state. If spirit lay
within man and nature, this was a strong argument against organized churches
that were supported by tithes and learned ministries that claimed superior
spiritual wisdom and separate spiritual authority - the power to teach,
discipline, and punish. [20] Vitalism could also be used to support
the notion of human equality and to justify in cosmic terms anti-monarchical and
even democratic political ideas. The natural philosophy of the radicals
tended to dissolve hierarchy, while hierarchical social order found support in
the Christian dualism newly shored up by the corpuscular philosophy of the
reforming Puritans. [21]
The inductive or experimental aspect
of the new corpuscular philosophy worked out in the 1650s also bore an
ideological message meant to counter the radicals. Scientific progress would come through
painstaking inquiry, the collection of evidence, and the testing of hypotheses.
Knowledge then was not, as the
sectaries with their emphasis on magic and the occult maintained, the result of
mystical experience or God’s direct revelation to the saints.
[22] God instead revealed Himself indirectly by two means,
nature and Scripture, His word and His work, and both required close study in
order to bear fruit. This emphasis
upon patient, industrious scrutiny was directed against the antinomian theology
of the radical sectaries, which insisted that God revealed Himself immediately
to the saints so that they might achieve perfection or at least perfect wisdom
in this life. The fruits of
salvation were accessible here and now as well as in the world to come. For the Puritan reformers, on the other
hand, the effortless pleasures of salvation were deferred to the next life; in
this life rewards would come only through reason and industry.
[23] Science, the new philosophy, was the model: knowledge
would come not through visions or divine illumination but rather through a
searching and sustained inquiry into nature, the humility and dedication of the
experimental philosopher. Nor was
this update on the work ethic only directed against the illuminism of the
sectaries; it was also seen as an instrument of social control. As Boyle insisted, hard work would keep
men too busy to contrive heresy or to plot social revolution. [24] Science would be particularly valuable in this regard
too because the practical application of its discoveries would create more and
more employment. [25] Both the corpuscularianism and the experimentalism of
the
19. Jacob, Boyle, pp.
112-115.
20. Thomas Edwards, Gangraena,
3rd ed. (
21. Edwards, Gangraena, pp.
15-19, 23-24, 28-29; Jacob, Boyle, Chs. 3 and 4; and Jacob,
Newtonians, Ch. 1.
22. Jacob, Boyle, pp.
98-112.
23. ibid., pp.
85-88.
24. Peter Pett, A Discourse
Concerning
25. Thomas Sprat, A History of the
Royal Society (
256
reforming philosophers were designed
to combat two threats, heresy and social insubordination, at the same
time.
The new corpuscular philosophy was
also meant to answer one particularly virulent version of philosophical and
religious heresy: Hobbes’s Leviathan. Hobbes himself was anything but a
radical, but his peculiar conservatism was pitched on the most radical
philosophical and theological grounds, which from the 1650s on often resembled
the political and religious views of men much more radical than he. In politics Hobbes put forth a persuasive
argument for political obligation that rested entirely on considerations of
power and self-interest and denied the force of arguments from divine right,
providence, or traditional Christian morality. [26] As for religion, his mechanistic metaphysics denied the
existence of spirit and a spiritual world and hence any independent role to the
clergy, who were traditionally seen as the guardians and interpreters of the
operations of spirit in the world. The clergy, according to Hobbes, were
fraudulent as intermediaries between God and man and should be reduced to mere
functionaries of the civil sovereign. [27] From the point of view of the Puritan natural
philosophers Hobbes sucked too much spirit out of the world, while the sectaries
pumped too much back in.
The reforming Puritan savants
deployed their corpuscular philosophy against Hobbes and Hobbesists, just as
they did against antinomians and other radicals. Indeed after 1660 Hobbesism was
increasingly identified with subversion [28] - and with
good reason, as we shall see. Corpuscularianism preserved a role for
spirit in the universe, namely, that of imparting motion to matter and giving
shape to the world through providential design. Hence the corpuscularians, against
Hobbes’s radical surgery, supported the clergy’s authority as interpreters of
God’s ways and will. [29] The experimentalism of the Puritan savants was also
aimed against Hobbes: the way to knowledge was through induction and the testing
of hypotheses, not through Hobbes’s deductive rationalism any more than through
the saints’ illuminism. [30
Under the impact of radical
sectarian and Hobbesist challenges the Puritan philosophers grafted their
reforming science onto an ideology that sought to reestablish order and
stability in church and state. Science was not only seen to alleviate
man’s material condition; it also might cure the excesses of revolution. The natural philosophers who created the
new ideology of science, like Boyle, Wilkins, and Charleton, kept the reforming
aims of the Puritan scientific vision, particularly when they were easily
accommodated to or even promoted the larger political and religious goal. So they continued to argue for science as
