The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Joseph L. Henderson
Cultural Attitudes in
Psychological Perspective
Inner City
Books, Toronto, 1984, 72-78
HHC: Henderson proposes four basic
cultural attitudes: social, religious, aesthetic and philosophic. I reproduce his summary discussion of all four
which includes his assessment of a ‘scientific’ attitude.
Discussion of the Cultural Attitudes
Anyone who has understood and accepted my description
of the four attitudes, and can support my thesis that a psychological attitude
may also find its place among them, will require no further discussion. However, I am mindful of the difficulties some
people had in accepting these postulates when I first presented them in 1962. [78] They asked: What cultural forms besides mine had been
proposed by other students of culture? Why had I chosen these four attitudes and why
only four? Why not include a scientific
attitude? What relevance, if any, did I
think the four attitudes had to Jung’s four functions of the personality? What historical origin did I ascribe for the
appearance of four cultural attitudes? I
propose to answer these questions briefly in the order I have listed them.
I have found valuable support outside my own
psychological discipline among certain friends and colleagues who liked my
exposition of the attitudes and felt no need to intellectualize it. A similar type of acknowledgment came from
certain writings which fell into my hands at the right time to encourage me. The best of these was Irwin Edman’s Four Ways of Philosophy, which he presents
in four chapters entitled “Logical Faith,” “Social Criticism,” “Mystical
Insight,” and “Nature Understood.” I
found here many points of likeness to my cultural attitudes; specifically, logical
.faith corresponds to my philosophic attitude, social criticism to
the social attitude, mystical insight to the religious attitude and nature
understood to the aesthetic attitude.
I found a similar way of viewing culture among French
anthropologists, as described by Claude Lévi-Strauss in his beautifully worded
essay, “The Scope of Anthropology.” The
French anthropologists rescued anthropology from Durkheim’s
reduction “of all culture to one total social fact,” [79] just as Jung
rescued psychoanalysis from a similar reductive interpretation of culture based
on the sexual theory of neurosis established by Freud. Lévi-Strauss describes this new attempt to
rehabilitate a differentiated picture of culture:
Now, this analysis in depth was to permit Mauss,
without contradicting Durkheim... to reestablish
bridges - which at times had
72
been
imprudently destroyed - between his concern and the other sciences of man:
history, since the ethnographer deals in the particular, and also biology and
psychology... Too often since Durkheim - and even
more among some of those who believe themselves to be liberated from his
doctrinal grip - sociology had seemed like the product of a raid hastily
carried out at the expense of history, psychology, linguistics, economics, law,
and ethnography. To the booty of this
pillage, sociology was content to add its own labels; whatever problem was
permitted to it could be assured of receiving a prefabricated “sociological”
solution… Social facts do not reduce themselves to scattered fragments. They are lived by men, and subjective
consciousness is as much a form of their reality as their objective
characteristics. [80]
A social attitude is beautifully characterized in Mauss’s affirmation that what is essential in society:
is that
movement of all, the living aspect, the fleeting instant in which society
becomes, or in which men become, through feeling, conscious of themselves and
of their situation vis-a-vis others. [81]
Contrary to the sturdy, pragmatic assertions of
sociologists, any attempt to pin down this “living aspect” of social reality,
writes Lévi-Strauss:
… will remain largely illusory: we shall never
know if the other fellow whom we cannot, after all, become, fashions from the
elements of his social existence a synthesis which can exactly correspond to
that which we have worked out. [82]
As Lévi-Strauss indicates, we may use other cultural
attitudes to form those symbolic bridges which are necessary for communication,
one of which is an aesthetic attitude. This has led the anthropologists to create a
science of semiology, which, in the sense
that Ferdinand de Saussure employed it, includes
language, myth, “the oral and gestural signs of which
ritual is composed, marriage rules, kinship systems, and certain terms and
conditions of economic exchange.” [83] This all depends upon aesthetic apperception and in
studying these behavior patterns the anthropologist himself acquires on the one
hand an aesthetic detachment from the culture he studies, and on the other a
special kind of empathy with it. In the
first case, the field worker views the primitive society he has come to study
as a symbol of something which is predetermined by his own Western education,
and he tends to see this image as part of a universal pattern, without
antecedents but maintaining a
73
mysterious
correspondence to other forms in other places, regardless of diffusions of
custom or evolutionary change.
In contrast to this kind of aesthetic apperception,
with its detachment from the objects or persons of its study, we find those
field workers who immerse themselves so thoroughly in the mythology and ritual
of small societies that they almost become psychically identical with
them. This may lead certain enthusiasts
into grotesque forms of aesthetic imitation.
