The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Marjorie
Grene
On Some Distinctions Between Men and Brutes
Ethics,
57 (2), Jan. 1947, 121-127
EVERYONE appears to agree nowadays on the need
for a revaluation of human values; but some think we must for the first time
set man into his proper place in the whole of animal nature, while others are
certain we need to reaffirm his special place outside the sphere of the merely
natural. Whether the problem is one of
abstract metaphysics or practical pedagogy, this issue is involved.
Perhaps a re-examination of some of the historical
alternatives may, if not answer, at least help to clarify the question. Put at its crudest, the current opposition
seems to be something like this: on the one hand, it is said that, like other philosophic
theories of the past, the traditional cleavage between man and nature is the
result of overabstraction so gross that the principal facts of the case are
overlooked or actually denied. The
considerable, in fact, central, role of impulse, habit, and the irrational
generally is denied in favor of a reason which actually men are most
infrequently seen to exercise in its purity even in the abstruse fields of
logic or mathematics, let alone in the tangled and pressing concerns of their
daily existence. Of course, every theory
of human nature includes its account of feeling and emotion, but the objection
in the main is that traditional theories treat feeling as something bad to be
suppressed rather than as the real driving force it actually is: a force
morally indifferent in itself but operating for good or ill under a variety of
circumstances. On the other side such
biological treatment of human nature is said to eliminate any standard of good
or evil by which to discriminate one use of emotion from another. If men are not distinguished from brutes by
some unique character which itself supplies a standard of value, then, it is
thought, no end is left for human endeavor, nothing remains but the Hobbesian
sequence of appetites and aversions in which no need or appetite can be
criticized as bad or harmful. As a
result of this lack, every excess of cruelty and sadism is sanctioned; and, in
the resulting war of all against all, the good and decent elements in human
nature - which under ordinary circumstances can be observed to exist equally
with the bad and brutal ones - are swamped by the more violent impulses thus
dangerously unleashed. The practical
result is the stasis of Corcyra or Europe under the Nazis; the theoretical
result is the ideal tyrant of Thrasymachus or the leader-principle of the S.S.
man. Both sides see evil practical
consequences from the alternative view: the one in the suppression of fruitful
and progressive impulses, the other in the loosing of brutal drives which by a
natural process suppress the better ones. But, quite apart from the moot question of the
effect of any philosophic theory on anybody’s practice, the principal charge
philosophically seems in both cases to be one of inadequacy: because men are
described as different from other animals or because they are described as like
them, the facts of human nature as common experience reveals them are falsely
reported.
The charge of inadequacy is justified on both sides, I think. In historical terms: the Cartesian separation of men and brutes is wrong - but not every distinction between men and brutes is essentially Cartesian (though personally I suspect that every honest Christian one is so, unless, like the Kantian, it renounces its own metaphysical foundation); the Hobbesian identification of the desires of men and brutes is wrong,
121
but not every theory that makes men
similar to other animals is Hobbesian.
First, as to the Cartesian
distinction. Certainly the theory
of “brutism” is, judged by the criterion of adequacy, one of the most fantastic
theories about anything anywhere in the history of Western thought. To think of the animal body as a machine with,
in man, a completely incorporeal yet communicating entity mysteriously attached
raises all the insoluble and unnecessary problems of interaction that everyone
has been pointing out for three centuries. As a. result, human psychology is either
absurdly or merely conventionally described - the latter, e.g., in Descartes’s
pallid recapitulations of Senecan morals to the Princess Elizabeth, a subject
which obviously interested him not at all. For orthodox principles of morality could be
automatically deduced from his metaphysics and physics, and there was no
problem about it - since, in fact, a decent Stoic-Christian morality can easily
be fitted into any simple dualistic account of reason and the passions. But if human nature is superficially dealt
with in the Cartesian account, the unfortunate remainder of animal creation
receives infinitely more flagrant mistreatment. The experience of the owner of two tournebroches
who visited Port Royal can be duplicated by anyone who has ever had a dog,
even a fairly stupid one (see S. Alexander’s posthumously published essay, The
Mind of My Dog), or for that matter by anyone who has had any acquaintance
with any of the higher mammals. On the
one hand, there seems no reason to hold that the very similar facial
expressions, for example, which are thought to denote certain feelings in human
beings do not express any feeling in other animals. And, on the other hand, the dissimilarity in
the thought-processes of other animals suggested by the absence of speech is
amply offset by striking similarities in other behavior patterns associated
with processes of inference - see the example of the tournebroche or, if
you want more up-to-date material, Köhler’s apes. It is not too sweeping a statement, I think,
to say that no theory which makes human thought and feeling differ toto
coelo from the thought and feeling of other creatures can ever be accepted
by anyone who has had any ordinary experience of animals at all; there are
simply too many facts the theory has to ignore or at least fantastically to
reinterpret to make them fit.
Of course, attacking poor Descartes for his brutism is beating a very dead horse. Descartes’s philosophy is not one of the eternally recurrent Weltanschauungen but a peculiar synthesis suited to a very special time and place: a synthesis which outside the atmosphere of seventeenth-century French theological circles - or, better, seventeenth-century French Augustinian theological circles - does not synthesize at all. But there are two reasons why more organic theorists of human nature can still relevantly attack a theory as obviously dead as Cartesian dualism. The influence of that view in modern thought runs so wide and deep that even as staunch a phenomenalist as J. S. Mill can unquestioningly differentiate the permanent possibility of feeling from the permanent possibility of sensation, though nothing in the phenomena as he views them could justify such a distinction. Even more important, it can be fairly maintained, I think, that the Cartesian theory of human reason and animal nature represents the core of the Christian tradition and that the Jansenists were quite correct in so accepting it. Certainly, the disagreement between Descartes and the Thomists on the relation of thought to sensation and of the knowledge of mind to that of body (as represented in Objections I, II, and VI) was a very genuine disagreement. But stitching an Aristotelian theory of knowledge into the interstices of a Christian world view does not in the least alter the fundamental necessity for any orthodox Christian position: that animus must be radically different from anima, that the single respect in which man is made in the image of his maker must be entirely separate and distinct in him from everything bodily. In some medieval accounts of the
122
human soul [1] one feels
that the transition from the finest animal spirits to the mind itself is so
gradual that one can imagine animus as the rarest and subtlest portion
of the anima; that is what Descartes himself suggests when he runs over
the things he had “imagined” himself to be. [2] But though such an identification
may make things easier for the lay imagination and furnish charming matter for
the artist, theologically and philosophically it is surely most dangerous; and
no serious Christian theory would dare admit it. In short, a Christian world view demands an
Augustinian-Jansenist-Cartesian conception of the relation of mind to body and
human to animal nature, and the importation of pseudo-scientific phraseology
from the Philosopher about the way of knowing mind and nature can serve only to
obscure, not to eliminate, that necessity.
Even the apparently noncommittal view of Locke on
human reason is still Cartesian and depends explicitly, moreover, on a divine
sanction. If we still believe in the Jeffersonian
revision of Locke’s law of nature, we have unfortunately no logical or rather
metaphysical right to do so unless we take the Cartesian world and its all-wise
maker with it - or unless we have an alternative account of man and nature from
which the right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness is equally
deducible.
But if Hobbesian psychology is really the exclusive
alternative to the Cartesian-Christian conception, our philosophical as well as
practical situation is pretty desperate. For if Cartesian brutism does less than
justice to the common facts of animal life in general, so does the so-called selfish
system to our common experience of human feelings. Hobbes himself admits the test of his
philosophy is in our own hearts [3] and,
while we may find there the fears and expectations he describes, we find too
much that for their sake we are asked to explain away. In his definitions of the passions Hobbes
gives cursory treatment to such feelings as “kindness,” for instance; but they
have, of course, no motive force, not even, as in Hume, for mere moral
judgment, let alone as sources of action. Some kindly feelings, for instance, gratitude,
Hobbes even describes in such a way as palpably to contradict the facts, or at
least to omit important and relevant parts of them:
To have received from one, to
whom we think ourselves equal, greater benefits than there is hope to requite,
disposeth to counterfeit love; but really secret hatred… For benefits oblige; and obligation is
thraldom; and unrequitable obligation, perpetual thraldom; which is to one’s
equal, hateful. But to have received
benefits from one, whom we acknowledge for superior, inclines to love; because
the obligation is no new depression; and cheerful acceptation (which men call Gratitude)
is such an honor done to the obliger, as is taken generally for
retribution. [4]
Or in the treatment of family relations, for example, Hobbes, of
course, takes no account of any natural ties of affection but indicates simply
the obligation to obedience on the part of the child toward whoever nourishes
it:
For it ought to obey him by
whom it is preserved; because preservation of life being the end, for which one
man becomes subject to another, every man is supposed to promise obedience, to
him, in whose power it is to save, or destroy him. [5]
In Behemoth, when he presents himself with the problem of a man ordered by the sovereign to execute his own father, there is indeed some suggestion in the way his interlocutor puts the question that such a man might feel some hesitation in obeying. But the basic question, whether there is such a thing as filial affection, is hedged; and the answer is made that, after all, the order is unlikely anyhow, and if it is given it must be obeyed only if decreed as a law rather than as a special order having refer-
1. See, e.g., Hugh of St.
Victor De medicina animae.
2. Meditation ii.
3. Leviathan (Everyman
ed.), Introduction.
4. Ibid., chap. xi, p. 50.
5. Ibid., chap. xx, p.
105.
123
ence to a particular person. [6] To be sure, Hobbes can,
if he likes, explain away the kindlier passions to his own satisfaction; but if
each man’s introspection is really the test of the correctness of the theory,
then there is strong evidence against it somewhere in the experience of most of
us. Granted, with Hume, that the gentler
passions are weaker than Hobbes’s basic fears and appetites; they are there
nevertheless in some measure, as each of us can verify. And, what is more, no system of education
could induce them if there were not some spark in us for such habituation to
work on. The same argument - that used
by Hume in the “Enquiry” against egoism - is valid against Hobbes’s political
psychology. Perhaps many of us act like
Hobbesian men all the time, and all of us most of the time; but many of us
admire actions Hobbes would condemn as foolish, and a few even practice them. And, though Hobbes would, of course, account
for such admiration or practice as the consequence of hearing or reading
seditious doctrine, such miseducation would not have taken effect were there
not something in men’s natures to respond to it.
Nevertheless, Hobbes’s inadequacy is not the result of
an equation of men and brutes or a failure to distinguish human reason as a
unique directive element distinct from animal passion. In the first place, Hobbes does distinguish
men from other animals, and much more shrewdly than the Cartesians. Strauss seems to think the basic Hobbesian
distinction is contained in the observation that man alone among animals is
vain or proud; and the reference to pride as the basic human passion, he
thinks, invalidates Hobbes’s mechanical account as a consistent system. [7] If,
however, one takes the Hobbesian philosophy of motion at its face value,
interpreting the relation between Hobbes’s philosophy of nature and human
nature, for example, as Tönnies does, one may take as fundamental the
distinction of the Leviathan: brutes and men reason, with prudence, from
effects to causes; men also, in science, from causes to effects. The latter type of ratiocination, starting
from definitions, depends on the invention of language, which makes man if not
different in kind from brutes at least an infinitely cleverer brute in the
techniques of satisfying his animal wants. This distinction, unlike the Cartesian, may be
amply confirmed by observation of animals as well as of men.
But not only does Hobbes himself make a clear
distinction (if not two distinctions) between men and other animals; the inadequacies
of his system can be largely eliminated even in a philosophy which stresses the
similarities of various species, namely, in Hume’s moral philosophy. The examples Hume uses to show such likeness,
especially in the chapters on pride and humility and love and hatred in
animals, [8] are admittedly very weak; for
he seems to have confined his observations principally to barnyard fowl, who
are surely among the species least endowed with thought and feeling. But his illustrations can be bettered without
altering the basic analogy which is fundamental to his whole system of
knowledge and morals. It is an important
part of the evidence for his theory of mind that it explains a wider range of
phenomena, namely, animal and human, than any other. In fact, it is, Hume says, only another hypothesis
accounting equally well for animal as well as human thought and feeling that
could, by the rules of empirical evidence, be said to have equal probability
with his own. Yet Hume, stressing the
likeness of men and brutes, takes full cognizance of the benevolent aspect of
human nature, giving man’s limited generosity place beside his more
self-centered feelings. Sympathy is not,
to be sure, by any means the primary motive force for most human action; but it
sometimes functions as motive in the direct form of kindness or
6. English Works, ed.
Molesworth, VI, 227.
7. Strauss, The Political
Philosophy of Hobbes (Oxford, 1936), chap. ii, passim; cf.,
e.g., De cive, chap. v, art. 5: “[HHC: Latin not reproduced].”
8. Treatise,
Book II, Part I, sec. 12, and Part II, sec. 12.
124
benevolence and serves in its weakened
(because generalized) form as the source of moral judgment.
What is mistaken in Hobbes, one concludes, is not the
equation of men and other animals but the reduction of both to mere motions. One is no better off with men and brutes made
mere machines than with the Cartesian world of machines and incorporeal minds
to observe them. One is no better off
with a nature dead through and through than with a dead nature and a live
reason mysteriously functioning in it. The selfish system is the logical result of a
thoroughgoing mechanism in which motions to and from, that is, appetites and
aversions, in the individual body are the only possible passions. On the other hand, Hume’s use of any and all
given feelings as data, with the flexible range of imaginative association operating
on them, allows the admission of much wider data and more inclusive treatment
of them and, therefore, a much more adequate account of the variety and range
of human character and feeling.
Perhaps, then, by the ample inclusion in our data of
the gentler as well as the more violent feelings, we may produce a description
of human nature that will give a sufficient basis for moral judgment without
recourse to a supernaturally implanted reason. As a matter of fact, Hume’s ethics has
descriptively, I think, a high degree of adequacy; moreover, despite the
current rejection of Hume’s atomic psychology, the pragmatic philosophy seems
to me in the main an attempt to restore Hume’s position - with a good deal less
precision than Hume achieved. But,
despite its competency to describe more varied phenomena of human nature than
most ethical systems, Hume’s morals has two serious drawbacks. First, a question may be raised about the adequacy
of its metaphysical basis - and again the same doubt would apply to its contemporary
descendants in the philosophies of pragmatism, since, despite the rejection of
Hume’s atomic theory of mind, his fundamental position is maintained: i.e., the
reality of universals is denied. But, of course, if Peirce’s critique of
nominalism or Plato’s refutation of Protagoras in the Theaetelus should
be correct, such a philosophic basis would be mistaken, no matter how adequate
the conclusions presumably deduced from it. That objection, however, goes far beyond the
range of this discussion. More immediately
relevant is the objection raised by Hume himself: in a letter to Hutcheson he
suggests that, should the universal existence of the moral sense fail to be confirmed
in experience, his and Hutcheson’s ethics would collapse. [9] Explicitly, of course,
pragmatism stresses the relativity of value-judgments rather than the simple
uniformity of human feeling Hume relies on. But Hume certainly in his emphasis on custom
and habit takes equal account of the variation in such judgments; and, on the
other side, modern pragmatism as an ethics still implicitly demands a simple
faith not so unlike the eighteenth-century one: a faith that really everyone is
at heart an awfully nice fellow. Neither
Hume’s system nor modern pragmatism gives us any defense when we meet with
individuals or groups who are definitely not in the least nice fellows and
whose philosophy of human nature is not at all nice either. In the polite circles of eighteenth-century
Edinburgh and Paris or in the bigger-and-better heyday of our roaring twenties
the mere description of human good nature may have looked very charming; but in
Plato’s generation, for instance, it was clearly not enough, and it is just as
clearly not enough in this one.
Yet a return to the Cartesian distinction with its
absurdity and artificiality is no satisfactory escape. Are there other traditional ways out to be
inspected? Plato himself, faced with a
not dissimilar moral situation, could distinguish something unique in human
nature as a source of moral standards and. at the same time see a continuity in the whole range of animal nature. In the metaphor of the many-headed beast, the
lion and the man, for example, [10]
9 Letters,
ed. Grieg (Oxford, 1932), I, 40, No. 16.
10. Republic 588B.
125
the likeness and difference are equally
pointed. So are they (with greater emphasis
on the continuity of animal life) in Diotima’s account of the urge for
immortality. [11] Or,
in the myth of the Phaedrus, for instance, the soul throughout the
universe has a uniform function, but human souls have a unique insight that
puts them high in what is nevertheless presumably a continuous hierarchy:
For the soul that has not seen
the truth will not come into this (i.e. human) shape. For a man must understand what is spoken
according to form, bringing together what comes from many perceptions into one
by means of reasoning. [12]
Moreover, in several of his accounts of human
psychology, Plato indicates that the passions which men presumably share with
beasts are something to be controlled, not extinguished - and that, as the
theory of the [HHC: Greek not reproduced] suggests, reason itself
never operates without the motive force of passion accompanying it. So again, as in Hume, we may recognize the
continuity of animal nature and acknowledge the importance of feeling in men - but
with the recognition of the unique element in this most godlike of animals, the
element which should control the brutal aspects of man’s nature however seldom
it may, in fact, effectively do so. And,
certainly, Plato, unlike Hume, does not fail to supply a sufficient metaphysic
to support his moral system. But again
there are at least two major difficulties in the way of taking Plato’s
psychology as the solution to our problem. For one thing the metaphysical foundation of
Plato’s ethic eliminates any but a strictly intellectual standard of morality;
and an ethic which allows no virtue distinct from intelligence is simply too
uncomfortable for use by most ordinary mortals. One can so define wisdom as to eliminate
really clever bad people; but to eliminate good, kind, decent stupid or at least
simple-minded, unintellectual people is, I should think, rather too much for
most of us. But the principal difficulty
in Plato’s account of men and animals is in the metaphysic itself on which it
rests: despite the enormous spread and influence of something called Platonism,
I suppose there has never really been a Platonist and never can be. From the unlucky Dionysius
on, every supposed follower of Plato has been infinitely less elusive, more
stock and settled and therefore dead than the creator of the dialogues himself.
Some few people have the gift of
illuminating Platonic metaphysics (most have not) - but it is not a doctrine to
be taken over and imposed as a solution on our particular problems. We may or may not find indefinite depths of
suggestion and illumination in the dialogues - set, for instance, Diotima’s
discussion mentioned above beside Hobbes’s bungling treatment of the family - but
there is no Platonic system in the framework of which we can neatly put man
into his place in nature and feel satisfied that our moral standard is provided
and our problem solved.
The question remains: how can we retain a sense of
man’s uniqueness sufficient to provide a standard of value that can hold in the
face of the relativity of human feelings and judgments, yet without resorting
to the implausible and barren conception of a Christian-Cartesian soul split
off from all natural kinship? One more
suggestion may be found in Kantian morals - where man is acknowledged to be an
animal (in fact, from the cognitive point of view he is nothing else), yet at
the same time when looked at morally something radically different. In a review of an Italian work on evolution [13] Kant declared himself in sympathy with the
conception that man has developed from and is biologically akin to four-footed
beasts; but he uses the evidence in a peculiar way. Moscati had suggested that certain disorders
of the female reproductive system result from an upright posture obviously
lately and awkwardly assumed. Kant
declares this confirms his view that, while we are animals, we are
11. Symposium 207A f.
12. Phaedrus 249B.
13. Werke, ed. Cassirer, IV, 437.
126
botched, bad animals - and our purpose in life
is therefore something different from the satisfaction of our animal needs. So Kant could accept, I should think, a thoroughly
physiological interpretation of human behavior and still find that, though all
this be true, there is something more. The ethical situation remains what it is, at a
tangent to the natural or biological explanation, complete and self-sufficient
though the latter must always appear. Kant’s teleological language in talking of
human action (what Nature intends with us, etc.) is puzzling and his whole
puritanical account of man’s character most lamentable and one-sided: what less
loveable creature than the misanthropic philanthropist he so admires? Nevertheless, the general conception of men’s
complete animal and yet nonanimal nature is, if one may take it out of context,
most suggestive - as is the second and least abstract formulation of the moral
law: “Treat every human being always as an end and never as a means.”
But, of course, it must be said that, despite the ostensible division
of morality from metaphysics or theology, Kant did have a supernatural faith,
and a most austere one, to sustain his sense of duty; and without that support
most of us, I suspect, have difficulty in discovering in its Kantian purity the
moral law within on the presence of which the whole system admittedly rests. So we come back to the question suggested by
our glance at Hume and Plato:
Can an ethical system really stand on its own without
an adequate metaphysic; or what acceptable metaphysic can justify the ethical
standard we wish to support? That is a
problem far beyond the scope of this discussion, but one on which it looks as
if the question in hand must ultimately depend. Short of its treatment, one can merely point
out some of the factors that make our present perplexities about human values
something a little better than a Hobson’s choice between the Hobbesian machine-man
and the Cartesian-Christian separate and immortal mind.
LEMONT, ILLINOIS
127