a means to greater private profit and national wealth and power, because
science, to the extent that it increased agricultural production, trade, and
shipping, would also foster domestic peace. The scientific
26. Besides Hobbes, Leviathan
(
27. Hobbes,
28. [Thomas Tenison], “The Epistle
Dedicatory,” The Creed of Mr. Hobbes Examined
(
29. John Wallis to John Owen, Oct.
10, 1655, in Peter Toon, ed., The Correspondence of John Owen
(1616-1683), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 87-88;
John Wallis, Hobbiani Puncti Dispunctio (Oxford, 1657), pp. 42-43;
and Robert Boyle, “The Preface,” An Examen of Mr. T. Hobbes His Dialogus
Physicus de Natura Aeris (Oxford, 1662).
30. Boyle, “The Preface,” An
Examen; and John Wallis, “The Epistle Dedicatory,” Elenchus Geometriae
Hobbianae (
protagonists equated a science made
practical with growing prosperity, social order, and the public good. [31]
The initial Puritan reforming vision
of the 1640s thus survived in a continuing belief in the material benefits of
science. [32] By the late 1650s, however, this belief in science as an
instrument of material progress was wedded to a new Anglican theology, one no
longer essentially Puritan but latitudinarian. Its central tenets were repudiation of
predestination, a concomitant emphasis on free will and striving as the keys to
salvation, and an almost obsessive concern for design, order, and harmony as the
primary manifestations of God’s role in the universe.
[33] Evolved during the 1650s, this liberal Anglicanism
relied upon the new science to verify both God’s order in an unstable world and
the superiority of cautious scientific inquiry to the illuminations of the
spirit. During the Cromwellian
Protectorate the hope among men like Boyle and Richard Baxter was that this view
could be translated into a church settlement based upon Archbishop James Usher’s
schemes for moderate episcopacy. [34] These hopes of course were never realized, but they
survived the Restoration, and this scientifically grounded latitudinarianism
received its classic formulations in the works of Robert Boyle published after
1660 and in Thomas Sprat’s History of the Royal Society (1667),
masterminded by John Wilkins. It
was thus adopted as the public stance, if not the official ideology, of the
Royal Society. [35]
Barbara Shapiro has argued against
Merton and the Mertonians that to the extent that the early fellows of the Royal
Society shared a common outlook it was latitudinarian. According to Shapiro, science itself or
scientific humanism was the shaping force in the development of
latitudinarianism, and she attributes little or no influence in this regard to
the radical revolution and the latitudinarian responses to it.
[36] We would argue in contrast, on the basis
of what we now know, that this new Anglicanism with its supportive science and
natural philosophy was crucially defined by the dialectics of revolution, by the
challenges posed by the radical sectaries and the reforming Puritan response to
them. With Webster we would agree
that in 1640 the initial scientific vision was Puritan (although we would not
agree with him that it was killed off rather than developing into something
else); with Shapiro we would agree that by 1660 this vision had become
latitudinarian (although we would not agree with her that it had never been
Puritan). Yet against both Webster
and Shapiro it must be asserted that Puritanism was transformed into liberal
Anglicanism during and because of the Revolution. In that transformation lie the Anglican
origins of modern
31. Wren, Parentalia, p. 196;
and Royal Society, Letter Book Supplement, A-B Copy, Beale, pp. 348, 382,
389-390, 403, 410. For a suggestive
approach to politics and economic ideology in this period see Joyce Appleby,
Economic Thought and Ideology in Seventeenth Century England (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1978), Ch. 9.
32. Jacob, Boyle, pp.
133-159.
33. “See Robert Martin Krapp,
Liberal Anglicanism: 1636-1647 (Ridgefield, Conn.: Acorn Press, 1944);
John F. H. New, Anglican and Puritan: The Basis of Their Opposition,
1558-1640 (Stanford/London: Stanford University Press, 1964), pp. 16-21; for
further evidence of preaching against predestination in Cambridge during the
1650s, see Spencer Research Library, University of Kansas, diary of Charles
North, MS A. 41, fol. 1, Dr. Cudworth of Clare Hall “On 4 Esiah: 5;” also
Dr. Arrowsmith, and Dr. Love on the theme “faith without good works is dead.”
