The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Martin Heidegger
The Question Concerning Technology
[1954]
in William
Lovitt, The
Question Concerning Technology
and Other Essays, Harper Torchbooks,
1977, 3-35.
In what follows we shall be questioning concerning technology. Questioning builds a way. We would be advised, therefore, above all to
pay heed to the way, and not to fix our attention on isolated sentences
and topics. The way is a way of
thinking. All ways of thinking, more or
less perceptibly, lead through language in a manner that is extraordinary. We shall be questioning concerning technology,
and in so doing we should like to prepare a free relationship to it. The relationship will be free if it opens our
human existence to the essence of technology. [1] When we
1. “Essence” is the
traditional translation of the German noun Wesen.
One of Heidegger’s principal aims in
this essay is to seek the true meaning of essence through or by way of the
“correct” meaning. He will later show
that Wesen does not simply mean what
something is, but that it means, further, the way in which something
pursues its course, the way in which it remains through time as what it is. Heidegger writes elsewhere that the noun Wesen does not mean quidditas
originally, but rather “enduring as presence” (das
Währen als
Gegenwart). (See An introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Ralph Manheim
[New York: Doubleday, 1961], p. 59.) Wesen as a noun
derives from the verb wesen, which is
seldom used as such in modern German.
The verb survives primarily in inflected forms of the verb sein (to be) and in such words as the
adjective anwesend (present). The old verbal forms from which wesen stems meant to tarry or dwell. Heidegger repeatedly identifies wesen as “the same as währen
[to last or endure].” (See p. 30 below and SR 161.) As a verb, wesen
will usually be translated [here with “to
come to presence,” a rendering wherein the meaning “endure” should be strongly
heard. Occasionally it will be translated
“to essence,” and its gerund will be rendered with “essencing.” The noun Wesen
will regularly be translated “essence” until Heidegger’s explanatory
discussion is reached. Thereafter, in
this and the succeeding essays, it will often be translated with “coming to
presence.” In relation to all these
renderings, the reader should bear in mind a point that is of fundamental
importance to Heidegger, namely, that the root of wesen,
with its meaning “to dwell,” provides one integral component in the meaning
of the verb sein (to be). (Cf. An Introduction to Metaphysics, p. 59.)]
HHC:
[bracketed] displayed on page 4 of the
original
3
can respond to this essence, we shall be able to experience
the technological within its own bounds.
Technology is not equivalent to the essence of technology. When we are seeking the essence of “tree,” we
have to. become aware that That which pervades every
tree, as tree, is not itself a tree that can be encountered among all the other
trees.
Likewise, the essence of technology is by no means anything
technological. Thus we shall never
experience our relationship to the essence of technology so long as we merely
conceive and push forward the technological, put up with it, or evade it. Everywhere we remain unfree
and chained to technology, whether we passionately affirm or deny it. But we are delivered over to it in the worst
possible way when we regard it as something neutral; for this conception of it, [2] to which today we particularly like to
do homage, makes us utterly blind to the essence of technology.
According to ancient doctrine, the essence of a thing is considered to
be what the thing is. We ask the
question concerning technology when we ask what it is. Everyone knows the two statements that answer
our question. One says: Technology is a
means to an end. The other says:
Technology is a human activity. The two
definitions of technology belong together. For to posit ends and
procure and utilize the means to them is a human activity. The manufacture and utilization of equipment,
tools, and machines, the manufactured and used things themselves, and the needs
and ends that they serve, all belong to what tech-
2. “Conception” here
translates the noun Vorstellung. Elsewhere in this volume, Vorstellung will usually be translated by “representation,” and its related verb vorsteflen
by “to represent.” Both “conception”
and “representation” should suggest a placing or setting-up-before. Cf. the discussion of Vorstellung
in AWP. 131-132.
4
nology is. The whole complex of these contrivances is
technology. Technology itself is a
contrivance, or, in Latin, an instrumentum.
[3]
The current conception of technology, according to which it is a means
and a human activity, can therefore be called the instrumental and
anthropological definition of technology.
Who would ever deny that it is correct?
It is in obvious conformity with what we are envisioning when we talk
about technology. The instrumental definition
of technology is indeed so uncannily correct that it even holds for modern
technology, of which, in other respects, we maintain with some justification
that it is, in contrast to the older handwork technology, something completely
different and therefore new. Even the
power plant with its turbines and generators is a man-made means to an end
established by man. Even the jet
aircraft and the high-frequency apparatus are means to ends. A radar station is of course less simple than
a weather vane. To be sure, the construction
of a high-frequency apparatus requires the interlocking of various processes of
technical-industrial production. And certainly
a sawmill in a secluded valley of the Black Forest is a primitive means compared
with the hydroelectric plant in the Rhine River.
But this much remains correct: modern technology too is a means to an
end. That is why the instrumental
conception of technology conditions every attempt to bring man into the right
relation to technology. Everything
depends on our manipulating technology in the proper manner as a means. We will, as we say, “get” technology
“spiritually in hand.” We will master
it. The will to mastery becomes all the
more urgent the more technology threatens to slip from human control.
But suppose now that technology were no mere
means, how would it stand with the will to master it? Yet we said, did we
3. Instrumentum
signifies that which functions to heap or build up or to arrange. Heidegger here equates it with the noun Einrichtung, translated “contrivance,” which
can also mean arrangement, adjustment, furnishing, or equipment. In accordance with his dictum that the true
must be sought by way of the correct, Heidegger here anticipates with his
identification of technology as an instrumentum
and an Einrichtung his later “true”
characterization of technology in terms of setting-in-place, ordering, Enframing, and standing-reserve.
5
not, that the instrumental definition of technology is
correct? To be sure.
The correct always fixes upon something
pertinent in whatever is under consideration.
However, in order to be correct, this fixing by no means needs to
uncover the thing in question in its essence. Only at the point where such an uncovering
happens does the true come to pass. [4]
For that reason the
merely correct is not yet the true. Only
the true brings us into a free relationship with that which concerns us from
out of its essence. Accordingly, the
.correct instrumental definition of technology still does not show us
technology’s essence. In order that we
may arrive at this, or at least come close to it, we must seek the true
by way of the correct. We must ask: What
is the instrumental itself? Within what
do such things as means and end belong? A
means is that whereby something is effected and thus
attained. Whatever has an effect as its
consequence is called a cause. But not
only that by means of which something else is effected is
a cause. The end in keeping with which
the kind of means to be used is determined is also considered a cause. Wherever ends are pursued and means are
employed, wherever instrumentality reigns, there reigns causality.
For centuries philosophy has taught that there are four causes: (1) the
causa materialis,
the material, the matter out of which, for example, a silver chalice is
made; (2) the causa formalis,
the form, the shape into which the material enters; (3) the causa finalis, the
end, for example, the sacrificial rite in relation to which the chalice
required is determined as to its form and matter; (4) the causa efficiens, which
brings about the effect that is the finished, actual chalice, in this instance,
the silversmith. What technology is,
when represented as a means, discloses itself when we trace instrumentality
back to fourfold causality.
But suppose that causality, for its part, is veiled in darkness with
respect to what it is? Certainly for
centuries we have acted as though the doctrine of the four causes had fallen
from heaven as a truth as clear as daylight. But it might be that the time has come to ask,
Why are there just four causes? In relation to the aforementioned four, what
does “cause” really mean? From
4. “Come to
pass” translates sich ereignet.
For a discussion of the fuller
meaning of the verb ereignen, see T 38
n. 4, 45.
6
whence does it come that the causal character of the
four causes is so unifiedly determined that they
belong together?
So long as we do not allow ourselves to go into these questions,
causality, and with it instrumentality, and with the latter the accepted
definition of technology, remain obscure and groundless.
