The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
On the Role of Themata in Scientific
Thought
Science,
New Series,188 (4186)
Content
HHC: Index
added |
When the historian of science studies a product of
scientific work - a published paper, a laboratory record, a transcript of an
interview - he is dealing first of all with an event. A number of different facets of the event
can engage his attention. One can
distinguish at least eight such facets, corresponding to different types of
interesting questions:
First is of course the understanding of the scientific
content of the event (E) at a given time, both in contemporaneous terms and,
separately, in terms of what we now believe to be the case. What did the scientist claim was at
issue? What was he in fact
confronted with? For this we need
to establish the awareness, within the area of public scientific knowledge at
the time of the event, of the so-called scientific facts, data, laws, theories,
techniques, lore. I would include
under this heading the larger part of historical research on what are called
scientific world views, paradigms, and research programs; chiefly, however,
historians and scientists are still concerned with digging out the concepts and
propositions embodied in the event studied and with rendering them in empirical
and analytical language.
Second is the time trajectory of the state of shared (that is, “public”) scientific knowledge (let us call it S2) that led up to and perhaps goes beyond the time chosen above. Establishing this means, so to speak, the tracing of the world line of an idea or a subject of research, a line on which E is a point. Whether we are studying the problem of falling bodies from Kepler to
* The author is professor of physics at
328
This tracing of conceptual development and of the
“context of justification” is the most frequent and strongest activity of
historians of science and historically inclined science
educators.
Third is the more ephemeral personal aspect of the
activity in which E is embedded. Here we are in the context of discovery,
trying to understand the “nascent moment,” which may be poorly documented and
not necessarily appreciated or understood by the agent himself. Except for work on a few such figures as
Kepler or Einstein, scientists until recently have been rather impatient with
such studies, and so have philosophers. The very institutions of science - the
methods of publication, the meetings, the selection and training of young
scientists - are designed to minimize attention to this element. The success of science itself as a
shareable activity seems to be connected with this systematic neglect of what
Einstein called the “private struggle.” Moreover, the apparent contradiction
between the often “illogical” nature of actual discovery and the logical nature
of well-developed physical concepts is perceived by some as a threat to the very
foundations of science and rationality itself.
The alternative path is not easy. In one of his interviews, Einstein urged
historians of science to concentrate on comprehending what scientists were
aiming at, “how they thought and wrestled with their problems.” But he pointed out that the scholar would
have to have sufficient insight, a kind of Fingerspitzengefühl both for
the content of science and for the process of scientific research, as solid
facts about the creative phase are likely to be few; and that, as in physics
itself, the solution to historical problems may have to come by very indirect
means, the best outcome to be hoped for being not certainty but only a good
“probability” of being “correct anyway.”
One of the nicest testimonials on the contrary
orientations of scientists and of historians of science was provided by P. A. M.
Dirac not long ago. He agreed to
lecture about his work at the summer school on the History of 20th-Century
Physics at Varenna in 1972.
At the end of the first week, after having sat in on the lectures by the historians of science, Dirac began his own first lecture in this manner
(1):I have learned a great deal here, not only individual
facts about the history• of science, which I have picked up from various
lectures, but I have learned to appreciate the point of view of the historian of
science. It is really a very
different point of view from that of the research physicist. The research physicist, if he has made a
discovery, is then concerned with standing on the new vantage point which he has
gained and surveying the field in front of him. His question is, Where do we go from
here? What are the applications of
this new discovery? How far will it
go in elucidating the problems which are still before us? What will be the prime problems now
facing us?
He wants rather to forget the way by which he attained
this discovery. He proceeded along
a tortuous path, followed various false trails, and he doesn’t want to think of
these. He feels perhaps a bit
ashamed, disgusted with himself, that he took so long. He says to himself, What a lot of time I
wasted following this particular track when I should have seen at once that it
will lead nowhere. When a discovery
has been made, it usually seems so obvious that one is surprised that no one had
thought of it previously. With that
point of view, one doesn’t want to remember all the work that led up to the
making of the discovery.
Now, that is just the opposite to what the historian of
science wants. He wants to know the
various influences at work, the various intermediate steps, and he may have some
interest in the false trails. These
are rather contradictory points of view, and most of my life has been spent with
the point of view of the research physicist, and that involves forgetting as
quickly as possible the various intermediate steps.