Cf. Gregory Memorandum, Gregory
MSS, University Library,
34. R. Abernathy, “Richard Baxter and the
35. “Jacob, Boyle, pp.
133-143, 152-159.
36. Barbara Shapiro, John Wilkins
1614-1672 (Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1969), pp.
1-11, 224-250.
258
science and the ideological
continuity of English science from Boyle to
That continuity is everywhere
apparent, in the rhetoric of private philosophizing as well as in public
ideology. The articulation of this
new Anglicanism received philosophical refinement in Restoration Cambridge,
where a new generation of natural philosophers, Platonists as they were called,
labored to create a metaphysics of spirit that would prove compatible with the
new science and yet repudiate “enthusiastic” sectarianism. Henry More and Ralph Cudworth, although
in no sense experimentalists like Boyle and his associates (and hence sometimes
in disagreement with them), nevertheless embraced the primacy of spirit over
matter, of Creator over creation, so central to the new corpuscularian
philosophy. For a time More looked
to the mechanical philosophy of Descartes as an alternative to the pantheism of
the sects and the materialism of Hobbes. Eventually he discarded Descartes, too,
because his radical separation of matter and spirit created an intellectual gap
through which the heresies of the sects and the mechanisms of Hobbes might creep
once again. [37
The Cambridge Platonists, and More
in particular, like the Puritan reformers, saw this struggle with heresy in
historical and cosmic terms; they too were millenarians. Millenarianism flourished in the private
world of college tutorials; it was now understood to be too dangerous a doctrine
for pulpit orations. Within
Anglican circles the quiet purveyors of prophecy can often be traced to
The millennium of the Restoration
latitudinarians did display certain marked differences from that of the Puritan
reformers: it was largely a private matter, self-consciously aimed against, as
Evelyn put it, “the Millenaries of old, or Fifth Monarchists of Late,” it
entailed no amelioration of existing social inequities, and invariably it gained
expression at moments of political crisis - the prospect or reality of Catholic
monarchy, the revolution of 1688-1689, the wars against France. It too applied scientific theories to
social conditions. Anglican
millenarianism posited a preordained harmony and order, imposed by God on
nature, enforced by the established church and monarchical state on society.
And in the case of
By and large Anglican
millenarianism, that particular “civic consciousness” of its latitudinarian
wing, remained well beneath the surface after 1660 and even, although for
different reasons, after 1689. Liberal Anglicans of the Restoration had
to tread carefully; they got and indeed sought few enough preferments from the
recently restored hierarchy, which was bent upon dissociating itself from those
who had
37. Charles Webster, “Henry More and
Descartes: Some New Sources,” British Journal for the History of Science,
1969, 4:359-364; Marjorie Nicolson, “The Early Stages of Cartesianism in
England,” Studies in Philology, 1929, 26:356-374; Sterling P. Lamprecht,
“The Role of Descartes in Seventeenth Century England,” Columbia
University, Studies in the History of Ideas, 1935, 3:18 1-242. We are not implying that the
rejection of Descartes can be explained solely along social and religious lines;
cf. Kargon, Atomism in
38. Isaac Newton, Opticks
(
compromised with the Interregnum and
punishing them. For a young man
with an instinctively cautious temperament, such as
The Puritan philosophers were
trimmers. They trimmed during the
1650s when they sought the resettlement of the church along latitudinarian lines
that would incorporate Anglicans and Presbyterians in one communion, tolerate
mild dissent, and discipline sectarian extremists. [39] They trimmed again during the Restoration, when that
broad church was not forthcoming, and decided to work within the Anglican
establishment and to pitch their science on theological grounds that were
latitudinarian but nonetheless Anglican. [40] As their sermons reveal, this trimming, so consistent
from the 1650s right through the Revolution of 1688-1689, was sustained by two
hopes: the prospect that science would bring wealth and power (not to speak of
the goods it had already delivered) and the desire first to obtain and then to
preserve order and stability, an environment in which the profitable pursuit of
science could take place, against threats of subversion from below and, at least
during the Restoration, by Catholics from outside. [41]
Yet trimming did not mean retreat
from polemical involvement with the church’s enemies. After 1660 church and monarchy had been
rendered secure against varieties of political and intellectual radicalism that
doggedly persisted despite the new mechanisms for suppression. Although the radical sectaries were
forced underground after the Restoration, and consequently their history largely
obliterated, there were significant eruptions that reveal what happened. In particular the activities and writings
of that most infamous Restoration heretic and subversive, Henry Stubbe, tie the
1650s to the 1670s and beyond.