For a long time we have been accustomed to representing cause as that
which brings something about. In this
connection, to bring about means to obtain results, effects. The causa efficiens, but one among the four causes, sets the
standard for all causality. This goes so
far that we no longer even count the causa finalis, telic finality, as causality. Causa, casus, belongs to the verb cadere,
“to fall,” and means that which brings it about that something falls out as
a result in such and such a way. The
doctrine of the four causes goes back to Aristotle. But everything that later ages seek in Greek
thought under the conception and rubric “causality,” in the realm of Greek
thought and for Greek thought per se has simply nothing at all to do with
bringing about and effecting. What we
call cause [Ursache] and
the Romans call causa is called aition by the Greeks, that to which something
else is indebted [das, was ein
anderes verschuldet]. [5] The four causes are the
ways, all belonging at once to each other, of being responsible for something
else. An example can clarify this.
Silver is that out of which the silver chalice is made. As this matter (kyle), it is co-responsible for the chalice. The chalice is indebted to, i.e., owes thanks
to, the silver for that out of which it consists. But the sacrificial vessel is indebted not
only to the silver. As a chalice, that
which is indebted to the silver appears in the aspect of a chalice and not in
that of a brooch or a ring. Thus the
sacrificial vessel is at the same time indebted to the aspect (eidos) of chaliceness. Both the silver into which the aspect is
admitted as chalice and the aspect in which the silver appears are in their
respective ways co-responsible for the sacrificial vessel.
5. Das,
was ein anderes verschuldet is a quite idomatic
expression that here would mean to many German readers
“that which is the cause of something else.” The verb verschulden
actually has a wide range of meanings - to be indebted, to owe, to be
guilty, to be responsible for or to, to cause. Heidegger intends to awaken all these meanings
and to have connotations of mutual interdependence sound throughout this
passage.
But there remains yet a third that is above all responsible for the
sacrificial vessel. It is that which in
advance confines the chalice within the realm of consecration and bestowal. [6] Through this the chalice
is circumscribed as sacrificial vessel. Circumscribing gives bounds to the thing. With the bounds the thing does not stop;
rather from out of them it begins to be what, after production, it will be. That which gives bounds, that which completes,
in this sense is called in Greek telos, which
is all too often translated as “aim” or “purpose,” and so misinterpreted. The telos is
responsible for what as matter and for what as aspect are together co-responsible
for the sacrificial vessel.
Finally there is a fourth participant in the responsibility for the
finished sacrificial vessel’s lying before us ready for use, i.e., the
silversmith - but not at all because he, in working, brings about the finished
sacrificial chalice as if it were the effect of a making; the silversmith is
not a causa efficiens.
The Aristotelian doctrine neither knows the cause that is named by this
term nor uses a Greek word that would correspond to it.
The silversmith considers carefully and gathers together the three
aforementioned ways of being responsible and indebted. To consider carefully [uberlegen]
is in Greek legein, logos. Legein is rooted
in apophainesthai, to bring forward
into appearance. The silversmith is
co-responsible as that from whence the sacrificial vessel’s bringing forth and
resting-in-self take and retain their first departure. The three previously mentioned ways of being
responsible owe thanks to the pondering of the silversmith for the “that” and.
the “how” of their coming into appearance and into play for the production of
the sacrificial vessel.
Thus four ways of being responsible hold sway in the sacrificial vessel
that lies ready before us. They differ
from one another, yet they belong together. What unites them from the beginning? In what does this playing in unison of the
four ways of being
6. Literally, “confines
into” - the German preposition in with the accusative. Heidegger often uses this construction in ways
that are unusual in German, as they would be in English. It will ordinarily be translated here by
“within” so as to distinguish it from “in” used to translate in with the
dative.
8
responsible play? What
is the source of the unity of the four causes? What, after all, does this owing and being
responsible mean, thought as the Greeks thought it?
Today we are too easily inclined either to understand being responsible
and being indebted moralistically as a lapse, or else to construe them in terms
of effecting. In either case we bar to
ourselves the way to the primal meaning of that which is later called
causality. So long as this way is not
opened up to us we shall also fail to see what instrumentality, which is based
on causality, actually is.
In order to guard against such misinterpretations of being responsible
and being indebted, let us clarify the four ways of being responsible in terms
of that for which they are responsible. According
to our example, they are responsible for the silver chalice’s lying ready before us as a sacrificial vessel. Lying before and lying ready (hypokeisthai) characterize the presencing
of something that presences. The four
ways of being responsible bring something into appearance. They let it come forth into presencing [An-wesen]. [7] They set it free to that
place and so start it on its way, namely, into its complete arrival. The principal characteristic of being
responsible is this starting something on its way into arrival. It is in the sense of such a starting something
on its way into arrival that being responsible is an occasioning or an inducing
to go forward [Ver-an-lassen]. [8] On the
7. By writing An-wesen, Heidegger stresses the composition of the verb anwesen, translated as “to presence.” The verb consists of wesen
(literally, to continue or endure) with the prepositional prefix an- (at,
to, toward). It is man who must receive presencing, man to whom it comes as enduring. Cf. On Time
and Being, trans. Joan Stambaugh (New York:
Harper & Row, 1972), p. 12.
8. Ver-an-lassen
is Heidegger’s writing of the verb veranlassen
in noun form, now hyphenated to bring out its meaning. Veranlassen
ordinarily means to occasion, to cause, to bring about, to
call forth. Its use here relates back to
the use of anlassen (to leave
[something] on, to let loose, to set going), here translated “to start
something on its way.” Anlassen has just been similarly written as an-lassen so as to emphasize its composition from lassen (to let or leave) and an (to or
toward). One of the functions of the
German prefix ver- is to intensify the
force of a verb. André Préau quotes Heidegger as saying: “Ver-an-lassen
is more active than an-lassen. The ver-,
as it were, pushes the latter toward a doing [vers
un faire].” Cf.
Martin Heidegger, Essais et
Conferences (Paris: Gallimard, 1958), p. 16 n.
basis of a look at what the Greeks experienced in being responsible,
in aitia, we now give this verb “to
occasion” a more inclusive meaning, so that it now is the name for the essence of
causality thought as the Greeks thought it. The common and narrower meaning of “occasion”
in contrast is nothing more than striking against and releasing, and means a
kind of secondary cause within the whole of causality.
But in what, then, does the playing in unison of the four ways of
occasioning play? They let what is not
yet present arrive into presencing. Accordingly, they are unifiedly
ruled over by a bringing that brings what presences into appearance. Plato tells us what this bringing is in a
sentence from the Symposium (205b): [HHC: Greek not reproduced]. “Every
occasion for whatever passes over and goes forward into presencing
from that which is not presencing is poiesis, is bringing-forth [Her-vor-bringen].” [9]
It is of utmost importance that we think bringing-forth in its full
scope and at the same time in the sense in which the Greeks thought it. Not only handcraft manufacture, not only
artistic and poetical bringing into appearance and concrete imagery, is a
bringing-forth, poiesis. Physis also, the
arising of something from out of itself, is a bringing-forth, poiesis. Physis is indeed poiesis
in the highest sense. For what presences by means of physis
has the bursting open belonging to bringing-forth, e.g., the bursting of a
blossom into bloom, in itself (en heautōi).
In contrast, what is brought forth
by the artisan or the artist, e.g.,
9. The full gamut of meaning
for the verb hervorbringen, here functioning
as a noun, includes to bring forth or produce, to generate or beget, to utter,
to elicit. Heidegger intends that all of
these nuances be heard. He hyphenates
the word in order to emphasize its adverbial prefixes, her- (here or
hither) and vor- (forward or forth). Heidegger elsewhere makes specific the meaning
resident in Her-vor-bringen for him by
utilizing those prefixes independently. Thus he says (translating literally),
“Bringing-forth-hither brings hither out of concealment, forth into unconcealment” (cf. below, p. 11); and - after identifying
working (wirken) and her-vor-bringen - he says that working must be understood
as “bringing hither-into unconcealment, forth-into
presencing” (SR 161). Because of the awkwardness of the English
phrase “to bring forth hither,” it has not been possible to include in the
translation of her-vor-bringen the nuance of
meaning that her- provides.
10
the silver chalice, has the bursting open belonging to
bringing-forth not in itself, but in another (en allōi),
in the craftsman or artist.