However, with the understanding of what the historians
of science are concerned with, I have tried to think over the past, and have
done my best to remember the various incidents, things that happened 50 years ago. I have tried to figure out the
influences, the effect of the various teachers that I had and the training that
I received, to see how these things led me to the style of work which I followed
in later life.
A fourth component of historical research is indeed the establishment of the time trajectory of this largely private scientific activity (S
1) - the personal continuities and discontinuities in development. Now the event E at time t begins to be seen as the intersection of two trajectories, of two world lines, one for public science and one for private science, to use a shorthand terminology which is useful enough if not pushed too hard.Fifth, parallel to the trajectory of S1 and
shading into it as one of its boundaries is a band tracing the
psychobiographical development of the person whose work is being studied. We are dealing here with the new and
tantalizing field which explores the relation between a person’s scientific work
and his intimate style of thought and life. Frank Manuel’s A Portrait of Isaac
Newton (2) is
perhaps the best example available.
Sixth is unavoidably the study of the sociological
setting, conditions, influences, arising from colleagueship, the dynamics of
teamwork, the state of professionalization at the time, the institutional means
for funding, for evaluation and acceptance, and quantitative trends. Here we deal with the fields of science
policy studies and sociology of science in the narrower
sense.
Seventh, a similar band, parallel to and shading into
the trajectories of S1 and S2, deals with cultural
developments outside science that influence science or are influenced by it -
with questions concerning the feedback loops, science-technology-society and
science-literature, on which some of the most interesting work today is being
done.
Finally, there is the logical analysis of the work under
study. In my own development, first
as a student of P. W. Bridgman and Philipp Frank and later as their colleague,
interest in and respect for a valid analysis of the logic of science in fact
preceded work in the analysis of the more strictly historical aspects of a
case.
These eight areas of study are not separated by hard
barriers. To be sure, each has
invited its own specialization and thereby its own operational self-definition.
For each we could quickly put
forward the names of heroes and the shape of future hopes of development -
though we might now all agree, with various intensities of regret, that the
resolution of a real case in the history of science in all its ambiguities and
interdisciplinary connections into separable components is, after all, a
reductionistic strategy which our human limitations force or doom us to
employ.
The method of dealing with complex entities by
resolution or reduction found its use in science itself very early. One recalls, for example, the passage in
the Second Day of Galileo’s Dialogo,
329
where Salviati and Simplicio are discussing the motion
of an object released from the mast of a moving ship. Simplicio refuses Salviati’s proposal to
resolve the motion into a horizontal and a vertical component, one for free fall
straight to the center of the earth, the other with constant velocity in the
direction of initial motion. Perhaps we should credit Simplicio’s
resistance to a premonition that the whole method of resolution and reduction is
precarious and has no more necessity than any other methodological thema - that
is, it is neither verifiable nor falsifiable, and its usefulness depends
entirely on how soon you are satisfied with your results.
As we now know, Salviati was grossly exaggerating. Resolving the motion of the falling
object into two components in order to understand motion and its causes is only
the first step in an essentially infinite chain of resolutions. If one wants more detail about the
motion, other laws enter. The
appearance of the Coriolis force is responsible for an eastward deflection of
the object. The laws for falling
bodies in real media at various Reynolds numbers have to enter to calculate the
effect of friction and turbulence. The more detail one wants to know, the
more resolutions become necessary. The process would have become infinitely
regressive if an Occam’s Razor had not been invented in our century for cutting
off all side effects below a certain limit. Quantum physics did give us a way to
stop, owing to the uncertainty principle and the finite size of Planck’s
constant; they extinguish the meaningfulness of all further
questions.
And there is another lesson. The two components Salviati chose, while
they were plausible enough and even turned out to be useful, were not endowed
with any provable necessity over any other set of two or more components of
motion that might have been imagined. I mention this to acknowledge that my
list of components is not to be taken as the recital of an unchangeable, sacred
Eightfold Way. On the contrary, one
reason for making the list was to be able to conclude that it is incomplete in
an important respect. That is to
say, there remains a set of questions which are irresistible (to me, at any
rate); which cannot be handled naturally in this eightfold scheme at all; and
which lay bare a link between scientific activity and humanistic studies, a link
that few have studied so far.
Any listing of such questions will have to include
these: What is constant in the ever-shifting theory and practice of science -
what makes it one continuing enterprise, despite the apparently radical changes
of detail and focus of attention? What element remains valuable in theories
long after they have been disproved? What are the sources of energy that keep
certain scientific debates alive for decades? Why do scientists - and for that matter
also historians, philosophers, and sociologists of science - with good access to
the same information often come to hold so fundamentally different models of
explanation? Why do some scientists
hold on to models of explanation that are contrary to the evidence, sometimes at
enormous risks?
Why do scientists privately not accept a dichotomy
between the context of verification and that of discovery, and publicly often
accept it? If it is true, as
Einstein believed, that the process of formulating laws purely by deduction is
“far beyond the capacity of human thinking,” what may be guiding the leap across
the chasm between experience and basic principle? What is behind the obviously
quasi-esthetic choices which some scientists make - for example, in rejecting as
merely “ad hoc” a hypothesis that to other scientists may appear to be a
necessary doctrine? Are the grounds
from which such choices spring confined to the scientific imagination, or do
they extend beyond it?
To handle such questions I have proposed a ninth
component in the analysis of a scientific work. I have used for it a time-honored term,
“thematic analysis,” familiar from somewhat related uses in anthropology, art
criticism, musicology, and other fields. In many (perhaps most) past and present
concepts, methods, and propositions or hypotheses of science, there are elements
that function as themata, constraining or motivating the individual and
sometimes guiding (normalizing) or polarizing the scientific community. In the scientists’ own public
presentations of their work, and during any ensuing scientific controversy,
these elements are usually not explicitly at issue. The discussion seems to concern chiefly
the empirical content and the analytical content, that is, the repeatable
phenomena and the propositions concerning logic and mathematics. By way of a very rough analogy, I have
suggested that those two elements be considered the x and y coordinates of a
plane within which the discussion seems chiefly to proceed since the
“meaningfulness” of concepts is tested by the resolution of concepts or
propositions into those elements - “meaningful” in the sense that agreed-upon
rules generally exist for verifiability or falsifiability of the statements made
in that language.
Thus, in R. A. Millikan’s famous oil drop experiment the
question whether or not the electric charges on small objects always come in
multiples of some fundamental constant, called the charge of the electron, could
in principle have been resolved quickly by coming to terms on how and what was
being observed through the telescope or ultramicroscope when a particle was seen
to move in the view field, and whether and how to amend the equation for Stokes’
law for the fall of small objects by extrapolation of a correction term. If that were all, the lengthy fight about
the existence of a postulated “subelectron” would never have happened. But in 1910, and continuing for some
years afterward, the controversy between Millikan and Felix Ehrenhaft was joined
- at the intersection, as it were, of two sets of world
lines.
Analysis of the published research reports, of the
expressed motivations, and of the ever-hardening attitudes of the protagonists
on opposite sides of the question shows here, as in other cases, the strong role
of an early, unshakable commitment to opposite themata on the part of the
opponents; the one to the thema of discreteness as the fundamental explanatory
principle operating in electricity, the other to the thema of the continuum and
hence antiatomism. In Millikan’s
case the commitment to an atomistic explanation of electricity predated his
experimental verification and indeed helped him to pick his way through
initially indifferent data to support his contention. In the other, the growing dedication to
the antithema led to a veritable flood of
counter-experiments.
The themata that appear in science can, in our very
rough analogy, be presented as lying along a dimension orthogonal to the (xy) plane in which
verification and falsification can take place, hence somewhat like a z axis rising from it. While the xy plane does suffice for most discourse within science in the sense of a
public, consensual activity, it is the three-dimensional (xyz) space which is
required for a more complete analysis—whether historical,
330
philosophical, or psychological – of scientific
statements, processes, and controversies. (My argument is not to introduce thematic
discussions or even a self-conscious awareness of themata into the practice of
science itself. It is indeed one of
the great advantages of scientific activity that in the xy plane many
questions - for example, concerning the “reality” of scientific knowledge -
cannot be asked. Only when such
questions were ruled out of place in a laboratory did science begin to grow
rapidly.) It is fruitful to make
distinctions between three different uses of themata: the thematic concept, or
the thematic component of a concept (examples I have analyzed are the use of the
concept of symmetry and of the continuum); the methodological thema (such as the
preference for expressing the laws of science where possible in terms of
constancies, or extrema, or impotency); and the thematic proposition or thematic
hypothesis (exemplified by overarching statements such as Newton’s hypothesis
concerning the immobility of the center of the world, or the two principles of
special relativity theory).
The attitude I have taken in the task of identifying, ordering, and categorizing thematic elements in scientific discussions is to some degree analogous to that of a folklorist or anthropologist who listens to the epic stories for their underlying thematic structure and recurrences. While the analogy leaves much to be desired, there are more than superficial relations. For example, the awareness of themata which are sometimes held with obstinate loyalty helps one to explain the character of the discussion between antagonists far better than do scientific content and social surroundings alone. The attachment of physicists such as H. A. Lorentz, Henri Poincaré, and Max Abraham to the old electromagnetic world view and their discomfort with Einstein’s relativity theory become a good deal more understandable when the ether is thought of as operating as the embodiment of thematic concepts (for example, of the absolute and the plenum). Thus in their obituary for Abraham, Max von Laue and Max Born wrote perceptively
(3):[Abraham) found the abstractions of Einstein disgusting
in his very heart. He loved his
absolute ether, his field equations, his rigid electron, as a youth loves his
first passion whose memory cannot be erased by any later experience… His
opposition was grounded in physical, fundamental persuasions to which he, purely
in accord with his feelings, held on as long as possible… [As Abraham himself
once said] against the logical coherences he had no counterarguments; he
recognized and admired them as the only possible conclusion of the plan of
general relativity. But this plan
was to him thoroughly unsympathetic, and he hoped that the astronomical
observation would disconfirm it and bring the old, absolute ether again into
honor.
A finding of thematic analysis that appears to be
related to the dialectic nature of science as a public, consensus-seeking
activity is the frequent coupling of two themata in antithetical mode, as when a
proponent of the thema of atomism finds himself faced with the proponent of the
thema of the continuum. Antithetical couples - such as evolution
and devolution, constancy and change, complexity and simplicity, reductionism
and holism, hierarchy and unity, the efficacy of mathematics (for example,
geometry) versus the efficacy of mechanistic models as explanatory tools - are
not too difficult to discern, particularly in cases that involve a controversy
or a marked advance beyond the level of common work (4).
I have been impressed by how few themata there are - at
least in the physical sciences. I
have found about 50 singlets and doublets and occasional triplets so far, and I
suspect the total will turn out to be less than 100. The appearance of a new thema is rare.
Complementarity in 1927 and
chirality in the 1950’s are two of the most recent such additions in physics.
Related to that is the antiquity
and persistence of themata, right through scientific evolution and “revolution.”
Thus, the old antithesis of plenum
and void surfaced in the debate early this century on “molecular reality” -
indeed, it can also be found in the work of contemporary theoretical physicists.
One may even predict that, no
matter how radical the advances will seem in the near future, they will with
high probability still be fashioned in terms of currently used
themata.
The persistence in time, and the spread in the community
at a given time, of these relatively few themata may be what endows science,
despite all its growth and change, with what constant identity it has. The interdisciplinary sharing of themes
among various fields in sciences tells us something both about the meaning of
the enterprise as a whole and the commonality of the ground of imagination that
must be at work.
To illustrate some of these points, and to show that
current as well as historical cases are amenable to this analysis, I want to
focus on an example in one of the liveliest fields of physics today, as embodied
in publications of Steven Weinberg (5). The line tracing the
development of Weinberg’s thoughts intersects the trajectory of a stream of
developments in quantum electrodynamics initiated by Enrico Fermi in 1934 and
now basing itself on techniques started independently in the late 1940’s by R.
P. Feynman, Julian Schwinger, Freeman J. Dyson, and Sinitiro Tomonago. Other points on the trajectory include
recent discoveries by groups at CERN, Argonne Laboratory, and the National
Accelerator Laboratory. In thematic
terms, the “event” we shall study is only the latest in a very old sequence of
attempts, reaching past many revolutions and heady victories back to the first
scientist of recorded history; for the main preoccupation is the identification
of the fundamental constituent of which all matter is presumed to be
made.
To put it briefly, Weinberg, his collaborators, and
other groups have been working on the problem of finding common ground between
the four types of interaction (“forces”) that are now believed to account for
all physical phenomena: the gravitational interation that all particles
experience, the electromagnetic force that accounts for phenomena involving
charged particles and the interaction of light with matter, the “strong” nuclear
force that acts between members of the large family of elementary particles
called hadrons, and the “weak interaction” postulated to describe extremely
short-range interactions of some elementary particles (such as the scattering of
a neutrino by a neutron and the radioactive decay of a neutron into a proton, an
electron, and an antineutrino).
In 1967, Weinberg (and, independently, Abdus Salam of
331
the weak interaction is mediated by the so-called
intermediate vector boson (IVB) which, if it is found to exist, will have to be
exceedingly massive. Weinberg’s
proposal was that the mass-less photon and the very massive IVB are close
relatives - that the IVB’s are by and large members of the photon family but get
their mass (the appearance of their difference) by virtue of being associated
with broken gauge symmetry groups.
At the time Weinberg proposed the theory, “there was,”
he now notes (6), “no experimental evidence for or against it, and no immediate
prospects for getting any.” To this
day the IVB’s cannot be produced directly (for instance, in accelerators), but
indirect evidence for their existence has been reported. In a paper published under the names of
55 investigators from
seven institutions in a pan-European collaboration at the CERN laboratory (7),
two events were found in which a mu-neutrino was scattered by an electron, and
several hundred events in which a mu-neutrino was scattered by a neutron or a
proton. (The latter reaction showed
up nicely also on more recent experiments at Argonne National Laboratory and the
National Accelerator Laboratory.) This is evidence that the “neutral
current” reaction, a new kind of weak interaction predicted by Weinberg
involving the postulated neutral IVB, may be taking place, and so indirectly
supports the theory which makes these particles a member of the same family as
the photons.
Moreover, strong interactions also become amenable to
calculations with the same methods as are used for weak and electromagnetic
interactions. It is possible,
therefore, that the strong interactions are caused by exchange of particles that
belong to the same family as the photon and the IVB. “If these speculations are borne out by
further theoretical and experimental work,” Weinberg says in the last sentence
of his most recent survey (6, p. 59), “we shall have moved a
long way toward a unified view of nature.”
Now let us go to the beginning of this same report,
which is entitled “Unified theories of elementary-particle interaction,” and
look at it through eyes alert to themata. What, then, are the thematic conceptions,
methodological themata, and thematic suppositions that inhere in this search for
the IVB’s and their photon-like family membership?
We can readily catalog a few of the more evident themata
when we carefully scan just the first page of the article (8). It
begins:
One of man’s enduring hopes has been to find a few
simple general laws that would explain why nature, with all its seeming
complexity and variety, is the way it is. At the present moment the closest we can
come to a unified view of nature is a description in terms of elementary
particles and their mutual interactions. All ordinary matter is composed of just
those elementary particles that happen to possess both mass and (relative)
stability: the electron, the proton and the neutron. To these must be added the particles of
zero mass: the photon, or quantum of electromagnetic radiation, the neutrino,
which plays an essential role in certain kinds of radioactivity, and the
graviton, or quantum of gravitational radiation...
What strikes us at once is the acknowledgment that “one
of man’s enduring hopes has been to find a few simple general laws” and thereby
obtain a “unified” (the first word of the title) theory. Unification or synthesis, with its
promise of increased understanding through increased economy of thought, is a
member of a triplet of themata, one of its antithetical aspects being
multiplicity (or complexity, variety), the other being the theme we discussed
before, that of resolution rather than synthesis. Each of these three members of the
triplet has its uses. Here,
clearly, unification is taken to be preeminent. “… Why nature, with all its seeming
complexity and variety, is the way it is.” Kepler, who asked in the preface of the
Mysterium Cosmographicum why the planets are at the distances they are,
of the number and with the motions which we find them to have, “and not
otherwise,” would have agreed with this description of one of man’s enduring
hopes. So would most scientists
since. The second sentence,
however, bares a preconception which not all scientists will share. We find here a new thematic commitment,
that of constructing the desired unified view of nature out of “elementary
particles and their mutual interactions.” We hear the echo of Democritus’ “all is
atoms and void.” But Schrodinger
and his followers, to whom the fundamental tool of explanation was the
continuum, would not have agreed; nor would Einstein; nor would Heisenberg agree
in his latest phase, since he now claims that one cannot build matter out of
matter but must seek the base in formal principles, along lines he ascribes
explicitly to Plato. Nor, of
course, would biologists, psychologists, or social scientists be satisfied with
this particular unified view of nature, in terms of particles and their
interactions. A choice has been
made here, though a choice that promises indeed a breathtaking view of a
nature.
What is being conveyed in Weinberg’s opening by
“elementary”? A few sentences later
it is defined to mean that there is not now “any successful theory that explains
the elementary particles in terms of more elementary constituents.” Some day, to be sure, one may find “still
more elementary constituents, named quarks”; but until that time, so long as
“strenuous efforts” make it “impossible to break particles,” they are
elementary.
Their quality of being elementary anchors the whole
arrow of explanation, upward from these presumed elementary particles to the
antithetical entities, constructs (such as nuclei, atoms, or ordinary matter,
all of which are “composed” of elementary matter). The antiquity of that quest, from Thales
to Prout to J. J. Thomson to our day, is evident. These elementary particles, then, are
today’s true “atoms” in the sense of the Greek atomos. They form one leg of another triplet
of themata, the second being the construct made of and explained by these atoms
or elementary quanta, and the third being the notion of the continuum, the
indefinitely cuttable (9).
The list of elementary particles then consists of the electron, the proton, and the neutron. “To these must be added the particles of zero mass: the photon… - the neutrino - ... and the graviton.” We are here clearly in a world of particulate discreteness; although the wave property that inheres in such particles is of course not doubted, it simply is not part of the image that has captured attention and primacy
(10).The number and variety of elementary particles, Weinberg
says, is “bewildering.” But there
are ways of retaining sanity and gaining insight by mastering the bewildering
variety. The ordering of chaos by
means of the concept of hierarchy or levels or categories - a manageable few,
just four - comes to the rescue as a methodological theme. The division into four categories -
gravitation, electromagnetic interaction, strong interactions, and weak
interactions - is not merely a separation into separate pigeonholes for very
different birds. There is a real
hierarchy
332
here which orders the subsections, showing a sequence of ranges of interactions, from infinity to much less than 10
-14 centimeter.Already one can see from this brief outline that, as
Weinberg puts it, “a certain measure of unification has been achieved in making
sense of the world.” Helping to
make sense of the world in a way not possible through the demands of logicality
alone is indeed one of the chief functions of a thema. “We are still faced, however, with the
enormous problem of accounting for the baffling amount of elementary-particle
types and interactions.” Methodologically, the theory evokes more
than an echo of an older scheme of fourfold categories, one so magnificently
successful that it helped to rationalize the observable phenomena for some 2000
years: the four Elements, with their own internal hierarchy, from lightest to
heaviest, and their own rules of interaction. However, the new unification through
hierarchical ordering promises among its many advantages that two and perhaps
three of the forces in the four categories “have an underlying
identity.”
The way to discover this identity is through analogies
in behavior which would collapse the superficially different entities to a state
in which they share something more than membership in a hierarchical order.
This quest for something more is
answered by turning to the conception of family [for example (6, p. 55): “Our hopes of perceiving
an underlying identity in the weak and electromagnetic interactions lead us
naturally to suppose that there may be some larger gauge symmetry that forces
the photon and the intermediate vector boson into a single family”]. The chief explanatory tool on the road to
greater simplicity is this “family” connection, existing despite an “appearance”
of great differences - for example, the difference between the photon’s zero
mass and the necessarily very large mass of the intermediate vector boson. Throughout this article of Weinberg’s and
many others in this field, one of the recurring conceptions is precisely this
splendid one of groups, families, and superfamilies (“superfamilies of eight,
ten, or even more members”) (11).
The familial
relationships between the elementary particles are far more profound than in the
ad hoc families that were discovered in the chemical periodic table in the last
century or in, say, the work of Linnaeus. But the methodological use as a tool of
explanation is not qualitatively different. Let me take the occasion of the surfacing
of this fine anthropomorphic word to go back to Weinberg’s opening page, where
reference is made to “a few additional short-lived particles” and we are told
that “we can create a vast number of even shorter-lived species.” Elementary particle physics is sometimes
wryly referred to as zoology; and it is shot through and through with themes
that may well have, as many themes seem to me to have, their origins in a part
of the imagination that was formed prior to the conscious decision of the
researcher to become a scientist.
The technical report of, say, the analysis of a bubble chamber photograph
is cast largely in terms of a life-cycle story. It is a story of evolution and
devolution, of birth, adventures, and death. Particles enter on the scene, encounter
others, and produce a first generation of particles that subsequently decay,
giving rise to a second and perhaps a third generation. They are characterized by relatively
short or relatively long lives, by membership in families or
species.
Listening to these village tales told by physicists, one is aware that the terminology may initially not have been “seriously” meant. Yet the life-cycle thema works, and so do a number of other themata imported into the sciences from the world of human encounters. It has, incidentally, always amused me to see how strenuously the psychologists of the period around the turn of the century tried to gain added respectability by borrowing concepts from physics for the description of human relationships. Evidently they were unaware that they were reimporting conceptual tools when they themselves were closer to the real thing. One is reminded of the story of the bank building in
We have not yet finished with Weinberg’s first
page. Several other magnificent
themata begin to show themselves: isotropy and homogeneity (for example,
particles of the same species are, as far as we now know, “absolutely identical,
whether they occupy the same atom or lie at opposite ends of the universe”);
symmetry - a concept which I believe was first used explicitly and seriously in
modern physics on the first page of Einstein’s 1905 paper on relativity; and
conservation (“of energy and momentum at every instant”).
On later pages we would encounter the following
additional themata, among others: the efficacy of geometrical representation
(such as Feynman diagrams), the efficacy of integers as explanatory tools (the
debt of modern quantum mechanics to the holiest precept of Pythagoras), again
conservation (of charge), infinity and finiteness (of mass), more on symmetry
principles (12). And above all, models (6, p. 57); the
word “model” is probably one of the most frequently used words in the writings
by theoretical physicists.
In this manner we are brought to the last sentence in
the paper. It has been quoted
above, but we can now look at it in a somewhat new light: “If these speculations
are borne out by further theoretical and experimental work [meaning, by
analytical or formalistic as well as empirical content, or by y- and
x-axis representations] we shall have moved a long way toward a unified view of
nature” - that is, toward the fulfillment of one of man’s enduring hopes, hopes
that find expression in his themata, some new and many
ancient.
Lest it be thought that I have come as John the Baptist:
I have not, and would indeed like
to avoid his fate. Let me therefore
end with a list of limitations I see in the thematic analysis of scientific
work.
1) While themata can have a strong grip on the scientist
or the community, and can be the most interesting aspect of a given case, there
exist important parts of the history of science and of current work where
themata do not seem to enter prominently. In studying the case of the work of
Enrico Fermi and his group, I found it no great help to think of it
thematically.
2) Even if this were not true, I would not like it to be
thought that the themata in a scientific work are its chief reality. Otherwise, work in the history of
science would degenerate into descriptivism, and scientific findings would seem
to be on a par with
333
the tales of the old men in the hills of Albania, to
whom today’s story is just about as good or as bad as yesterday’s. There is in science evidently a sequence
of refinements, a rise and fall, and occasionally the abandonment or
introduction of themata. But also
there undoubtedly has been on the whole a progressive change to a more
inclusive, more powerful grasp on natural phenomena.
3) The hold of a thema on a scientist does not make him
right. It can mislead. Nor, for that matter, does the grip of a
thema make him necessarily wrong.
4) We need to know more about the origins of themata.
It is rather clear to me that an
approach like Peter Medawar’s (13),
stressing the connections between cognitive psychology and individual
scientific work, is a proper place to start.
5) The thematic commitment of a scientist typically is
remarkably long-lived. But it can
change. Examples are Wilhelm
Ostwald, who first turned against atomism and then reversed himself once more;
Planck; Einstein; and a few others.
Moreover, embracing a thema such as atomism in one field of physics
occasionally has not prevented the embrace of the opposite thema by the same
person for another field of physics. A case in point is Millikan’s
championship of the “atom” in electricity, even while he was struggling fiercely
against the quantum of light. Poincaré was conservative and ether-bound
when it came to relativity theory, but quite oppositely directed in quantum
theory.
6) Themata are shared by members of a community, with
minor variations among the individual scientists, in whom I see the primary
repository of themata. But some
themata have a career that can be conveniently understood in life-cycle terms.
That is, they rise, atrophy, and
fade away; explanatory devices such as macrocosmic-microcosmic correspondence,
inherent principles, teleological drives, action at a distance, space-filling
media, organismic interpretation, hidden mechanisms, and absolutes of space,
time, and simultaneity - they all once ruled strongly in physics. The detailed study of the mechanism of
such rise and decay is much needed.
7) There is always the danger of confusing thematic
analysis with something else: with Jungian archetypes, with metaphysics, with
paradigms and world views. (It
might well be that the latter two contain elements of themata. But the differences are overwhelming.
For example, thematic oppositions
persist during “normal science,” and themata persist through revolutionary
periods. To a much larger degree
than either paradigms or world views, thematic decisions seem to come more from
the individual than from the social surrounding.) While the thematic analysis may be
limited by the requirement of some firsthand experience with the scientific
material (again, Fingerspitzengefühl), the rewards of doing more specific
work on real cases seem to me far more evident than those to be had from
engaging in comparisons among different historiographic schools, or in
psychological or rational “reconstructions,” or in the preparation of
overarching, general treatises.
8) Finally, there is a need for self-awareness. The search for answers in the history of
science is itself imbued with themata, just as is the search for a unified
theory of elementary particles. One
must be prepared for the critique of those who are afflicted, not with one’s own
themata, but with their antithemata, and one must be ready to run up against the
limitations within which one necessarily works - as Einstein did in his frank
way when he said, “Adhering to the continuum originates with me not in a
prejudice, but arises out of the fact that I have been unable to think up
anything organic to take its place” (14). His own work is of course
testimony to the fact that one can turn such inherent limits of the scientific
imagination into strengths, rather than merely deploring or neglecting
them.
I. P. A. M. Dirac, in Topics in the History of 20th-Century Physics: Proceedings of the International School of Physics “Enrico Fermi” at Varenna, 1972, C. Weiner, Ed. (Academic Press, New York, in press).
2. F. E. Manuel, A Portrait of Isaac Newton
(Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1968).
3. M. von Laue and M. Born, Phys. Z. 24, 52
(1923).
4. Examples are given in G. Holton, Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein (Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1973), particularly parts I and 2.
S. For example, “Recent progress in unified gauge theory
of the weak, electromagnetic, and strong interactions,” Rev. Mod. Phys. 46, 255
(1974).
6. S. Weinberg, “Unified theories of elementary-particle
interaction,” Sci. Am.
231 (No. 1), 56 (1974).
7. F. J. Hasert et al., Phys. Lett. 46B, 121, 138
(1973).
8. Since not all themata appear in so many words, we
would properly need a second scanning, proceeding in larger units. The fact that this paper appeared in a
more popular journal rather than a professional archival publication helps our
purpose; somehow, scientists are more likely to reveal their thematic
assumptions when addressing general audiences.
9. The atom as thema does not have to refer to a natural
physical object such as the discrete elementary entities, the gamma particle,
the neutron, and the proton. It can
be an element from which much more formalistic entities are constructed. For example, later (6, p. 58) Weinberg
notes that the weak interactions, if they really have an intrinsic strength
comparable to that of the electromagnetic interactions, “can provide additional
corrections to isotopic spin symmetry.” Theoretical entities, no less than the
now more palpable nuclei or atoms or, for that matter, crystals, can be thought
of as a sum or aggregate composed of various terms, for example, a core term and
a number of correction terms.
10. As for the graviton, Weinberg remarks parenthetically
that it ‘interacts too weakly with matter for it to have been observed yet, but
there is no serious reason to doubt its existence.” It is a splendid and daring dismissal of
the weary Simplicio in Galileo’s dialogues who, since 1632, has been exclaiming
at just such a point: “What? So you
have not made a hundred tests, or even one? And yet you so freely declare it to be
certain?” [Galileo Galilei, Dialogue
Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, S. Drake, translator (Univ.
of California Press, Berkeley, 1953), p. 145].
11. “Families of elementary particles are believed to be a consequence of a symmetry principle known as isotopic spin symmetry, analogous to the rotational symmetry that produced the family of quantum states within the hydrogen atom. The grouping of these families of elementary particles into superfamilies (octets, decimets, and so on) was proposed independently in the early 1960’s by Murray Gell-Mann and Yuval Ne’eman” (6, p.
55).12. Symmetry principles provide “information about the
laws of nature on the deepest possible level,” symmetries that are “broken,”
chiral symmetries, and so on (6, pp. 55-56).
13. P. B. Medawar, induction and Intuition (American
Philosophical Society, Philadelphia, 1969).
14. A. Einstein, in Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist,
P. Schilpp, Ed. (Harper, New York, 1959), vol. 2, p.
686.
334