A radical Independent in the 1650s,
Stubbe has been conventionally seen as a turncoat upholder of the status quo
after the Restoration. His famous
attacks on the Royal Society have been read by such noted authorities as Richard
Foster Jones and Herschel Baker as a conservative defense of the traditional
Aristotelian learning against the incursions of the new philosophy of the Royal
Society. [42] A defense of traditional learning these attacks may have
been, but what has until now been missed is the radical aim underlying them.
Stubbe’s brief was not against the
science of the Royal Society but rather against its natural religion. He was the first to see the ideological
implications of its position: it upheld traditional religion - belief in a
providential God and a clergy delegated to justify His ways to man. This was too much for Stubbe the radical
Hobbesian. [43] Indeed it was tantamount to popery.
[44] Stubbe instead advocated a return to what
he believed to be purest Christianity - a simple Arian creed denying the
divinity of Christ, toleration of opinion beyond that,
39. See note
33.
40. Jacob,
41. Jacob, Boyle, pp. 159-176;
and J. R. Jacob, “Boyle’s Atomism and the Restoration Assault on Pagan
Naturalism,” Social Studies of Science, 1978,
8:211-233.
42. Richard Foster Jones, Ancients
and Moderns, 2nd ed. (St. Louis, Mo.: Washington University Press, 1961),
pp. 244-262; and Herschel Baker, The Wars of Truth (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1947), pp. 362-365.
43. British Library Add. MS 32553,
fols. 5-34; Francis Thompson, “Lettres de Stubbe a Hobbes,” Archives de
Philosophie, 1936, 12:99-106; Henry Stubbe, The Miraculous Conformist
(London, 1666), pp. 2, 4-6, 10-11, 27; Royal Society, Boyle Letters 2, fol.
65v; Henry Stubbe, “The Preface to the Judicious Reader,” Legends No
Histories (London, 1670), (the third unnumbered page); Joseph Glanvill, A
Praefatory Answer to Mr. Henry Stubbe (London, 1671), Preface (first
unnumbered page), pp. 6, 11, 63.
44. Henry Stubbe, The Plus Ultra
Reduced to a Non Plus (
260
and a church in which the civil
authority possessed complete control and the clergy, assuming there was any, was
thus stripped of any independent spiritual authority.
[45] Stubbe’s ecclesiology, moreover, rested
on a vitalistic materialism, equally applicable to the world of man and nature,
reminiscent of Winstanley. [46] Stubbe spread his ideas underground through an important
and until now ignored manuscript. [47] He also probably preached his extreme Erastianism -
arguing state supremacy in ecclesiastical matters - or what he liked to call
“Mahometan Christianity” to Dissenters in rural
Nor were Stubbe and latter-day
Whiggish Stubbians ignored by the natural philosophers of the Royal Society.
Robert Boyle and his circle were in active and continuous dialogue with Stubbe
and with varieties of philosophical heresy throughout the Restoration.
[50] Boyle in public and Newton in private, to
name only the two leading philosophers, continued to define their own
metaphysics in response to the threat posed by what Newton called atheism and
Boyle preferred to label naturalism - the philosophies of Hobbes, Stubbe, and
their ilk. Boyle’s imagination ran
wild. He and his Anglican
associates, John Evelyn and John Tillotson among others, powerful churchmen all,
feared that should the king grant a declaration of indulgence in 1686, sectaries
would unite with papists to undo the Reformation in
While Boyle and Glanvill pounded at
the naturalists in print, More and Cudworth in
A close reading of
45. Henry Stubbe, An Account of
the Rise and Progress of Mahometanism, ed. Hafiz Mahmud Khan Shairani
(
46.
See note 43 above and Account of
Mahometanism, p. 49.
47. Account of Mahometanism;
J. R. Jacob, “Civil Religion and Radical Politics: Stubbe to Toland,” book
in preparation; J. R. Jacob, “Aristotle and the New Philosophy: Stubbe v.
the Royal Society,” in M. Hanen et al., eds., Science, Pseudoscience and
Society (Waterloo, Ontario: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1980), in
press.