Sometimes, however, it leads anthropologists to genuine initiatory experiences
in the societies they have come to study, as we see in Carlos Castaneda’s
account of his shamanic apprenticeship, The
Teachings of Don Juan: A Yaqui
Way of Knowledge, and its excellent Jungian interpretation by Donald
Williams. [84]
The value of this is found in a projective identification
which, in the right circumstances, creates the mood for acquiring subjective
insights which may correspond to objective facts. At its best, it enables Lévi-Strauss to say:
Our science arrived at maturity the day that Western man began to see
he would never understand himself as long as there was a single race or people
on the surface of the earth that he treated as an object. [85]
Then, leaving the aesthetic attitude abruptly, he adds, “It was to
spread humanism to all humanity.” [86]
Humanism, as I have come to understand it
psychologically, comes from a special blend of religious and social attitudes. As Christianity lost its hierarchical
structure and became broadly socialized, from the time of the late Renaissance
in Europe, religion became anthropocentric as well as theocentric.
Lévi-Strauss speaks of the
very exceptional emotion which the anthropologist experiences when he
enters a house in which tradition, uninterrupted for four centuries, goes back
to the reign of Francis I... especially how many ties link him with that age in
which the New World was revealed to Europe by being laid open to ethnographical
inquiry! [87]
He therefore deplores the fact that it has taken so
long for anthropology to be recognized, but this is so because the heavy hand
of colonialism prevented the men of earlier times from recognizing the
authenticity of the primitive societies. Only with the approach of the modern era in
which we are still living was pure
74
anthropology
born. The first characteristic of this,
as Lévi-Strauss rightly asserts, “is of a
philosophical order”:
As Merleau-Ponty has written, each time the
sociologist (but it is the anthropologist he is thinking of) returns to the
living sources of his knowledge, to that which operates in him as a means of
understanding the cultural formations most remote from himself,
he is spontaneously indulging in philosophy... And, indeed, the field research
with which every anthropological career begins is the mother and wet-nurse of
doubt, the philosophical attitude par excellence. The “anthropological doubt” does not only
consist of knowing that one knows nothing, but of resolutely exposing what one
thought one knew, and indeed one’s very own ignorance... I think it is by its
more strictly philosophical method that anthropology is distinguished from
sociology. [88]
Thus we see that Lévi-Strauss outlines a series of
cultural attitudes for anthropology that neatly parallel my clinical
observation that these same four attitudes are also basic in general culture: the
social, religious, aesthetic and philosophic.
It sometimes seems that Jung’s four typological
functions, taken separately, subtend the cultural attitudes. In Psychological
Types, he speaks of two kinds of intuition in an introvert: that which
tends toward an aesthetic attitude, and that which inclines one toward a
philosophic attitude. [89] In other places, Jung seems to regard aestheticism as the product of the
two “perceptive” functions, intuition and sensation, while the philosophic or
social attitudes become identified with the two “rational” functions, thinking
and feeling. [90]
In his later work, however, Jung disclaims any
identity between cultural attitudes and psychological function. In his writings, it becomes clear that
intellectual understanding is not the exclusive property of the thinking
function. The perceptive functions,
intuition or sensation, may provide an approach to art and to some extent may
define the style in which an artist paints or writes or composes; but a true
work of art, like the successful result of a scientific experiment, stands on
its own feet regardless of the personal psychology of its creator or perceiver.
No matter how faithfully we develop the four functions
or understand them in other people, they do not account for the existence of
religious, philosophic, aesthetic or social values. Hence
75
there is
a remarkable difference between people of identical personality type and
function if they are differently oriented to culture. This suggests that a prerequisite for psychological
maturity lies in attaining cultural maturity no less than in developing one’s
personality in the context of an individual life situation. But where the personality functions and the
cultural attitudes do meet, they form very interesting combinations of what we
may call “life-style,” as illustrated by Joan Evans in Taste and
Temperament.
[91] I have also pointed out the relevance of Dr. Meiklejohn’s view of education as a means of providing such
a “listing of cultural groupings” (above, p. 26) as would certainly bring the
functions of personality into connection with a wide variety of cultural
attitudes.
Nor should the cultural attitudes be confused with
vocational ambitions. It has sometimes
been assumed that by culture I meant institutionalized cultural forms or the
roles people play in expressing them. Thus
a social attitude was thought to be equivalent to that of a political reformer
or social worker, an aesthetic attitude only embodied in an artist, a
philosophical attitude found in a full professor of philosophy, while a
religious attitude could be appropriately represented only by the devout member
of a church or by a priest or theologian. I use the term “attitude” in a sense that
cannot be equated with vocational choices. Any one of the four attitudes may be
experienced by anyone, regardless of vocation or personality. One comment that struck me as particularly
apt, when I first began to notice cultural attitudes, was made to me in a
personal conversation with the religious historian, Frederick Spiegelberg, in which he observed that clergymen, far from
always being religious, may be drawn to their calling by aesthetic, philosophic
or social interests. One might strive to
achieve equal development of all the attitudes; but I think this must be very
rare, and possibly not even desirable. The
most culturally alive people I know regard themselves as incomplete and are
eagerly learning and recombining new attitudes all their lives with all the
limitations of time in this respect.