The modes of occasioning, the four causes, are at play, then, within
bringing-forth. Through bringing-forth,
the growing things of nature as well as whatever is completed through the
crafts and the arts come at any given time to their appearance.
But how does bringing-forth happen, be it in nature
or in handwork and art? What is
the bringing-forth in which the fourfold way of occasioning plays? Occasioning has to do with the presencing [Anwesen] of
that which at any given time comes to appearance in bringing-forth. Bringing-forth brings hither out of
concealment forth into unconcealment. Bringing-forth comes to pass only insofar as
something concealed comes into unconcealment. This coming rests and moves freely within what
we call revealing [das Entbergen]. [10] The
Greeks have the word
10. The verb entbergen (to reveal) and the allied noun Entbergung (revealing) are unique to
Heidegger. Because of the exigencies of
translation, entbergen must usually be
translated with “revealing,” and the presence of Entbergung,
which is rather infrequently used, has therefore regrettably been obscured
for want of an appropriate English noun as alternative that would be
sufficiently active in meaning. Entbergen and Entbergung
are formed from the verb bergen
and the verbal prefix ent-. Bergen means to rescue, to recover, to
secure, to harbor, to conceal. Ent- is used in German verbs to connote in
one way or another a change from an existing situation.
It can mean “forth” or “out” or can
connote a change that is the negating of a former condition. Entbergen connotes
an opening out from protective concealing, a harboring forth. For a presentation of Heidegger’s central
tenet that it is only as protected and preserved - and that means as enclosed
and secure - that anything is set free to endure, to continue as that which it
is, i.e., to be, see “Building Dwelling Thinking” in Poetry, Language,
Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), p.
149, and cf. p. 25 below.
Entbergen
and Entbergung
join a family of words all formed from Bergen-verbergen
(to conceal), Verborgenheit (concealment),
das Verbor gene (the
concealed), Unverborgenheit (unconcealment), das Llnverborgene (the unconcealed) - of which
Heidegger makes frequent use. The lack
of viable English words sufficiently numerous to permit a similar use of but
one fundamental stem has made it necessary to obscure, through the use of
“reveal,” the close relationship among all the words just mentioned. None of the English words used – “reveal,”
“conceal,” “unconceal” - evinces with any adequacy
the meaning resident in bergen
itself; yet the reader should be constantly aware that the full range of
connotation present in bergen sounds
for Heidegger within all these, its derivatives.
aletheia for
revealing. The Romans translate this
with veritas. We say “truth” and usually understand it
as the correctness of an idea.
But where have we strayed to? We
are questioning concerning technology, and we have arrived now at aletheia, at revealing. What has the essence of technology to do with
revealing? The answer: everything. For every bringing-forth is grounded in
revealing. Bringing-forth, indeed, gathers
within itself the four modes of occasioning – causality - and rules them
throughout. Within its domain belong end
and means, belongs instrumentality. [11] Instrumentality is
considered to be the fundamental characteristic of technology. If we inquire, step by step, into what
technology, represented as means, actually is, then we shall arrive at
revealing. The possibility of all
productive manufacturing lies in revealing.
Technology is therefore no mere means. Technology is a way of revealing. If we give heed to this, then another whole
realm for the essence of technology will open itself up to us. It is the realm of revealing, i.e., of truth. [12]
This prospect strikes us as strange. Indeed, it should do so, should do so as
persistently as possible and with so much urgency that we will finally take
seriously the simple question of what the name “technology” means. The word stems from the Greek. Technikon means that which belongs to techne. We
must observe
11. Here and elsewhere
“belongs within” translates the German gehört
in with the accusative (literally, belongs into), an unusual usage that
Heidegger often employs. The regular
German construction is gehort zu (belongs to). With the use of “belongs into,” Heidegger
intends to suggest a relationship involving origin.
12. Heidegger here
hyphenates the word Wahrheit (truth) so
as to expose its stem, wahr. He points out elsewhere that words with
this stem have a common derivation and underlying meaning (SR 165). Such words often show the connotations of
attentive watchfulness and guarding that he there finds in their Greek
cognates, horaa, are, e.g., wahren (to watch over and keep safe) and bewahren (to preserve). Hyphenating Wahrheit
draws it overtly into this circle of meaning. It points to the fact that in truth, which is unconcealment (Unverborgenheit),
a safekeeping carries itself Out. Wahrheit thus offers here a very close
parallel to its companion noun Entbergung (revealing;
literally, harboring forth), built on bergen
(to rescue, to harbor, to conceal). See
n. 10, above. For a further discussion
of words built around wahr, see T 42,
n. 9.
12
two things with respect to the meaning of this word. One is that techne
is the name not only for the activities and skills of the craftsman, but
also for the arts of the mind and the fine arts. Technë belongs
to bringing-forth, to poiësis; it is
something poietic.
The other point that we should observe with regard to techne is even more important. From earliest times until Plato the word techne is linked with the word episteme. Both words are names for knowing in the
widest sense. They mean to be entirely
at home in something, to understand and be expert in it. Such knowing provides an opening up. As an opening up it is a revealing. Aristotle, in a discussion of special
importance (Nicomachean Ethics, Bk. VI, chaps.
3 and 4), distinguishes between episteme and techne
and indeed with respect to what and how they reveal. Technë is
a mode of aletheuein. It reveals whatever does not bring itself
forth and does not yet lie here before us, whatever can look and turn out now
one way and now another. Whoever builds
a house or a ship or forges a sacrificial chalice reveals what is to be brought
forth, according to the perspectives of the four modes of occasioning. This revealing gathers together in advance the
aspect and the matter of ship or house, with a view to the finished thing
envisioned as completed, and from this gathering determines the manner of its
construction. Thus what is decisive in techne does not lie at all in making and
manipulating nor in the using of means, but rather in
the aforementioned revealing. It is as revealing,
and not as manufacturing, that techne is
a bringing-forth.
Thus the clue to what the word techne
means and to how the Greeks defined it leads us into the same context that
opened itself to us when we pursued the question of what instrumentality as
such in truth might be.
Technology is a mode of revealing. Technology comes to presence [West] in
the realm where revealing and unconcealment take
place, where aletheia, truth, happens.
In opposition to this definition of the essential domain of technology,
one can object that it indeed holds for Greek thought and that at best it might
apply to the techniques of the handcraftsman, but
that it simply does not fit modern machine-powered technology. And it is precisely the latter and
it alone that is the disturbing thing, that moves us to ask
the question concerning technology per se. It is said that modern technology is something
incomparably different from all earlier technologies because it is based on
modern physics as an exact science. Meanwhile
we have come to understand more clearly that the reverse holds true as well:
Modern physics, as experimental, is dependent upon technical apparatus and upon
progress in the building of apparatus. The
establishing of this mutual relationship between technology and physics is
correct. But it remains a merely historiographical establishing of facts and says nothing
about that in which this mutual relationship is grounded. The decisive question still remains: Of what
essence is modern technology that it happens to think of putting exact science
to use?
What is modern technology? It
too is a revealing. Only when we allow
our attention to rest on this fundamental characteristic does that which is new
in modern technology show itself to us.
And yet the revealing that holds sway throughout modern technology does
not unfold into a bringing-forth in the sense of poiesis.
The revealing that rules in modern
technology is a challenging [Herausfordern], [13]
which puts to nature the
unreasonable demand that it supply energy that can be extracted and stored as
such. But does this not hold true for
the old windmill as well? No. Its sails do indeed turn in the wind; they are
left entirely to the wind’s blowing. But
the windmill does not unlock energy from the air currents in order to store it.
In contrast, a tract of land is challenged into the putting out of coal
and ore. The earth now reveals itself as
a coal mining district, the soil as a mineral deposit. The field that the peasant formerly cultivated
and set in order [besteilte] appears
differently than it did when to set in order still meant to take care of and
13. Herausfordern
means to challenge, to call forth or summon to action, to demand
positively, to provoke. It is composed
of the verb fordern (to demand, to
summon, to challenge) and the adverbial prefixes her- (hither) and aus- (out). The verb might be rendered very literally as
“to demand out hither.” The structural
similarity between herausfordern and her-vorbringen (to bring forth hither) is readily apparent.
It serves of itself to point up the relation
subsisting between the two modes of revealing of which the verbs speak - modes
that, in the very distinctive ways peculiar to them, occasion a coming forth
into unconcealment and presencing.
See below, 29-30.
14
to maintain. The work
of the peasant does not challenge the soil of the field. In the sowing of the grain it places the seed
in the keeping of the forces of growth and watches over its increase. But meanwhile even the cultivation of the
field has come under the grip of another kind of setting-in-order, which sets
upon [stellt] nature. [14] It sets upon it in the
sense of challenging it. Agriculture is
now the mechanized food industry. Air is
now set upon to yield nitrogen, the earth to yield ore, ore to yield uranium,
for example; uranium is set upon to yield atomic energy, which can be released
either for destruction or for peaceful use.
This setting-upon that challenges forth the energies of nature is an
expediting [Pördern], and in two ways. It expedites in that it unlocks and exposes. Yet that expediting is always itself directed
from the beginning toward furthering something else, i.e., toward driving on to
the maximum yield at the minimum expense. The coal that has been hauled out in some
mining district has not been supplied in order that it may simply be present
somewhere or other. It is stockpiled;
that is, it is on call, ready to deliver the sun’s warmth that is stored in it.
The sun’s warmth is challenged forth for
heat, which in turn is ordered to deliver steam whose pressure turns the wheels
that keep a factory running.
14. The verb stellen (to place or set) has a wide variety
of uses. It can mean to put in place, to
order, to arrange, to furnish or supply, and, in a military context, to
challenge or engage. Here Heidegger sees
the connotations of herausfordern (to
challenge, to call forth, to demand out hither) as fundamentally determinative
of the meaning of stellen, and this
remains true throughout his ensuing discussion. The translation of stellen
with “to set upon” is intended to carry this meaning. The connotations of setting in place and of
supplying that lie within the word stellen remain
strongly present in Heidegger’s repeated use of the verb hereafter, however,
since the “setting-upon” of which it speaks is inherently a setting in place so
as to supply. Where these latter
meanings come decisively to the fore, stellen
has been translated with “to set” or “to set up,” or, rarely, with “to
supply.”
Stellen
embraces the meanings of a
whole family of verbs: besteilen (to
order, command; to set in order), vorsteilen
(to represent), sicherstellen (to
secure), nachstellen (to entrap), verstellen (to block or disguise), herstelien (to produce, to set here), darstelien (to present or exhibit), and so
on. In these verbs the various nuances
within stellen are reinforced and made
specific. All these meanings are
gathered together in Heidegger’s unique use of the word that is pivotal for
him, Ge-stell (Enframing).
Cf. pp. 19 ff. See also the opening paragraph of “The
Turning,” pp. 36-37.
The hydroelectric plant is set into the current of the Rhine. It sets the Rhine to supplying its hydraulic
pressure, which then sets the turbines turning. This turning sets those machines in motion
whose thrust sets going the electric current for which the long-distance power
station and its network of cables are set up to dispatch electricity. [15] In the context of the
interlocking processes pertaining to the orderly disposition of electrical
energy, even the Rhine itself appears as something at our command. The hydroelectric plant is not built into the
Rhine River as was the old wooden bridge that joined bank with bank for
hundreds of years. Rather the river is
dammed up into the power plant. What
the river is now, namely, a water power supplier,
derives from out of the essence of the power station. In order that we may even remotely consider
the monstrousness that reigns here, let us ponder for a moment the contrast
that speaks out of the two titles, “The Rhine” as dammed up into the power works,
and “The Rhine” as uttered out of the art work, in Hölderlin’s
hymn by that name. But, it will be
replied, the Rhine is still a river in the landscape, is it not? Perhaps. But how? In no other way than as an object on call for
inspection by a tour group ordered there by the vacation industry.
The revealing that rules throughout modern technology has the character
of a setting-upon, in the sense of a challenging-forth. That challenging happens in that the energy
concealed in nature is unlocked, what is unlocked is transformed, what is
transformed is stored up, what is stored up is, in turn, distributed, and what
is distributed is switched about ever anew. Unlocking, transforming, storing, distributing,
and switching about are ways of revealing. But the revealing never simply comes to an
end. Neither does it run off into the
indeterminate. The revealing reveals to
itself its own manifoldly interlocking paths, through
regulating their course. This regulating
itself is, for its part, everywhere secured. Regulating and securing even become the chief
characteristics of the challenging revealing.
15. In these two sentences,
in order to show something of the manner in which Heidegger gathers together a
family of meanings, a series of stellen verbs
- stellen (three times); herstellen,
bestellen - have been translated with
verbal expressions formed around “set.” For the usual meanings of these verbs, see n.
14.
16
What kind of unconcealment is it, then, that
is peculiar to that which comes to stand forth through this setting-upon that
challenges? Everywhere everything is
ordered to stand by, to be immediately at hand, indeed to stand there just so
that it may be on call for a further ordering. Whatever is ordered about in this way has its
own standing. We call it the
standing-reserve [Bestand]. [16] The word expresses
here something more, and something more essential, than mere “stock.” The name “standing-reserve” assumes the rank
of an inclusive rubric. It designates
nothing less than the way in which everything presences that is wrought upon by
the challenging revealing. Whatever
stands by in the sense of standing-reserve no longer stands over against us as
object.
Yet an airliner that stands on the runway is surely an object. Certainly. We can represent the machine so. But then it conceals itself as to what and how
it is. Revealed, it stands on the taxi
strip only as standing-reserve, inasmuch as it is ordered to ensure the
possibility of transportation. For this
it must be in. its whole structure and in every one of its constituent parts,
on call for duty, i.e., ready for takeoff. (Here it would be appropriate to discuss
Hegel’s definition of the machine as an autonomous tool. When applied to the tools of the craftsman,
his characterization is correct. Characterized
in this way, however, the machine is not thought at all from out of the essence
of technology within which it belongs. Seen
in terms of the standing-reserve, the machine is completely unautonomous,
for it has its standing only from the ordering of the orderable.)
The fact that now, wherever we try to point to modern technology as the
challenging revealing, the words “setting-upon,” “ordering,”
“standing-reserve,” obtrude and accumulate in a dry, monotonous, and therefore
oppressive way, has its basis in what is now coming to utterance.
16. Bestand
ordinarily denotes a store or supply as “standing by.” It carries the connotation of the verb bestehen with its dual meaning of to last and
to undergo. Heidegger uses the word to
characterize the manner in which everything commanded into place and ordered
according to the challenging demand ruling in modern technology presences as
revealed. He wishes to stress here not
the permanency, but the orderability and substitutability
of objects. Bestand
contrasts with Gegenstand (object;
that which stands over against). Objects
indeed lose their character as objects when they are caught up in the
“standing-reserve.” Cf. Introduction, p.
xxix.
Who accomplishes the challenging setting-upon through which what we
call the real is revealed as standing-reserve? Obviously, man. To what extent is man capable of such a
revealing? Man can indeed conceive,
fashion, and carry through this or that in one way or another. But man does not have control over Unconcealment itself, in which at any given time the real
shows itself or withdraws. The fact that
the real has been showing itself in the light of Ideas ever since the time of
Plato, Plato did not bring about. The
thinker only responded to what addressed itself to him.
Only to the extent that man for his part is already challenged to
exploit the energies of nature can this ordering revealing happen. If man is challenged, ordered, to do this,
then does not man himself belong even more originally than nature within the
standing-reserve? The current talk about
human resources, about the supply of patients for a clinic, gives evidence of
this. The forester who, in the wood,
measures the felled timber and to all appearances walks the same forest path in
the same way as did his grandfather is today commanded by profit-making in the
lumber industry, whether he knows it or not. He is made subordinate to the orderability of cellulose, which for its part is challenged
forth by the need for paper, which is then delivered to newspapers and
illustrated magazines. The latter, in
their turn, set public opinion to swallowing what is printed, so that a set
configuration of opinion becomes available on demand. Yet precisely because man is challenged more
originally than are the energies of nature, i.e., into the process of ordering,
he never is transformed into mere standing-reserve. Since man drives technology forward, he takes
part in ordering as a way of revealing. But
the unconcealment itself, within which ordering
unfolds, is never a human handiwork, any more than is the realm through which
man is already passing every time he as a subject relates to an object.
Where and how does this revealing happen if it is no mere handiwork of
man? We need not look far. We need only apprehend in an unbiased way That which has
already claimed man and has done so, so decisively that he can only be man at
any given time as the one so claimed. Wherever man opens his eyes and ears, unlocks
his heart, and gives himself over to meditating
18
and striving, shaping and working, entreating and thanking,
he finds himself everywhere already brought into the unconcealed. The unconcealment of
the unconcealed has already come to pass whenever it calls man forth into the
modes of revealing allotted to him. When man, in his way, from within unconcealment
reveals that which presences, he merely responds to the call of unconcealment even when he contradicts it. Thus when man, investigating, observing,
ensnares nature as an area of his own conceiving, he has already been claimed
by a way of revealing that challenges him to approach nature as an object of
research, until even the object disappears into the objectlessness
of standing-reserve.
Modern technology as an ordering revealing is, then, no merely human
doing. Therefore we must take that
challenging that sets upon man to order the real as standing-reserve in
accordance with the way in which it shows itself. That challenging gathers man into ordering. This gathering concentrates man upon ordering
the real as standing-reserve.
That which primordially unfolds the mountains into mountain ranges and
courses through them in their folded togetherness is the gathering that we call
“Gebirg” [mountain chain].
That original gathering from which unfold the ways in
which we have feelings of one kind or another we name “Gemüt”
[disposition].
We now name that challenging claim which gathers man thither to order
the self-revealing as standing-reserve: “Ge-stell”
[Enframing]. [17]
We dare to use this word in a sense that has been thoroughly unfamiliar
up to now.
17. The translation “Enframing” for Ge-steil
is intended to suggest, through the use of the prefix “en-,” something of
the active meaning that Heidegger here gives to the German word. While following the discussion that now
ensues, in which Enframing assumes a central role,
the reader should be careful not to interpret the word as though it simply
meant a framework of some sort. Instead
he should constantly remember that Enframing is
fundamentally a calling-forth. It is a
“challenging claim,” a demanding summons, that
“gathers” so as to reveal. This claim en
frames in that it assembles and orders. It puts into a framework or configuration
everything that it summons forth, through an ordering for use that it is
forever restructuring anew. Cf. Introduction, pp. xxix ff.
According to ordinary usage, the word Gestell
[frame] means some kind of apparatus, e.g., a bookrack. Gestell is
also the name for a skeleton. And
the employment of the word Gestell [Erframing] that is now required of us seems equally eerie,
not to speak of the arbitrariness with which words of a mature language are
thus misused. Can anything be more strange? Surely not. Yet this
strangeness is an old usage of thinking. And indeed thinkers accord with this usage
precisely at the point where it is a matter of thinking that which is highest. We, late born, are no longer in a position to
appreciate the significance of Plato’s daring to use the word eidos for that which in everything and in
each particular thing endures as present. For eidos,
in the common speech, meant the outward aspect [Ansicht]
that a visible thing offers to the physical eye. Plato exacts of this word, however, something
utterly extraordinary: that it name what precisely is not and never will be
perceivable with physical eyes. But even
this is by no means the full extent of what is extraordinary here. For idea names not only the nonsensuous aspect of what is physically visible. [18] Aspect (idea) names
and is, also, that which constitutes the essence in the audible, the tasteable, the tactile, in everything that is in any way
accessible. Compared with the demands
that Plato makes on language and thought in this and other instances, the use
of the word Gestell as the name for the
essence of modern technology, which we now venture here, is almost harmless. Even so, the usage now required remains something
exacting and is open to misinterpretation.
Enframing means the gathering together of
that setting-upon which sets upon man, i.e., challenges him forth, to reveal the
real, in the mode of ordering, as standing-reserve. Enframing means that
way of revealing which holds sway in the essence of modern technology and which
is itself nothing technological. On the other hand, all those things that are so familiar to us and are standard parts of an
assembly, such as rods, pistons, and chassis, belong to the technological. The assembly itself, however, together with
the aforementioned stockparts, falls within
18. Where idea is
italicized it is not the English word but a transliteration of the Greek.
20
the sphere of technological activity; and this activity
always merely responds to the challenge of Enframing,
but it never comprises Enframing itself or brings it
about.
The word stellen [to set upon]
in the name Ge-stell [Enframing] not only means challenging. At the same time it should preserve the
suggestion of another Stellen from
which it stems, namely, that producing and presenting [Her- und Dar-stellen] which, in the sense of poiesis,
lets what presences come forth into unconcealment.
This producing that brings forth - e.g.,
the erecting of a statue in the temple precinct - and the challenging ordering
now under consideration are indeed fundamentally different, and yet they remain
related in their essence. Both are ways
of revealing, of aletheia. In Enframing,
that unconcealment comes to pass in conformity with
which the work of modern technology reveals the real as standing-reserve. This work is therefore neither only a human
activity nor a mere means within such activity. The merely instrumental, merely
anthropological definition of technology is therefore in principle untenable. And it cannot be rounded out by being referred
back to some metaphysical or religious explanation that undergirds
it.
It remains true, nonetheless, that man in the technological age is, in
a particularly striking way, challenged forth into revealing. That revealing concerns nature, above all, as
the chief storehouse of the standing energy reserve. Accordingly, man’s ordering attitude and
behavior display themselves first in the rise of modern physics as an exact
science. Modern science’s way of
representing pursues and entraps nature as a calculable coherence of forces. Modern physics is not experimental physics because
it applies apparatus to the questioning of nature. Rather the reverse is true. Because physics, indeed already as pure
theory, sets nature up to exhibit itself as a coherence of forces calculable in
advance, it therefore orders its experiments precisely for the purpose of
asking whether and how nature reports itself when set up in this way.
But after all, mathematical physics arose almost two centuries before
technology. How, then, could it have
already been set upon by modern technology and placed in its service? The facts testify to the contrary. Surely technology got under way only
when it could be supported by exact physical science. Reckoned chronologically, this is correct. Thought historically, it does not hit upon the
truth.
The modern physical theory of nature prepares the way first not simply
for technology but for the essence of modern technology. For already in physics the challenging
gathering-together into ordering revealing holds sway. But in it that gathering does not yet come
expressly to appearance. Modern physics
is the herald of Enframing, a herald whose origin is
still unknown. The essence of modern
technology has for a long time been concealing itself, even where power
machinery has been invented, where electrical technology is in full swing, and
where atomic technology is well under way.
All coming to presence, not only modern technology, keeps itself
everywhere concealed to the last. [19]
Nevertheless, it remains, with respect to its
holding sway, that which precedes all: the earliest. The Greek thinkers already knew of this when
they said: That which is earlier with regard to the arising that holds sway
becomes manifest to us men only later. That
which is primally early shows itself only ultimately
to men. [20] Therefore,
in the realm of thinking, a painstaking effort to think through still more primally what was primally
thought is not the absurd wish to revive what is past, but rather the sober
readiness to be astounded before the coming of what is early.
Chronologically speaking, modern physical science begins in the
seventeenth century. In contrast,
machine-power technology develops only in the second half of the eighteenth
century. But modern technology, which
for chronological reckoning is the later, is, from the point of view of the
essence holding sway within it, the historically earlier.
19. “Coming to presence”
here translates the gerund Wesende, a
verbal form that appears, in this volume, only in this essay. With the introduction into the discussion of
“coming to presence” as an alternate translation of the noun Wesen (essence), subsequent to Heidegger’s
consideration of the meaning of essence below (pp. 30 ff.), occasionally the presence
of das Wesende is
regrettably but unavoidably obscured.
20. “That which is primally early” translates die anfangliche
Prühe. For
a discussion of that which “is to all present and absent beings ... the
earliest and most ancient at once” - i.e., Ereignen,
des Ereignis - see “The Way to Language”
in On the Way to Language, trans. Peter D. Hertz (New York: Harper &
Row, 1971), p. 127.
22
If modern physics must resign itself ever increasingly to the fact that
its realm of representation remains inscrutable and incapable of being
visualized, this resignation is not dictated by any committee of researchers. It is challenged forth by the rule of Enframing, which demands that nature be orderable as
standing-reserve. Hence physics, in all
its retreating from the representation turned only toward
objects that has alone been standard till recently, will never be able
to renounce this one thing: that nature reports itself in some way or other
that is identifiable through calculation and that it remains orderable as a
system of information. This system is
determined, then, out of a causality that has changed once again. Causality now displays neither the character
of the occasioning that brings forth nor the nature of the causa
efficiens, let alone that of the causa formalis. It seems as though causality is shrinking
into a reporting - a reporting challenged forth - of standing-reserves that
must be guaranteed either simultaneously or in sequence. To this shrinking would correspond the process
of growing resignation that Heisenberg’s lecture depicts in so impressive a
manner.*
Because the essence of modern technology lies in Enframing,
modern technology must employ exact physical science. Through its so doing, the deceptive illusion
arises that modern technology is applied physical science. This illusion can maintain itself only so long
as neither the essential origin of modern science nor indeed the essence of
modern technology is adequately found out through questioning.
We are questioning concerning technology in order to bring to light our
relationship to its essence. The essence
of modern technology shows itself in what we call Enframing.
But simply to point to this is still in
no way to answer the question concerning technology, if to answer means to
respond, in the sense of correspond, to the essence of what is being asked
about.
Where do we find ourselves brought to, if now we think one step further
regarding what Enframing itself actually is? It is nothing technological, nothing on the
order of a machine. It is the way in
which the real reveals itself as standing-reserve.
* W.
Heisenberg, “Das Naturbild
in der heutigen Physik,” in Die Kflnste im technischen Zeitalter (Munich, 1954), pp. 43 ff.
Again we ask:
Does this revealing happen somewhere beyond all human doing? No. But
neither does it happen exclusively in man, or decisively through man.
Enframing is the gathering together that
belongs to that setting-upon which sets upon man and puts him in position to
reveal the real, in the mode of ordering, as standing-reserve. As the one who is challenged forth in this
way, man stands within the essential realm of Enframing. He can never take up a relationship to it
only subsequently. Thus the question as
to how we are to arrive at a relationship to the essence of technology, asked
in this way, always comes too late. But
never too late comes the question as to whether we actually experience ourselves
as the ones whose activities everywhere, public and private, are challenged
forth by Enframing. Above all, never too late comes
the question as to whether and how we actually admit ourselves into that
wherein Enframing itself comes to presence.
The essence of modern technology starts man upon the way of that
revealing through which the real everywhere, more or less distinctly, becomes
standing-reserve. “To start upon a way”
means “to send” in our ordinary language. We shall call that sending-that-gathers [versammelde Schicken] which
first starts man upon a ‘way of revealing, destining [Geschick]. [21] It is from out of this destining
that the essence of all history [Geschichte] is determined. History is neither simply the object of
written chronicle nor simply the fulfillment of human activity. That activity first becomes history as
something destined.* And
it is only the destining into objectifying representation that makes the
historical accessible as an object for historiography, i.e., for a science, and
on this basis makes possible the current equating of the historical with that
which is chronicled.
Enframing, as a challenging-forth into
ordering, sends into a way of revealing. Enframing is an
ordaining of destining, as is
21. For a further
presentation of the meaning resident in Geschick
and the related verb schicken, cf.
T 38 ff., and Introduction, pp. xxviii ff.
* See Vom Wesen der Wahrheit, 1930; 1st ed.,
1943, pp. 16 ff. [English
translation, “On the Essence of Truth,” in Existence and Being, ed.
Werner Brock (Chicago: Regnery, 1949), pp. 308 ff.]
24
every way of revealing. Bringing-forth, poiesis,
is also a destining in this sense.
Always the unconcealment of that which is [22] goes upon a way of revealing. Always the destining of revealing holds
complete sway over man. But that
destining is never a fate that compels. For man becomes truly free only insofar as he
belongs to the realm of destining and so becomes one who listens and hears [Hörender], and not one who is simply constrained to
obey [Höriger].
The essence of freedom is originally not connected with the will
or even with the causality of human willing.
Freedom governs the open in the sense of the cleared and lighted up,
i.e., of the revealed. [23] It
is to the happening of revealing, i.e., of truth, that freedom stands in the
closest and most intimate kinship. All
revealing belongs within a harboring and a concealing. But that which frees - the mystery - is
concealed and always concealing itself. All
revealing comes out of the open, goes into the open, and brings into the open. The freedom of the open consists neither in
unfettered arbitrariness nor in the constraint of mere laws. Freedom is that which conceals in a way that
opens to light, in whose clearing there shimmers that
veil that covers what comes to presence of all truth and lets the veil appear
as what veils. Freedom is the realm of
the destining that at any given time starts a revealing upon its way.
The essence of modern technology lies in Enframing.
Enframing
belongs within the destining of revealing. These sentences express something different
from the talk that we hear more frequently, to the effect that technology is
the fate of our age, where “fate” means the inevitableness of an unalterable
course.
But when we consider the essence of technology, then we experience Enframing as a destining of revealing. In this way we are already sojourning within
the open space of destining, a destining that in no way confines us to a
stultified compulsion to push on blindly with technology or, what comes to the
same
22. dessen was ist. On
the peculiar significance of des was ist
(that which is), see T 44 n. 12.
23. “The open” here
translates das Preie,
cognate with Freiheit, freedom. Unfortunately the repetitive stress of the
German phrasing cannot be reproduced in English, since the basic meaning of Freie - open air, open space - is scarcely heard in the
English “free.”
thing, to rebel helplessly against it and curse it as the
work of the devil. Quite to the
contrary, when we once open ourselves expressly to the essence of technology,
we find ourselves unexpectedly taken into a freeing claim.
The essence of technology lies in Enframing. Its holding sway belongs within destining. Since destining at any given time starts man
on a way of revealing, man, thus under way, is continually approaching the
brink of the possibility of pursuing and pushing forward nothing but what is
revealed in ordering, and of deriving all his standards on this basis. Through this the other possibility is blocked,
that man might be admitted more and sooner and ever more primally
to the essence of that which is unconcealed and to its unconcealment,
in order that he might experience as his essence his needed belonging to
revealing.
Placed between these possibilities, man is endangered from out of
destining. The destining of revealing is
as such, in every one of its modes, and therefore necessarily,
danger.
In whatever way the destining of revealing may hold sway, the unconcealment in which everything that is shows itself at
any given time harbors the danger that man may quail at the unconcealed and may
misinterpret it. Thus where everything
that presences exhibits itself in the light of a cause-effect coherence, even
God can, for representational thinking, lose all that is exalted and holy, the
mysteriousness of his distance. In the
light of causality, God can sink to the level of a cause, of causa efficiens. He then becomes, even in theology, the god
of the philosophers, namely, of those who define the unconcealed and the
concealed in terms of the causality of making, without ever considering the
essential origin of this causality.
In a similar way the unconcealment in
accordance with which nature presents itself as a calculable complex of the
effects of forces can indeed permit correct determinations; but precisely
through these successes the danger can remain that in the midst of all that is
correct the true will withdraw.
The destining of revealing is in itself not just any danger, but danger
as such.
Yet when destining reigns in the mode of Enframing,
it is the supreme danger. This danger
attests itself to us in two ways. As
soon as what is unconcealed no longer concerns man even as
26
object, but does so, rather, exclusively as
standing-reserve, and man in the midst of objectlessness
is nothing but the orderer of the standing-reserve,
then he comes to the very brink of a precipitous fall; that is, he comes to the
point where he himself will have to be taken as standing-reserve. Meanwhile man, precisely as the one so
threatened, exalts himself to the posture of lord of the earth. In this way the impression comes to prevail
that everything man encounters exists only insofar as it is his construct. This illusion gives rise in turn to one final
delusion: It seems as though man everywhere and always encounters only himself.
Heisenberg has with complete correctness
pointed out that the real must present itself to contemporary man in this way.*
In truth, however, precisely nowhere
does man today any longer encounter himself, i.e., his essence. Man stands so decisively in attendance on
the challenging-forth of Enframing that he does not
apprehend Enframing as a claim, that he fails to see
himself as the one spoken to, and hence also fails in every way to hear in what
respect he ek-sists, from out of his essence, in the
realm of an exhortation or address, and thus can never encounter only
himself.
But Enframing does not simply endanger man in
his relationship to himself and to everything that is. As a destining, it banishes man into that kind
of revealing which is an ordering. Where
this ordering holds sway, it drives out every other possibility of revealing. Above all, Enframing
conceals that revealing which, in the sense of poiesis,
lets what presences come forth into appearance. As compared with that other revealing, the
setting-upon that challenges forth thrusts man into a relation to that which
is, that is at once antithetical and rigorously ordered. Where Enframing
holds sway, regulating and securing of the standing-reserve mark all revealing.
They no longer even let their own
fundamental characteristic appear, namely, this revealing as such.
Thus the challenging Enframing not only conceals
a former way of revealing, bringing-forth, but it conceals revealing itself and
with it That wherein unconcealment,
i.e., truth, comes to pass.
* “Das Naturbild,”
pp. 60 if.
Enframing blocks the shining-forth and
holding-sway of truth. The destining
that sends into ordering is consequently the extreme danger. What is dangerous is not technology. There is no demonry
of technology, but rather there is the mystery of its essence. The essence of technology, as a destining of
revealing, is the danger. The
transformed meaning of the word “Enframing” will
perhaps become somewhat more familiar to us now if we think Enframing
in the sense of destining and danger.
The threat to man does not come in the first instance from the
potentially lethal machines and apparatus of technology. The actual threat has already affected man in
his essence. The rule of Enframing threatens man with the possibility that it could
be denied to him to enter into a more original revealing and hence to
experience the call of a more primal truth.
Thus, where Enframing reigns, there is danger
in the highest sense.
But where danger is, grows
The saving power also.
Let us think carefully about these words of Hölderlin.
What does it mean “to save”? Usually we think that it means only to seize
hold of a thing threatened by ruin, in order to secure it in its former
continuance. But the verb “to save” says
more. “To save” is to fetch something home into its essence, in order to bring
the essence for the first time into its genuine appearing. If the essence of technology, Enframing, is the extreme danger,
and if there is truth in Hölderlin’s words, then the
rule of Enframing cannot exhaust itself solely in
blocking all lighting-up of every revealing, all appearing of truth. Rather, precisely the essence of technology
must harbor in itself the growth of the saving power. But in that case, might not an adequate look
into what Enframing is as a destining of revealing bring into appearance the saving power in its arising?
In what respect does the saving power grow there also where the danger
is? Where something grows, there it
takes root, from thence it thrives. Both
happen concealedly and quietly and in their own time.
But according to the words of the poet
we have no right whatsoever to expect that there where the danger is we
28
should be able to lay hold of the saving power immediately
and without preparation. Therefore we
must consider now, in advance, in what respect the saving power does most
profoundly take root and thence thrive even in that wherein the extreme danger
lies, in the holding sway of Enframing. In order to consider this, it is necessary, as
a last step upon our way, to look with yet clearer eyes into the danger. Accordingly, we must once more question
concerning technology. For we have said
that in technology’s essence roots and thrives the saving power.
But how shall we behold the saving power in the essence of technology
so long as we do not consider in what sense of “essence” it is that Enframing is actually the essence of technology?
Thus far we have understood “essence” in its current meaning. In the academic language of philosophy,
“essence” means what something is; in Latin, quid. Quidditas, whatness, provides
the answer to the question concerning essence. For example, what pertains to all kinds of
trees - oaks, beeches, birches, firs - is the same “treeness.”
Under this inclusive genus - the
“universal” - fall
all real and possible trees. Is then the
essence of technology, Enframing, the common genus
for everything technological? If that
were the case then the steam turbine, the radio transmitter, and the cyclotron
would each be an Enframing. But the word “Enframing”
does not mean here a tool or any kind of apparatus. Still less does it mean the general concept of
such resources. The machines and
apparatus are no more cases and kinds of Enframing
than are the man at the switchboard and the engineer in the drafting room. Each of these in its own way indeed belongs as
stockpart, available resource, or executer, within Enframing; but Enframing is never
the essence of technology in the sense of a genus. Enframing is a way
of revealing having the character of destining, namely, the way that challenges
forth. The revealing that brings forth (poiesis) is also a way that has the character of
destining. But these ways are not kinds
that, arrayed beside one another, fall under the concept of revealing. Revealing is that destining which, ever
suddenly and inexplicably to all thinking, apportions itself into the revealing
that brings forth and that also challenges, and which allots itself to man. The challenging reveal-
ing has its origin as a destining in bringing-forth. But at the same time Enframing,
in a way characteristic of a destining, blocks poiēsis.
Thus Enframing, as a destining of revealing,
is indeed the essence of technology, but never in the sense of genus and essentia. If
we pay heed to this, something astounding strikes us:
It is technology itself that makes the
demand on us to think in another way what is usually understood by “essence.” But in what way?
If we speak of the “essence of a house” and the “essence of a state,”
we do not mean a generic type; rather we mean the ways in which house and state
hold sway, administer themselves, develop and decay - the way in which they
“essence” [Wesen].
Johann Peter Hebel in a poem, “Ghost on Kanderer
Street,” for which Goethe had a special fondness, uses the old word die Weserei. It
means the city hall inasmuch as there the life of the community gathers and
village existence is constantly in play, i.e., comes to presence. It is from the verb wesen
that the noun is derived. Wesen understood as a verb is the same as währen [to last or endure], not only in terms
of meaning, but also in terms of the phonetic formation of the word. Socrates and Plato already think the essence
of something as what essences, what comes to presence, in the sense of what
endures. But they think what endures as
what remains permanently [das Fortwährende]
(aei
on). And they find what endures
permanently in what, as that which remains, tenaciously persists throughout all
that happens. That which remains they
discover, in turn, in the aspect [Aussehen] (eidos,
idea), for example, the Idea “house.”
The Idea “house” displays what anything is
that is fashioned as a house. Particular,
real, and possible houses, in contrast, are changing and transitory derivatives
of the Idea and thus belong to what does not endure.
But it can never in any way be established that enduring is based
solely on what Plato thinks as idea and Aristotle thinks as to ti ēn einai
(that which any particular thing has always been), or what metaphysics in
its most varied interpretations thinks as essentia.
All essencing endures. But is enduring only permanent enduring? Does the essence of technology endure in the
sense of
30
the permanent enduring of an Idea that hovers over
everything technological, thus making it seem that by technology we mean some
mythological abstraction? The way in
which technology essences lets itself be seen only from out of that permanent
enduring in which Enframing comes to pass as a destining
of revealing. Goethe once uses the
mysterious word fortgewähren [to grant
permanently] in place of fortwähren [to
endure permanently].* He
hears währen [to endure] and gewähren [to grant] here in one unarticulated
accord. [24] And
if we now ponder more carefully than we did before what it is that actually
endures and perhaps alone endures, we may venture to say: Only what is
granted endures. That which endures primally out of the earliest beginning is what grants.
[25]
As the essencing of technology, Enframing is that which endures. Does Enframing hold
sway at all in the sense of granting? No
doubt the question seems a horrendous blunder. For according to everything that has been
said, Enframing is, rather, a destining that gathers
together into the revealing that challenges forth. Challenging is anything but a granting. So it seems, so long as we do not notice that
the challenging-forth into the ordering of the real as standing-reserve still
remains a destining that starts man upon a way of revealing. As this destining, the coming to presence of
technology gives man entry into That which, of
himself, he can neither invent nor in any way make. For there is no such thing as a man who,
solely of himself, is only man.
But if this destining, Enframing,
is the extreme danger, not only for man’s coming to presence, but for all
revealing as such, should this destining still be called a granting? Yes, most emphat-
* “Die Wahlverwandtschaften”
[Congeniality], pt. II, chap. 10, in the novelette Die wunderlichen
Nachbarskinder [The strange neighbor’s children].
24. The verb gewähren is closely allied to the verbs währen (to endure) and währen
(to watch over, to keep safe, to preserve). Gewâhren ordinarily
means to be surety for, to warrant, to vouchsafe, to
grant. In the discussion that follows,
the verb will be translated simply with “to grant.” But the reader should keep in mind also the
connotations of safeguarding and guaranteeing that are present in it as well.
25. Nur
das Gewährte währt. Das anfänglich
aus der Frühe
Währende ist
das Gewährende. A literal translation of the second
sentence would be, “That which endures primally from
out of the early…” On the meaning of
“the early,” see n. 20 above.
ically, if in this destining the
saving power is said to grow. Every
destining of revealing comes to pass from out of a granting and as such a
granting. For it is granting that first
conveys to man that share in revealing which the coming-to-pass of revealing
needs. [26] As
the one so needed and used, man is given to belong to the coming-to-pass of
truth. The granting that sends in one
way or another into revealing is as such the saving power. For the saving power lets
man see and enter into the highest dignity of his essence. This dignity lies in keeping watch over the unconcealment - and with it, from the first, the
concealment - of all coming to presence on this earth. It is precisely in Enframing,
which threatens to sweep man away into ordering as the supposed single way of
revealing, and so thrusts man into the danger of the surrender of his free
essence - it is precisely in this extreme danger that the innermost
indestructible belongingness of man within granting may come to light, provided
that we, for our part, begin to pay heed to the coming to presence of
technology.
Thus the coming to presence of technology harbors in itself what we
least suspect, the possible arising of the saving power.
Everything, then, depends upon this: that we ponder this arising and
that, recollecting, we watch over it. How can this happen? Above all through our catching sight of what
comes to presence in technology, instead of merely staring at the technological.
So long as we represent technology as an
instrument, we remain held fast in the will to master it. We press on past the essence of technology.
When, however, we ask how the instrumental comes to presence as a kind
of causality, then we experience this coming to presence as the destining of a
revealing.
When we consider, finally, that the coming to presence of the essence
of technology comes to pass in the granting that needs and uses man so that he
may share in revealing, then the following becomes clear:
26. Here and subsequently in
this essay, “coming-to-pass” translates the noun Ereignis.
Elsewhere, in “The Turning,” this
word, in accordance with the deeper meaning that Heidegger there finds for it,
will be translated with “disclosing that brings into its own.” See T 45; see
also Introduction, pp. xxxvi-xxxvii.
32
The essence of technology is in a lofty sense ambiguous. Such ambiguity points to the
mystery of all revealing, i.e., of truth.
On the one hand, Enframing challenges forth
into the frenziedness of ordering that blocks every
view into the coming-to-pass of revealing and so radically endangers the
relation to the essence of truth.
On the other hand, Enframing comes to pass
for its part in the granting that lets man endure - as yet unexperienced,
but perhaps more experienced in the future - that he may be the one who is
needed and used for the safekeeping of the coming to presence of truth. [27] Thus does the arising of
the saving power appear.
The irresistibility of ordering and the restraint of the saving power
draw past each other like the paths of two stars in the course of the heavens. But precisely this, their passing by, is the
hidden side of their nearness.
When we look into the ambiguous essence of technology, we behold the
constellation, the stellar course of the mystery.
The question concerning technology is the question concerning the
constellation in which revealing and concealing, in which the coming to
presence of truth, comes to pass.
But what help is it to us to look into the
constellation of truth? We look into the
danger and see the growth of the saving power.
Through this we are not yet saved. But we are thereupon summoned to hope in the
growing light of the saving power. How
can this. happen? Here and now and in little things, that we may
foster the saving power in its increase. This includes holding always before our eyes
the extreme danger.
The coming to presence of technology threatens revealing, threatens it
with the possibility that all revealing will be consumed in ordering and that
everything will present itself only in the unconcealedness
of standing-reserve. Human activity can
never directly counter this danger. Human
achievement alone can never banish it. But
human reflection can ponder the fact that
27. “Safekeeping” translates
the noun Wahrnis, which is unique to
Heidegger. Wahrnis
is closely related to the verb währen (to
watch over, to keep safe, to preserve), integrally related to Wahrheit (truth), and closely akin to währen (to endure) and gewähren
(to be surety for, to grant). On the
meaning of Wahrnis, see T 42, n. 9 and
n. 12 above.
all saving power must be of a higher essence than what is endangered,
though at the same time kindred to it.
But might there not perhaps be a more primally
granted revealing that could bring the saving power into its first shining
forth in the midst of the danger, a revealing that in the technological age
rather conceals than shows itself?
There was a time when it was not technology alone that bore the name technë. Once
that revealing that brings forth truth into the splendor of radiant appearing
also was called technē.
Once there was a time when the bringing-forth of the true into the
beautiful was called technē. And the poiēsis
of the fine arts also was called technē.
In Greece, at the outset of the destining of the West, the arts soared
to the supreme height of the revealing granted them. They brought the presence [Gegenwart]
of the gods, brought the dialogue of divine and human destinings, to radiance. And art was simply called technē.
It was a single, manifold revealing.
It was pious, promos, i.e.,
yielding to the holding-sway and the safekeeping of truth.
The arts were not derived from the artistic. Art works were not enjoyed aesthetically. Art was not a sector of cultural activity.
What, then, was art - perhaps only for that brief but magnificent time?
Why did art bear the modest name technē? Because it was a revealing that brought
forth and hither, and therefore belonged within poiēsis. It was finally that revealing which holds
complete sway in all the fine arts, in poetry, and in everything poetical that
obtained poiēsis as its proper name.
The same poet from whom we heard the words
But where danger is, grows
The
saving power also.
says to us:
poetically dwells man upon this earth.
The poetical brings the true into the splendor of what Plato in the Phaedrus calls to ekphanestaton,
that which shines forth most purely. The poetical thoroughly pervades every art,
every revealing of coming to presence into the beautiful.
34
Could it be that the fine arts are called to poetic revealing? Could it be that revealing lays claim to the
arts most primally, so that they for their part may
expressly foster the growth of the saving power, may awaken and found anew our
look into that which grants and our trust in it?
Whether art may be granted this highest possibility of its essence in
the midst of the extreme danger, no one can tell. Yet we can be astounded. Before what? Before this other possibility: that the frenziedness of technology may entrench itself everywhere
to such an extent that someday, throughout everything technological, the essence
of technology may come to presence in the coming-to-pass of truth.
Because the essence of technology is nothing technological, essential
reflection upon technology and decisive confrontation with it must happen in a
realm that is, on the one hand, akin to the essence of technology and, on the
other, fundamentally different from it.
Such a realm is art. But certainly only if reflection on art, for its part, does not
shut its eyes to the constellation of truth after which we are
questioning.
Thus questioning, we bear witness to the crisis that in our sheer
preoccupation with technology we do not yet experience the coming to presence
of technology, that in our sheer aesthetic-mindedness we no longer guard and
preserve the coming to presence of art. Yet
the more questioningly we ponder the essence of technology, the more mysterious
the essence of art becomes.
The closer we come to the danger, the more brightly do the ways into the saving power begin to shine and the more questioning we become. For questioning is the piety of thought.
35