48. Glanvill, Praefatory Answer,
pp. 62—63; and Jacob, “Civil Religion.”
49. Cf. Charles Blount et al., The
Oracles of Reason (
50. Jacob, “Boyle’s Atomism and Pagan
Naturalism,” passim.
51.
Ibid., pp.
224-228.
52. John Craig to John Conduitt,
language he employed was remarkably
similar to the Anglican polemics with which he was surrounded.
By the late l680s the threat posed
to the established church came not from West Country Whigs but from the monarchy
itself. Liberal Anglicans had been
of one voice in their opposition to Catholicism, yet they had been equally loyal
to the institution of monarchy. Where we find Royal Society pamphleteers
active during the Exclusion crisis, they were allied to the Tories. [56] An aggressively Catholic monarch who inherited a court
culture that was suspiciously Epicurean (and in his brother’s day notoriously
libertine) posed a delicate, almost insoluble, quandary.
In the light of that quandary, and
of what we now know about the political activity of the Royal Society during the
Restoration, we wish to propose a new approach to the timing of the publication
of
53. “De Gravitatione et aequipondo
fluidorum,” in A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall, eds., Unpublished
Scientfic Papers of Isaac Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1962), pp. 142-143.
54.
Ibid., p. 144.
55.
Ibid., p. 148.
56. J
R. Jacob, “Restoration Ideologies and
the Royal Society,” Hist. Sci., Feb. 1980,
18.
57.
Frank E. Manuel, The Religion of
Isaac Newton. The Fremantle Lectures, 1973 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974),
pp. 99-100, and, for portions of Yahuda MS 1 by
262
Pepys’s trimming at the court of
James II was well known, and indeed he paid dearly for it in the post-l689
political wilderness to which he was consigned.
The difficulty with the
Halley-Newton story, attractive though it is, is that it also closely resembles
George Ent’s description of his role in prodding William Harvey to allow his
De generatione animalium to be published in 1651. [58] That of course does not make the story untrue in the
case of Newton. But if there is
something to the hypothesis that the publication of Newton’s Principia
during the reign of James II was inspired by political motives, whether
Newton knew of them or not, we would expect some oblique indication of that
covert design, some hint dropped either in Halley’s admiring ode on Newton and
his achievement prefixed to the Principia, or possibly in Halley’s
fawning and explanatory letter on that achievement addressed to James II and
later published in the Philosophical Transactions.
[59]
A new translation of Halley’s ode,
which relates it directly to Lucretius’ De rerum natura, has been most
usefully supplied by W. R. Albury. That ode begins by reminding the
Principia’s readers that “the pattern of the Heavens” is based upon “Laws
which the all-producing Creator, when he was fashioning the first-beginnings of
things, wished not to violate and established as the foundations of his eternal
work.” After this brief mention of
the eternality of Law and the role of the Divine Monarch as its creator and
preserver, the poem goes on to glory in the power unleashed by Newton’s
intellect, which “has allowed us to penetrate the dwellings of the Gods and to
scale the heights of Heaven.” Couched entirely in Epicurean language,
Halley’s ode commends the new science sponsored by the Royal Society as the
means by which “we are truly admitted as table-guests of the Gods…”
[60]
We would agree with Albury’s
conclusion that the explanation for Halley’s choice of Lucretius as his model
must lie in his attempt to “reply to Epicurean criticism of the Royal Society”
which had circulated in court circles during the 1680s. In short Halley is trying “to convince
the fashionable Epicureans associated with the Stuart Court of the importance of
Newtonian science,” [61] and this at an absolutely critical
time for Anglican natural philosophers and churchmen who had been systematically
excluded from James’s court.
Perhaps we can now better understand
why, after the church’s hegemony had been reestablished in the early l690s,
Newton wrote a seemingly bizarre letter to Pepys in which he asserts, almost
hysterically, “I never designed to get anything by your interest, nor by King
James’s favour…” [62] If indeed the Principia had been published in an
attempt to be ingratiating, by reestablishing the supportive role that
scientific knowledge had given the monarchy during the Restoration, then either
Newton was innocent of these motives, or he became almost paranoid after
the
58. Christopher Hill, “Sir Isaac
Newton and His Society,” in his Change and Continuity in 17th Century England
(London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 1974), p. 274; cf. George Grinnell,
“Newton’s Principia as Whig Propaganda,” in Paul Fritz and David
Williams, eds., City and Society in the 18th Century (Toronto: Hakkert,
1973); pp. 181-192, which at least raises the issue of political motives,
although we do not agree with Grinnell’s
conclusions.
59. On Halley and James II, see I.
Bernard Cohen and Robert E. Schofield, Isaac Newton’s Papers and Letters on
Natural Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958), pp. 397-424;
on Halley and Tillotson, British Library MSS Add. 17017, fols. 143, 145-146; MSS
Add. 4236, fols. 230, 233, 227.
60. W. R. Albury, “Halley’s Ode on
the Principia of
61.
Ibid., pp. 36-37.
62. H. W. Turnbull, ed., The
Correspondence of Isaac Newton, Vol. III (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1961), p. 279.
Revolution in his concern that his
name not be associated with Pepys, who was by that time suspected of
Jacobitism.
If
In the period after 1689
From Boyle’s endowed pulpit and in
their writings the Newtonians preached to London-based and exceedingly
prosperous congregations. They
extolled the virtues of self-restraint and public-mindedness while at the same
time assuring their congregations that prosperity came to the virtuous and that
providence permitted, even fostered, material rewards. Men must acknowledge God’s providence by
the cultivation of virtue, by the pursuit of what
With the lapsing of the Licensing
Act in 1695 and with the heating up of party politics in the late 1690s, the
liberal Anglican establishment, along with court and monarchy, found itself
under assault by the radical and republican Whigs. [66] With the freethinker John Toland in
the vanguard, they put forth materialistic and
63. Ibid., pp. 12-13; cf. Millicent B.
Rex, University Representation in
64. Margaret Jacob, “Newtonianism and
the Origins of the Enlightenment: A Reassessment,” Eighteenth Century
Studies, 1977, 11: 1-25; on the circulation of Servetus manuscripts,
see Lambeth Palace Library MS 933, fol. 74; cf. Jacob, The Newtonians, p.
221.
65. Memorandum made by David Gregory,
66. Jacob, The Newtonians,
264
pantheistic - to use the word
invented by Toland in 1705 - arguments to justify the rule of Parliament over
placemen and standing armies, of civic religion over established church, of
religious pluralism over a narrowly circumscribed toleration. From their pulpits the Boyle lecturers,
with Samuel Clarke as their most philosophically gifted spokesman, [67] put forth
arguments to justify order and stability, to maintain the hierarchical and
providential interpretation of the constitutional
settlement.
But if Anglican hegemony now owed so
much to Newtonian science, what did
III – The Newtonian vs Radical
Enlightenment
If we date the origins of the
European Enlightenment to the l690s in
The implications of this distinction
between the Newtonian and the Radical Enlightenments, based as it is on the
content of belief as well as on the social relations of ideas, are significant
for eighteenth-century European studies. For instance the characteristic
materialism of the High Enlightenment, embodied in the writings of
the
67. Samuel Clarke, A Demonstration of
the Being and Attributes of God: More Particularly in Answer to Mr. Hobbs,
Spinoza, and their Followers (London, 1705); cf. John Toland, Socinianism truly
Stated; Being An Example of fair Dealing in all Theological Controversys…
by a Pantheist to an Orthodox Friend (London, 1705); Giancarlo Carabelli,
Tolandiana (Florence: La Nuova Italia, 1975), pp. 119-120.
68. J.
E. McGuire, “Existence, Actuality and
Necessity: Newton on Space and Time,” Annals of Science, 1978, 35: 470;
on More and Newton as revealed in “De Gravitatione,” pp. 471,480-482; on
Spinoza, p. 493; quotation from J. E. McGuire, “Newton on Place, Time and God:
an Unpublished Source,” British Journal for the History of Science, 1978,
11:114-123, from Cambridge University Library MSS Add. 3965, section 13, fols.
445r-446r.
69. For an excellent illustration of
such complexity see J. E. McGuire, “Neoplatonism and Active Principles: Newton
and the Corpus Hermeticum,” in Robert S. Westman and J. E. McGuire,
Hermeticism and the Scientific Revolution (Los Angeles: William Andrews
Clark Memorial Library, University of California, 1977), pp.
120-125.
70. P. M. Heimann, “Science and the
English Enlightenment,” History of Science, 1978, 16:143-151; cf. R. S.
Westfall, Science and Religion in Seventeenth-Century
French philosophe Paul Henri
d’Holbach, appears increasingly to have been alive and well decades before he
wrote and to have flourished in republican circles on both sides of the Channel
from at least as early as 1710. New
evidence from Dutch archives reveals the elaborate social contacts of English
republicans, Toland and Collins in particular, with French Protestant refugees
who avidly read Spinoza while adopting Toland’s own word, “pantheist,” to
describe themselves. This early
coterie survived well into the 1750s, became deeply involved in Freemasonry in
the Netherlands, and gave refuge to a variety of French materialists, among them
the Abbé Yvon, who wrote so many of the essays on materialism for Diderot’s
Encyclopedie
(1751).
[71]
Jean Rousset de Missy (1686-1762),
one of the founders of Dutch Freemasonry, knew Toland and Collins in The Hague
in those early years (1710-1713), translated their works into French, and lived
on to participate both in the Dutch Revolution of 1747 and in the first decade
of the High Enlightenment, when materialism seemed everywhere triumphant.
[72] Now an old man, Rousset wrote to Prosper Marchand, who
had been a good friend to Collins, to praise the Encyclopédie. The intellectual framework within
which Rousset describes both Diderot’s achievement and his concern that the
remaining volumes will be suppressed by the censor establishes the continuity
between the natural philosophy of the English radicals and the materialism of
the Enlightenment:
Do you realize that if the theses
[of the Abbé de Prades] had been permitted at the same time as the 10 enormous
volumes of the Encyclopédie, it would have led rapidly to Pantheism; or
it would have freed the wits, the wise and courageous women, also the Italian,
English and French deists and atheists of the charade of Religion which is so
necessary in society if we are not to be slaughtered [by one another], and
useful for nothing else - and that is certainly enough; but [proudly?] I am “le
petit Encyclopédiste.” [73]
Pantheism, derived specifically from
the heresies of the English Revolution and transmitted by the English
Commonwealthmen, lived on well into the Enlightenment and indeed permeated its
clandestine literature. [74] Of course it merged with Spinozism as well as with
varieties of Cartesian materialism, all indigenously continental versions of
scientific naturalism.
Anglican science, conceptually and
mathematically brilliant though it was, failed to accomplish one of its aims, to
eradicate the radicalism of the English Revolution.
71. John Lough, The Contributors
to the Encyclopédie (London: Grant & Cutler, 1973), pp. 2-3; “Âme,” in
Encyclopédie, ed. Denis Diderot (Berne/Lausanne,
1781), Vol. II; “Immatérialisme,” in Encyclopédie, Vol. XVIII. For
Yvon’s membership in an
72. Jean Sgard, “Jean Rousset de
Missy,” Dictionnaire desjournalistes (Grenoble: Presses universitaires de
Grenoble, 1976); cf. Margaret Jacob, “Newtonian Science and Radical
Enlightenment,” Vistas in Astronomy, 1979, 22:545-555. On Marchand and Collins, see
James O’Higgins, S. J., Anthony Collins (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,
1970), p. 80; and various letters at the
73. Rousset de Missy to Prosper
Marchand, University of Leiden Library, Marchand MSS 2, fol. 47, 28/2, no year,
but from the context probably 1752. De Prades’s thesis was condemned in
January, 1752. The original reads:
“Savez vous que cela auroit été grand train vers le Panthéisme si ces Theses
eussent passé et en méme tems les 10 énormes vol. de L’Encyclopédie, on
débarassoit les beaux Esprits, les femmes savantes & galantes, les petits
maItres tant de déistes et d’athées Italiens & Anglois et francois du joug
de la Religion si nécessaire dans la société pour n’y être pas égorgé, et pas
pour autre chose, et c’en est bien assez, mais [altier?], je fais le petit
Encyclopédiste.”
74. Jacob, “The Radical
Enlightenment: Pantheists, Freemasons and Republicans,” forthcoming with Allen
& Unwin, Ltd., 1980.
266
In the process, however, both its
methodology and its metaphysics were shaped by the dialectics of revolution: as
a result scientific arguments gave vital ideological support to Protestant
monarchy. In this sense the triumph
of Newtonian science represents another victory for the Whig constitution. The Anglican origins of modern science
provide a new framework for integrating the history of science and English
constitutional history - to the enrichment of both.
267