(Ars
longa, vita brevis.)
In choosing and describing these four cultural
attitudes I am well aware that I may be open to the criticism of being
unwilling to subject my views to a rigorous scientific critique. It has been suggested, for instance, as
already mentioned, that I should have included a scientific attitude in my
list. I hope my previous exposition
shows why I did not do so, and that, in keeping my
76
fourfold
classification of attitudes as it is, I was not trying to burden analytical
psychology with still another set of “four functions.” Therefore, I repeat: So far as we know, the
functions of the personality are, by definition, found to be psychologically
constant whereas the cultures themselves are in a continual process of change
and reformation. Furthermore, I consider
that a scientific attitude is not primary but is a hybrid combining two other
attitudes, which it also increasingly shares with them: the philosophic and the
aesthetic. Two of the greatest originators
of science, Aristotle and Descartes, were imbued with a philosophic attitude by
which they sought to limit man’s subjectivity to a minimum in observing the
nature of man or God. A. similar kind of
objectivity was made possible by the adoption of an aesthetic attitude allowing
certain men to stand aside from life and from themselves, observing nature and
man from a significant distance. Starting
from this aesthetic attitude they have, like Leonardo da
Vinci, made remarkable discoveries of a scientific nature.
I do recognize, however, that there is something
unique in any evolved scientific attitude, which is neither philosophic nor aesthetic
but only itself, and it is precisely this sense of
uniqueness that we also find in the psychological attitude which animates the
heuristic method of our present study. It
may be that this method will reveal not only the existence of a psychological
attitude but that of a scientific attitude of which the psychological is a
part. But certainly, because of their so
very recent appearance in history, we cannot claim for science or psychology
the same epistemological authenticity that we can demonstrate in the four basic
cultural attitudes as they originated and grew out of history into their
contemporary forms. There is some
evidence of their original unity in primitive societies that have resisted
technological development. Although
absolutely pure cultures no longer exist, we can reconstruct many of the tribal
chantways or dance-dramas from ceremonials still in use,
where, far from the urban centers of civilization, they still maintain some of
their original integrity. If we were to
attend a Navaho healing ceremonial, or a Bushman rain dance, an Australian
initiation rite or an Eskimo hunting ritual, we would find that the meaning of
the entire culture is evoked in each one.
Such ceremonies are religious because they invoke the
presence of gods or demigods, mediated by a priest or medicine man. The
77
rites are
social because the physical health and social well-being of the individuals or
the tribe are intimately bound up with them. All the adults, and frequently the children,
participate actively in the rites to ensure both their food supply and their
spiritual welfare. Everything has its
place in the family groups of the food-gathering peoples, and in the totemic
groups of the hunters, planters and herdsmen. The rites are aesthetic by virtue of their
performance of dances in costume, accompanied by music or drumming, and
primitive people frequently leave records of this dance-drama, or pre-figure it
in rock-drawings, carvings and in sand or pollen paintings of incomparable
artistic merit. Finally, they are
philosophic in the sense that different strands of tribal lore are woven
together to provide a rational explanation of the origin of the rites embodied
in a creation myth. This explains the
cosmos, the evolution and present place of animals and men living within it
together, according to theory. I have
tried to expose the continuing presence of cultural attitudes today in
accordance with these probable origins.
78
Notes
78. Joseph L.
Henderson, “The Archetype of Culture.”
79. Claude
Levi-Strauss, “The Scope of Anthropology,” p. 11.
80. Ibid., pp. 13-16.
81. Ibid., p. 16.
82. Ibid.
83. Ibid., p. 17.
110
84. Williams, Border Crossings.
85. Lévi-Strauss,
“Scope of Anthropology,” p. HENDERSON.
86. Ibid., p.
HENDERSON.
87. Ibid., p.
HENDERSON.
88. Ibid., p. 43.
89. Jung, Psychological Types, CW 6, pars. 661-662.
90. Ibid., pars. 577-671.
91. Joan Evans, Taste and Temperament, pp. 30-44. Evans singles out two psychological functions
which she calls quick and slow and sees them in a
study of the visual arts, where each may display either an introverted or an
extroverted style of composition. The
quick style, which has decorative, levitational and
experimental features, suggests the function of intuition. The slow style is earth-connected, contained, undramatic but totally real - in contrast to the
imaginative flights of the quick style - and is therefore suggestive of the
function of sensation. She cleverly
points out how easily we may recognize these patterns not only in the visual
arts but in the way people dress and furnish their homes, and I have noticed
them myself in preferences people show for similar styles in architecture and
gardening.
111
The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy