The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Steve Fuller
Being There with Thomas Kuhn:
A Parable for Postmodern Times
*
History and Theory,
31 (3Oct. 1992, 241-275
Content
Last Didactic Macrohistory of Science
HHC: Titling added
|
Although The Structure of Scientjfic
Revolutions is one of the most influential books of this century, its
author, Thomas Kuhn, is notorious for disavowing most of the consequences
wrought by his text. Insofar as these
consequences have appeared “radical” or “antipositivist,” this article argues
that they are very misleading, and that Kuhn’s complaints are therefore well
placed. Indeed, Kuhn unwittingly
succeeded where Daniel Bell’s The End of Ideology tried and failed,
namely, to alleviate the anxieties of alienated academics and defensive
policy-makers by teaching them that they could all profit from solving their own
paradigmatic puzzles. The influence of
Structure is traced from the philosophy of science into the social
sciences and science policy.
Special attention is paid to the import of the General Education in Science
curriculum at Harvard, in which Kuhn taught for most of the period prior to
writing Structure. Harvard
President James Conant had designed this curriculum in order to keep “pure
science” in the good favor of the American public, in whose eyes it suffered
after the use of the atomic bomb. While
Conant was keen to stress the distinctiveness of science from other social
practices, Kuhn’s model seemed to provide a blueprint for reconstituting any
practice as a science. This enabled
potentially antiscientific academics to become scientists themselves, thereby
neutralizing any radical challenges to the ends of scientific inquiry.
The article concludes by reconstructing
some of the inchoate possibilities for radical critique that Kuhn’s success
preempted, and by making some suggestions for how they may be recovered in the
present academic environment.
“Perhaps the revolutionary never existed - but
then it was necessary to invent him.”
Alan Musgrave (on Kuhn’s denial of the radical
views imputed to him) [1]
Contrary to expectations, the title of this essay
does not refer to the recent interesting attempts to accommodate Kuhn’s account
of scientific practice to the existential phenomenology of Martin Heidegger.
[2] Rather,
it refers to the critically acclaimed motion picture starring Peter Sellers. In
what follows, the
* A review of the reception and
importance of Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions on
the thirtieth anniversary of its publication.
1. Cited in Paradigms and Revolutions, ed.
Gary Gutting (Notre Dame, Ind., 1979), 51.
2. See, especially, Joseph Rouse, Knowledge and
Power (Ithaca, N.Y., 1987).
241
movie Being There will serve as a “paradigm” for understanding the reception of Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, one of the most consistently influential academic works of the twentieth century
. [3] Since 1962, when the book was first published, over one million copies have been sold worldwide, including translations into sixteen languages. [4] Yet, from the first opportunity he was given (up to his most recent interview), Kuhn has disavowed all of the more exciting and radical theses imputed to him by friends and foes alike. [5] Indeed, he has even endeavored to demonstrate by example, in his subsequent work, that he could not have been capable of anything so exciting and radical. [6] It is doubtful that there has ever been another academic who has met the greatness thrust upon him with such apparent ingratitude. [7] What is more remarkable, of course, is how, in full cognizance of Kuhn’s disclaimers, so much of the academic world has nevertheless felt compelled to position themselves with regard to his work. [8] What might we learn from this very strange episode in the annals of scholarship? But, first, a quick trip to the movies.
The protagonist of Being There is Chauncey,
the ward of a wealthy Washingtonian whose death marks the beginning of the film.
Chauncey is a kindly man of childlike simplicity who, in the course of
settling the estate of his deceased employer, is subject to several
misunderstandings that, by the end of the film, land him as a candidate for the
presidency of the United States. The
comic element of the plot is that Chauncey never quite realizes what it is that
he is saying that makes all the bigwigs hold his opinion in increasingly high
regard. Indeed, for the most part,
Chauncey is uncomfortable with this newfound attention and makes periodic
protests that he is not the man they think he is.
Needless to say, these protests are
either ignored or themselves misinterpreted. From
the audience’s standpoint, what seems to be happening is that Chauncey’s
interlocutors take his quite literal references to gardening and television, the
3. Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions [1962], 2nd ed. (Chicago, 1970).
4. Figures cited in John Horgan, “Profile:
Reluctant Revolutionary - Thomas S. Kuhn Unleashed ‘Paradigm’ on the World,”
Scientific American (May 1991), 40.
5. This is perhaps the most consistent
feature of Kuhn’s self-referential remarks. See
Kuhn, Structure, 174-210; “Reflections on My Critics,” in Criticism
and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (Cambridge,
Eng., 1970), 231-278; The Essential Tension (Chicago, 1977), xxi- xxiii,
293; Horgan, 40.
6. See, in particular, the reception of his last
sustained historical work: Thomas Kuhn, Black-Body Radiation and the Quantum
Discontinuity, 1894-1912 (Oxford, 1978).
A sense of the disappointment of the reviewers is captured by the title
of the major symposium devoted to the book: Martin Klein, Abner Shimony, and
Trevor Pinch, “Paradigm Lost?” Isis 70 (1979), 429-440.
This book seems to have pleased only
positivists, internal historians of science, and practicing physicists.
7. Horgan quotes Kuhn as saying, “I’ve often said
I’m much fonder of my critics than my fans” (49). Karl Marx ran a close second
to Kuhn in his desire to disown his admirers.
8. Many of the luminous who have so positioned
themselves are collected in Gutting. However,
the most artful “Kuhnotropist” is undoubtedly the sociologist Robert Merton, who
tries to demystify any aura of genius that might surround Kuhn by showing that
the success of Structure can be easily explained by Merton’s own
“principle of cumulative advantage.” (The
explanation of Merton’s own genius in arriving at this principle will no doubt
be tackled by some future historian, hopefully not at the expense of one of
Merton’s own theories!) See Robert
Merton, The Sociology of Science: An Episodic Memoir (Carbondale, 111.,
1977), 71-108. I myself have indulged in
shameless Kuhnotropistry, as evidenced in Steve Fuller, Social Epistemology
(Bloomington, Ind., 1988), 85-89, 97- 98, 111-119, 142-169, 219-224.
This essay is partly in atonement for my
errant ways.
242
entire scope of his existence, as metaphors for
various aspects of political life. Moreover,
Chauncey unwittingly confers the utmost profundity on his utterances by speaking
not very often, and then only in short and simple sentences.
Being There is clearly a spoof on
the superficiality of American politics, but it is more than that.
Some of Chauncey’s interlocutors have
lingering doubts about his untraceable past and peculiar manner, but typically
they give him the benefit of the doubt and try to make the most of the
situation. In fact, the collective
participation needed to propel Chauncey to ever greater acclaim is increasingly
evident in the film, until he becomes a genuine rallying point for the disparate
individuals involved. From a similar
comedy of errors that has marked Kuhn’s reception, I hope to draw a somewhat
hopeful lesson. But for readers
unfamiliar with the career of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, a
few details are in order to show that “comedy of errors” does not exaggerate the
book’s reception in the field from which its influence has flowed, the
philosophy of science.
The first extensive critical review of Structure is the one that emblazoned Kuhn in the minds of philosophers. Appearing in one of America’s premier journals, it was written by a young, Harvard- trained philosopher who had already published several articles showing that the logical analysis of language championed by the logical positivists did not do justice even to the very science they cherished most, physics. Like all language-games, Dudley Shapere argued, physics too has an irreducibly pragmatic character that can be understood only by a historically sensitized version of ordinary language philosophy, that is, a study of what members of a particular physics community meant in the context of their utterance. [9] Although Shapere thought that Stephen Toulmin had made many of Kuhn’s points - and in a philosophically more perspicacious manner - perhaps a decade earlier, the express generality of Structure’s account of science and its innocence of any formal logical apparatus made it an apt vehicle for enumerating the full range of omissions from the positivist account of science
. [10] More-
9. Dudley Shapere, “The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions,” Philosophical Review 73 (1964), 383-394.
See also Shapere, “Meaning and
Scientific Change,” in Mind and Cosmos, ed. R. Colodny (Pittsburgh,
1966), 41-85. Shapere’s Harvard mentor
was Morton White, whose own work strongly anticipated the “pragmatist turn”
associated nowadays with Richard Rorty. See,
especially, Morton White, Towards a Reunion in Philosophy (Cambridge,
Mass., 1956). White’s attempt to
encompass analytic and continental philosophy under a comprehensive pragmatism
was overshadowed in his day by Quine’s more focused and largely internal
critique of positivism’s conception of language.
Among Shapere’s early Harvard-influenced essays include “Mathematical
Ideals and Metaphysical Concepts,” Philosophical Review 69(1960),
376-385; “Space, Time, and Language,” in Philosophy of Science: The Delaware
Seminar, ed. B. Baumrin (New York, 1963), 139-170.
10. Shapere cites Toulmin’s two books on the
philosophy of science which predate Kuhn’s: Stephen Toulmin, The Philosophy
of Science: An Introduction (London, 1951); Foresight and Understanding
(London, 1961). Toulmin shares
with Kuhn an early background in physics and shares with Shapere philosophical
training in linguistic analysis. Both of
Toulmin’s books went into several editions and (unlike Structure) were
picked up by commercial publishers. And
while Toulmin seemed to attract a wide audience (for example, both Ernest Nagel
and Jacques Barzun endorsed his books), I would suggest that the reason he never
garnered Kuhn-like attention was that he wrote in the understated
Wittgensteinian style of perceptively remarking on simple examples without
issuing anything that might smack of a “theory” or a “scheme.”
243
over, by making Kuhn out to be proposing an “anti-positivist” viewpoint, Shapere made himself appear less an opponent than a mediator of opposing camps. Thus, Shapere could demonstrate the value of philosophical sophistication in moderating the more wild-eyed claims of historians overly impressed with the remoteness of the past
. [11]
The subsequent “historicist” turn in the
philosophy of science - portrayed specifically as a “revolt against positivism”
- proves Shapere to have been largely successful in his immediate intention.
[12] Unfortunately,
there is little reason to think that it was an intention shared by Thomas Kuhn,
who openly solicited that doyen of positivists, Rudolf Carnap, to have
Structure published as part of the International Encyclopedia of Unified
Science. As personal correspondence
reveals, Carnap warmly reciprocated, complimenting Kuhn on having provided a
historical grounding - in the contrast between “normal” and “revolutionary”
science - for the positivist distinction between questions that are decidable
within the terms of a conceptual framework and those that require the
introduction of extramural factors. [13]
And,
over the years, Kuhn certainly has wanted to leave the impression that he has
been more influenced by positivist, or at least more broadly “analytic,”
considerations about the nature of language and knowledge than by the
historicist ones that his work supposedly generated.
[14] To
11. This was a recurrent theme in the work of
Norwood Russell Hanson, who was the most visible American standard-bearer for
the emerging field of “History and Philosophy of Science” from the publication
of Patterns of Discovery (Cambridge, Eng., 1958) to his death a decade
later. Unlike the other philosophers
considered here (including Kuhn), Hanson frequently appeared in the pages of
American newsstand periodicals (especially the Nation) during the late
1950s and early 1960s. Even pages from
Patterns were excerpted in The Saturday Review.
In addition, Hanson helped
established History & Philosophy of Science programs at Cambridge, Indiana, and
Yale Universities. Of the figures
discussed here, Hanson seemed to be the most preoccupied with defining and
crossing disciplinary boundaries. Characteristic
work in this vein include “Scientists and Logicians: A Confrontation,”
Science 138 (1962), 1311-1314; “The Irrelevance of History of Science to
Philosophy of Science,” in What I Do Not Believe and Other Essays, ed. S.
Toulmin and H. Woolf (Dordrecht, 1971), 274-287.
12. The canonical presentation of the story Shapere
wanted his audience to believe is The Struture of Scientific Theories,
ed. Frederick Suppe [1973], 2nd ed. (Urbana, 1977), 3-232.
In an afterword to the second edition,
Suppe predicted that Kuhn’s influence was waning and that the future of
historicist philosophy of science belonged to Shapere and Toulmin.
In retrospect, the most striking
omission from Suppe’s 800-page tome is any reference to the person who turned
out to carry the torch for historicism, Larry Laudan, whose Progress and Its
Problems (Berkeley, 1977) was published the very same year as the second
edition of Suppe’s book. Chapter seven
of Laudan’s book threw down the gauntlet at the emerging field Sociology of
Scientific Knowledge, which (see below) stands in an interesting relation to
Kuhn.
13. The Carnap-Kuhn correspondence is analyzed in
George Reisch, “Did Kuhn Kill Logical Empiricism?” Philosophy of Science
58 (1991), 264-277.
14. For Kuhn’s increasing tendency to embrace
positivism, see Suppe, 647. Also,
contrast Kuhn’s early disavowal of any connection to the Sociology of Scientific
Knowledge (Kuhn, Essential Tension, xxi-xxii), with Kuhn’s eagerness to
insert himself in recent philosophical debates in semantics and the theory of
reference (Kuhn, “Possible Worlds in History of Science,” in Possible Worlds
in Humanities, Arts and Sciences, ed. S. Allen [Berlin, 1989], 9-32).
Finally, consider Kuhn’s accommodating
posture to the criticisms made of his work by such positivistically inclined
philosophers as Carl Hempel and Wesley Salmon: Kuhn, “Rationality and Theory
Choice,” Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983), 563-570.
244
understand the overarching significance of
Structure, especially the sorts of projects it has helped and impeded, we
need to start taking seriously that Kuhn’s book constituted, pace Shapere,
less a revolt against positivism than a continuation of positivism by other
means. However, this is not to deny to
Shapere the honor of having turned Kuhn into an object of philosophical
fascination by parceling out Structure into analysis-sized problems of
“meaning-variance,” “theory-laden observation,” and “absolute presuppositions.”
In this way, Shapere enabled Kuhn to
become routinely discussed in the same breath as the ascendant philosophers of
science of his generation, especially Toulmin, Russ Hanson, and, of course, Paul
Feyerabend. [15]
In the Anglo-American philosophical
community of the early 1960s, Shapere’s constructed cohort of “historicists”
were still perceived - to refashion a bit of Kuhn - as mere anomaly-mongers,
proffering elaborate counterexamples to positivist accounts of explanation and
confirmation, anomalies which, once stripped of their historical superfluities,
would be rendered tractable to logical analysis. [16] The idea that the historicists might
replace or succeed the positivists in a common lineage did not
appear persuasive (or at least not an item discussed in the main philosophy of
science journals) until Imre Lakatos published a volume of papers from a
symposium held during the 1965 meeting of the International Congress of Logic,
Methodology, and the Philosophy of Science, which was hosted by Lakatos’s home
institution, the London School of Economics. [17] The symposium in
question was officially devoted to the implications of Karl Popper’s philosophy
of science, but Lakatos was keen on using the
15. Kuhn, Toulmin, and Imre Lakatos (to be
discussed below) were all born in 1922. Hanson
and Feyerabend were born in 1924. Shapere
aside, the clustering of these figures as an intellectual cohort is largely a
product of the next generation of philosophers, such as Ian Hacking, Larry
Laudan, Harold Brown, Fred Suppe, and Peter Machamer, all of whom were born
around 1940. See, especially,
Machamer, “Understanding Scientific Change,” Studies in History and
Philosophy of Sciences (1975), 373-381; Brown, Perception, Theory, and
Commitment: The New Philosophy of Science (Chicago, 1977).
The latter, a textbook, received Kuhn’s
official endorsement.
16. Of all the historicists, this unflattering
image stuck most readily to Feyerabend, who in 1964 was most famous for
challenging Ernest Nagel’s model of explanation by reduction: Paul Feyerabend,
“Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism,” in Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, ed. H. Feigl and G. Maxwell (Minneapolis, 1962), III,
28-97. In retrospect, this challenge is
normally regarded as the first time the authority of the historical record had
successfully opposed a formal logical model. Although
few philosophers relinquished the goal of reductionism at that time, rather than
simply ignoring Feyerabend as raising irrelevant concerns, they endeavored to
accommodate Feyerabend’s challenge within the model.
See Kenneth Schaffner, “Approaches to
Reduction,” Philosophy of Science 34 (1967), 137-147.
During most of the 1960s, Kuhn’s name
typically appeared in philosophy journals as a corroborating footnote to a
discussion of Feyerabend’s challenges. It
is important to remember that Feyerabend did not consolidate his own philosophy
of science into a readily available text until the mid-1970s: Feyerabend,
Against Method (London, 1975). Before
that time, Feyerabend was taken to be a radical philosopher of physics, whose
views had interesting implications for the philosophy of science more generally.
An apt comparison in our own day is with
Arthur Fine, whom Joseph Rouse expects will come out of the closet shortly.
See Rouse, “The Politics of Postmodern
Philosophy of Science,” Philosophy of Science 58 (1991), 607-627.
17. Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge,
ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (Cambridge, Eng., 1970).
245
forum to present himself as the heir-apparent to Popper’s chair. [18] However, as fate would have it, Kuhn stole the show, with his contribution to a Popper Festschrift being the one in terms of which all the other speakers - including Popper, Lakatos, Toulmin, and Feyerabend - rewrote their papers
. [19] Thus, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, despite the Popperism packed into its title, is normally taught in seminars today as a repository of “famous responses to Kuhn.” And, after its publication, Kuhn starts to get routinely cited in order to legitimate various developments across the humanities and social sciences. [20]
Despite Shapere’s success at mounting a movement
against the positivist regime in the philosophy of science, he failed to
anticipate that his main vehicle, Kuhn, would turn out to be a Trojan Horse.
Because we still think of Feyerabend,
Toulmin, Hanson, and Kuhn as of a piece, the views of the first three thinkers
tend to be reduced to those of the fourth, the details of which are typically
best known to us. However, this
reduction obscures the criticisms that Kuhn’s supposed comrades lodged against
his views, which were more substantial than those that the positivists ever
raised. A less pronounced, but similar,
occlusion of differences has even occurred to the parallel band of
anti-positivists in Britain represented by Popper and his followers.
They, in particular, detected an unsavory affinity between Kuhn and the
positivists. Kuhn seemed to identify the
essence of the scientific enterprise with puzzle-solving, specifically filling
in the gaps of a paradigm, a practice that suspiciously resembled the logical
articulation and empirical confirmation of a theory.
Where was the image of science as a
critical enterprise, one - as Popper liked to say - continuous with Socratic
questioning? In Kuhn’s scheme, the
answer was to be found in the relatively rare instances of “revolutionary
science,” whose resolution depended entirely on which of the contesting sides
eventually turns out to have the most followers.
Thus, the most important moment in any inquiry - namely, determining how
to proceed so as to best satisfy the ends of inquiry-
18. Thus, Lakatos’s most famous and sustained
post-dissertation work appeared in this volume: “Falsification and the
Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,” in Criticism, 91-196.
A relevant point here is that Popper was
awarded his chair at the LSE in the “Logic of the Social Sciences,” based
largely on such wartime works as The Poverty of Historicism and The
Open Society and Its Enemies. Not
surprisingly, Popper’s main lobbyist for a permanent post at the LSE had been
the liberal economist Friedrich von Hayek. The
seminal work in methodology for which Popper is perhaps best known today, The
Logic of Scientific Discovery, was a product of his younger days in Austria
and was not translated into English until 1959.
Thus, Popper’s reputation as a general philosopher of science in the
English-speaking world emerged as part of “the revolt against positivism,” even
though Carnap (again!) supported the original publication of Popper’s book in
the series associated with the positivist journal, Erkenntnis.
19. Thomas Kuhn, “Logic of Discovery or Psychology
of Research?” in Criticism, 1-23.
20. The best of these papers are compiled in
Gutting. The publication of Criticism
coincided with the second edition of Structure, in which Kuhn
answered some of his critics in a postscript. As
one might expect, Kuhn has himself consistently denied that his model of
scientific change applies to the humanities and social sciences.
In fact, Kuhn had this to say when
invited to a conference in which Structure was discussed as one of the
major advances of twentieth century social sciences: “I know a great deal less
than I should, and in any case virtually nothing at all, about the social
sciences and I will not create confusion by bluffing it” (letter to Karl
Deutsch, cited in Advances in the Social Sciences, 1900-1980, ed. K.
Deutsch, A. Markovits, and J. Platt [Cambridge, Mass., 1986], 278).
246
was removed from the realm of rational deliberation to an apparently blind process akin to natural selection, the so-called Planck Effect. [21] As we shall see, the political imagery of revolution added an element of risk to this unpredictability, which subtly suggested that the questioning of ends should occur neither too often nor for too long. [22]
It is worth dwelling for a moment on the
significance that Kuhn’s philosophical critics attached to the word “rational”
and especially its counterpart, “irrational.” These
words charged a great many academic debates in the 1960s, many of which involved
Popper as the standard-bearer for “critical rationalism.” [23] A
common way of describing the aftermath of these debates provided much of the
early legitimation for the first field to declare itself the natural successor
to Kuhn’s project, namely, the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.
[24] According
to
21. “Max Planck, surveying his own career in his
Scientific Autobiography, sadly remarked that ‘a new scientific truth does
not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but
rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that
is familiar with it” (Kuhn, Structure, 151).
22. At the time, Kuhn’s fondness for the imagery of
religious conversion raised the most Popperian hackles, as it seemed to imply
that scientific revolutions could not be resolved rationally precisely
because they involved life decisions of the utmost importance.
Ironically the Popperians actually
agreed with the positivists and Kuhn that decisions concerning the “absolute
presuppositions” of one’s practice are a matter of free existential choice.
(I imagine that neo-Kantianism,
especially as filtered by Max Weber, is the source of this sentiment.
See Robert Proctor, Value-Free
Science? Purity and Power in Modern Knowledge [Cambridge, Mass., 1991], 15
1-154.) However, for that very
reason, Popperians have held that the merits of such a choice must be evaluated
in terms of its consequences (the extent of which are, unfortunately, rarely
specified). Thus, rational beings act so
as to be constrained only by the anticipation that they may want to reverse that
decision at a later date, if the consequences of their actions do not turn out
as planned. An ethic of “piecemeal
engineering” (Popper’s phrase) naturally follows from this imperative.
Ironically, in the same year that Kuhn’s
book was published, a work by a student of Popper’s was published, initially to
more fanfare, which argued against the irrationality implicit in the refusal of
Liberal Protestant theologians to contest absolute presuppositions: See W. W.
Bartley III, The Retreat to Commitment [1962], 2nd ed. (La Salle, Ill.,
1984).
23. The most famous was probably the German
Positivismusstreit that pitted Popperian social and economic theorists
(including Ralf Dahrendorf and Hans Albert) against the Frankfurt School,
especially Theodor Adorno and his understudy, Jurgen Habermas, who rose to
prominence in the following decade for his skill in mediating and synthesizing
alternatives forms of rationality. See
The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology, ed. Theodor Adorno (London,
1976). Another noteworthy rationality
debate, confined largely to Britain and its spheres of influence, concerned
whether there were cross-culturally valid, universal standards of reasoning.
It pitted against one another noted
anthropologists and philosophers, such as Ernest Gellner, Peter Winch, Alasdair
Maclntyre, Charles Taylor, Steven Lukes, and Ian Jarvie.
See Rationality, ed. Bryan Wilson
(Oxford, 1970).
24. In its early days, the Sociology of Scientific
Knowledge (SSK) was known as the “Strong Programme” to distinguish its own
methodological imperatives from those of the founder of the sociology of
knowledge, Karl Mannheim, who argued that the rational methodology of the
natural sciences precluded them from sociological explanation.
Since the early 1970s, when SSK first
made its presence felt from the Science Studies Unit at Edinburgh University, a
burgeoning and diverse body of empirical research has been promoted in
departments of “Science & Technology Studies” in Europe, Australia, and
increasingly America. The “Edinburgh
School” made the first institutional attempt to integrate history, philosophy,
and sociology of science - the three fields that Kuhn was seen as having brought
together in Structure. The
canonical formulation is David Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery
(London, 1976). Barry Barnes has drawn
detailed connections between Kuhn’s work and subsequent developments in SSK in
T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (Oxford, 1982).
247
this account, rationalist philosophers had
supposed that, without articulate knowledge of the norms of the scientific
method, all order in science would dissolve and scientists would simply go about
doing whatever they pleased. Nevertheless,
so the sociologists argued, by closely attending to the laboratory practices of
scientists, one can see that they get on quite well and regularly, even though
they are typically unable to articulate the principles that govern their
practices. What this seems to show,
then, is that no obvious empirical place can be found in scientific practice for
the methodological norms so cherished by philosophers.
While philosophers should have met this
line of argument easily, it is clear, in retrospect, that they did not. [25]
As a result, a valuable
opportunity was missed to explain the relevant sense in which the
rational/irrational distinction had to be drawn in order for the normative
philosophical project to flourish.
When one looks at the typical cases of “irrationality” that worry Popperians and other philosophers so much, they are not associated with mass hysteria or other undisciplined forms of behavior. Rather, irrationality is attached to a certain complacency or inertia that arises from one’s expectations being repeatedly confirmed or challenged only in ways that are easily accommodated or rebuffed. Rationality, then, is the turn of mind that resists habit, typically by criticism and actively confounding expectations
. [26] Kuhn’s apparent satisfaction with the preponderance of science being unreflective puzzle-solving is the clearest indication to his philosophical critics that Structure presents an “irrationalist” picture of the scientific enterprise. [27] One cannot underestimate the extent to which this Enlightenment idea of “Reason” triumphing over superstition and tradition remains a ready source of philosophical self-imagery even in our own day. [28] However, in the heat of philosophical debate, this eighteenth-century notion has been periodically confused with a conception of reason that came to the fore in the nineteenth century, especially with the rise of positivism. Here “reason” is a governing principle, one that regulates the growth of knowledge by directing and measuring the path of inquiry. Presupposed is that, without such a governing principle, human energies would be dissipated into random motion. In that case, irrationality would indeed be akin to mass hysteria. [29]
25. A compilation of the generally acrimonious
proceedings is The Rationality Debates: The Sociological Turn, ed. James
Robert Brown (Dordrecht, 1984).
26. In fact, the distinguished Popperian
anthropologist Ernest Gellner bases his entire philosophy of history on the idea
that, because logical coherence is inversely related to social coherence, any
attempt to achieve a more logically comprehensive picture of reality has
required challenging the normative integrity of one’s own social order.
See Ernest Geliner, Plough, Sword,
and Book (Chicago, 1989). It should
be clear that I concur with the spirit of Geilner’s thesis, if not its exact
letter.
27. See Popper’s and Feyerabend’s comments in
Criticism: Karl Popper, “Normal Science and Its Dangers,” 51—58; Paul
Feyerabend, “Consolations for the Specialist,” 197-229.
28. What has changed over the last two centuries is
the metaphysical warrant for Enlightenment. There
is less of an appeal to Reason as the essence of human nature (though it remains
in Jürgen Habermas, today’s leading Enlightenment thinker).
For a non-essentialist version, see
Steve Fuller, Philosophy, Rhetoric, and the End of Knowledge (Madison,
Wisc., 1992).
29. On the changing conceptions of reason, see
Maurice Mandelbaum, History, Man, and Reason: A Study in the Nineteenth
Century (Baltimore, 1971). Kuhn is
not alone in confusing the two senses of reason.
Richard Rorty’s Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature refutes the
notion of [“foundationalism,” which is
tied directly to the nineteenth-century conception, but part three (and his
subsequent work) indicates that he intends to have buried the eighteenth-century
conception as well. Rorty’s role as
an entry point for American understandings of recent French philosophical
critiques of reason has compounded the confusion.
Thus, while it is common for both friends and foes of “postmodernism” to
lump Jacques Derrida’s On Grammatology and Jean-Francois Lyotard’s The
Postmodern Condition as part of the same general antirationalist tendency,
Derrida specifically aims to undermine the positivist conception of reason by
engaging in an Enlightenment-like interrogation of that conception, whereas
Lyotard indicts the Enlightenment conception of reason precisely for its
totalizing sense of critique, which has destructive consequences for the
heterogeneity of knowledge production that marks our times.]
HHC: [bracketed]
displayed on page 249 of original.
248
To illustrate the confusion that results when
these two conceptions of reason are run together, consider Lakatos’s famous
charge that Kuhn is offering a “mob psychology” account of scientific
revolutions. [30]
In
response, calmer heads have reminded us that Lakatos overstates his case, as
Kuhn never really said that scientists take leave of their senses once shaken
from the spell of a paradigm. However
true this may be as a point of Kuhn exegesis, the response fails to get at the
nub of Lakatos’s complaint, which can only be understood once we notice that his
accusation was originally made in the context of an attack on the positivists
(whom Lakatos calls “justificationists”). For
a point that unites Kuhn and the positivists is their unwillingness to associate
radical criticism, or a choice between alternative normative systems, with
anything they would be willing to call “rational.”
For them, rationality is in the act of
rule-following, not in the act of rule-making or rule-breaking.
Lakatos understood well the significance of this distinction, which
corresponds, respectively, to the evaluative and the prescriptive sides of the
normative enterprise. [31]
As
philosophy’s command over the course of knowledge production has receded in the
face of academic specialization, philosophy’s normative posture has shifted from
prescription to evaluation, from legislator to judge, or still more modestly, to
accountant, a keeper of someone else’s books. [32] Victim
to a febrile intellect and an early death,
30. Lakatos, “Falsification,” 178.
31. See Imre Lakatos, “History of Science and Its
Rational Reconstructions,” in Scientific Revolutions, ed. I. Hacking
(Oxford, 1981), 108, n. 2. Among
historicist philosophers of science, Toulmin has been the most astute in
locating the origins of prescriptivist approaches to philosophy in legislation.
He sees the task of setting up ideals
and standards for comparing the claims of incommensurable theories as modeled on
the law-making needed for a jurisdiction that encompasses communities with quite
disparate local customs and entitlements: What
Socrates did in theory, Solon had already done in practice.
See Stephen Toulmin, Human
Understanding (Princeton 1972), 86-87. Explicitly
drawing on Toulmin, Donald Kelley has recently extended this thesis to include
the social sciences as further theorizations of the legislative impulse.
See Kelley, The Human Measure
(Cambridge, Mass., 1990).
32. The legislator/judge distinction goes back to
Kant’s distinction between regulative and constitutive principles of reason that
applied, respectively, to transcendental and empirical reality.
With regard to the comment on
“accountants,” since Lakatos’s death in 1974, the shift from prescription to
evaluation has become more pronounced in the philosophy of science, as
increasing numbers of younger philosophers have become adept in the details of
the special sciences (especially physics and biology).
This adeptness has enabled them to
function as referees for the intramural disputes of the sciences in question.
The intellectual godfather for much of
this generation is David Hull, a philosopher of biology who served for several
years as editor of the journal Systematic Zoology.
The philosophical lessons from that
experience are drawn in David Hull, Science as a Process (Chicago, 1988).
249
Lakatos never managed to stem this tide, though an interest in reasserting prescriptivism in the philosophy of science might ultimately explain his distinctive doctrines concerning the history of science
. [33]
The idea that Kuhn helped diminish the
normative dimension of the philosophy of science merits some attention, since
the first thing one usually says about Kuhn is that he undermined (“once and for
all”) the observation-theory, fact-value, empirical-normative,
descriptive-prescriptive distinctions from accounts of science.
Whatever else the latter term in each
binary may mean, Kuhn (on behalf of a litany of historicists) is said to have
shown that it “loads” or “impregnates” the former term.
Doesn’t such imagery suggest the
ascent of the normative? Here we
need to dig a bit deeper, for long before they spawned opponents, the
positivists had themselves already discovered that observations are
theory-impregnated (in the sense that observational content is deducible from
theoretical premises in a formal scientific language) and that facts are
value-laden (at least in the elliptical sense that the theoretical language one
uses for inquiry involves a free value choice).
[34] Moreover,
the positivists and the anti-positivists agreed on a generally instrumental view
of scientific language, one which portrayed theories as rules for governing the
conduct of inquiry. The key difference
between the positivists and their opponents lay in the attitude they took toward
these common elements. Whereas the
positivists believed that theory- or value-ladenness threatened the objectivity
of inquiry, unless explicitly circumscribed by an account of “testability,”
anti-positivists tended to treat the uncertain objectivity of inquiry as a brute
fact that could only be mitigated but never completely eliminated.
For his part, Kuhn masks this
uncertainty by taking responsibility for the choice between scientific languages
out of the hands of self-conscious deliberators and placing it in the “invisible
hand” of the Planck Effect. In so doing,
Kuhn effectively reintroduces a sharp distinction between the “empirical” and
“normative” questions of science in terms of a difference between the
determinable present (normal science) and an indeterminate future (revolutionary
science). This move made it that much
harder for philosophers like Lakatos to motivate, let alone execute, a theory of
“rationality” suitable for prescribing the course of inquiry.
In terms of the eighteenth- (“Enlightenment”) and
nineteenth- (“Positivist”) century conceptions of reason sketched above, Kuhn’s
account can be seen as having worked in the following way to marginalize a
strong sense of prescriptivism in the philosophy of science:
33. Certainly, Lakatos’s most notorious
contribution to philosophy has been his bald-faced endorsement of rational
reconstructions of the history of science, however much they may deviate from
the actual historical record. Whatever
else one may wish to say about such reconstructions, they offer a sense of how
the history would have gone, had it unfolded according to the philosopher’s
favorite rules. If philosophers can no
longer prescribe the course of knowledge production, the next best thing may be
to fantasize how much better it would have been had they been allowed to do so!
34. What are “value-free” and
“theory-neutral” are the possible observations that deductively follow from the
chosen theoretical language, and their testability by a method whose validity
does not depend on whether the tested theory is true or false.
250
(1) Through the Enlightenment spectacles with
which the Popperians looked at Kuhn, Kuhn is an irrationalist because he
valorizes the unreflective practices of normal science over the reflective ones
of revolutionary science. Popperians see
Kuhn as simply a traditionalist.
(2) However, “normal science” is not quite the old
idea of “tradition” in a new guise. Traditions
aim to preserve the past in the present, but normal science exhibits
cumulative growth. Traditional are
the practices in which normal scientists engage; not traditional are the
puzzle-solving domains to which those practices are applied.
Here Kuhn trades on the positivist
conception of reason, which predicates steady progress issuing from a firm
epistemic base.
(3) In this way, reason is successfully contained,
or relativized, to a paradigm, but inexpressible between paradigms.
Thus, there is no place for a critical
form of rationality that is independent from, let alone oppositional to, the
dominant epistemic practices of the time. [35]
To illustrate the sort of rationality that drops
out of Kuhn’s picture of science, consider some apt analogies from the history
of capitalist economics.
Corresponding to the Enlightenment conception of reason is the entrepreneur,
whose innovative spirit continually widens the sphere of production by breaking
up cottage industries and guild mentalities. Corresponding
to the Positivist conception of reason is the manufacturer whose factory out
produces all competitors. Whereas the
enemy of entrepreneurs - their vision of the irrational - is the sub-optimally
productive user of resources (say, one of Marx’s rentiers), the enemy of
manufacturers is the destroyer of resources (say, a Luddite attacking the
machines in their factory). The
“Kuhnian” economist is essentially a friend to the manufacturer but an enemy to
the entrepreneur. However, without a
supply of entrepreneurs periodically upsetting existing trade patterns, engaging
in “creative destruction” (in Schumpeter’s inspired terms), capitalism would
itself soon become just another scheme for perpetuating inherited wealth, only
this time wealth based on manufacture instead of agriculture.
In that case, if one is not a member of
a major industrial family, and emigration is not a possibility, then violent
overthrow of the system would seem to be the only means available for the
disenfranchised to acquire wealth. This
is where a “Kuhnian” economics would leave us - a place not so far from where
entrepreneurship’s leading theorist, Joseph Schumpeter, thought capitalism was
already heading. However, Schumpeter had
issued a proviso, one which may also be applicable to the fate of science in
Kuhn’s account. Schumpeter believed that
violent overthrow was no longer a real possibility, given the risk to the
relatively high standard of living that even the disenfranchised (supposedly)
enjoyed in mature capitalist economies. Rather,
entrepreneurship would itself probably be routinized, as
35. Thus, while one can understand Sandra Harding’s
reliance on Kuhn to refute positivism, Kuhn’s work itself provides little
comfort to her own “standpoint epistemology,” which implies a privileged
critical perspective for groups marginalized from the dominant forms of power in
society. See Harding, The Science
Question in Feminism (Ithaca, 1986), 197-210.
251
innovation became one more thing regulated by a state planning board. [36] A similar story has been told about the diminished prospects for scientific revolutions in the future, given the heavy personnel and material investments that have already been made in current forms of “Big Science.” [37] The question that needs to be asked of these gloomy forecasts is whether they are anything more than an artifact of an account of science that does not recognize a place for rational criticism outside of the existing epistemic power structure. [38]
Although it would go against the “Being There”
thesis to conclude that Kuhn was trying to foist an irrationalist image
upon radical criticism, Structure nevertheless does seem to have had this
effect on its readers, most noticeably on Paul Feyerabend, who openly converted
to irrationalism in the 1970s, reveling in the “anarchy” that would allegedly be
produced in a world without a uniform scientific method.
In a sense, Feyerabend merely acquiesced
to Kuhn’s vision of what Popper’s call for a “permanent revolution” in science
would look like - a vision that was, to be sure, shared by the positivists, who
always believed that Popper was courting cognitive chaos by eschewing
definitions in philosophy and advising that scientists suspect all their
knowledge claims as presumptions whose erroneous bases have yet to be discovered.
39 The
difference between Popper and Feyerabend is, of course, Kuhn.
Whereas Popper saw himself as subjecting
the ends and means of inquiry to the same critical standards as the products of
inquiry, Feyerabend takes Popper to be offering a politically naive strategy for
wresting the course of inquiry from the Big Science powermongers.
As Feyerabend might put it, the problem
is not that the powermongers won’t
36. The locus classicus of this view is
Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (New York, 1942).
37. A telling point here is that, in recent years,
with the exception of Feyerabend, no philosophical attention has been lavished
on the idea that science should do something other than it already is.
Since Kuhn’s work, philosophers of
science have been in virtually complete agreement about which instances of
historical and contemporary science deserve praise or blame.
Nowadays the debates turn on the best
way to account for the agreed upon cases. See,
for example, Scientific Realism, ed. Jarrett Leplin (Berkeley, 1984).
Contrary to received wisdom,
Structure did not so much “refute” the concept of progress in science as to
change the subject to one in which the philosophers disagreed only over the
finer points of semantics. For a
sophisticated account justifying the slowdown of science, influenced in part by
Kuhn, see Nicholas Rescher, The Limits of Science (Berkeley, 1984).
38. One brave attempt to lay down an external
rational critique of Big Science is Harry Redner, The Ends of Science
(Boulder, Cob., 1987), esp. 252-253 (a severe critique of Kuhn).
As Sujatha Raman has pointed out to me,
an emerging model for rationally criticizing Big Science from outside the
epistemic power structure is post-Cold War “downsizing” and “conversion” of the
U.S. military establishment, which is currently (albeit painfully) being
negotiated by career soldiers and civilian bureaucrats.
Here, too, one finds the rhetoric of
“great risk” that supposedly attends any attempt to alter radically the
institution’s scale and scope.
39. Several philosophers have noticed that
Feyerabend presupposes the positivists’ rather limited conception of rationality
so that he appears more outrageous than he really is.
See Arne Naess, “Paul Feyerabend - A
Green Hero?,” ed. Gonzalo Munevar, Beyond Reason: Essays on the Philosophy of
Paul K. Feyerabend (Dordrecht, 1991), 403-416.
It is worth recalling that, of all the
Popperians, Feyerabend was the only one whose early reputation was built as a
technical critic of positivism, which suggests that he may have ingested more
positivist dogma than he and his readers have realized.
See note 16.
252
listen to reason, but that they listen all too
well! Notice here that reason is
presumed to be always “internal” to science. The
only politically appropriate responses to Big Science, then, are forced entries,
withdrawals of support, and displays of irreverence - all, in one way or other,
violent departures from reason. [40]
But why must radical change occur radically?
In other words, why is reason
specifically precluded from being a vehicle by which a radical departure can be
made in the course of one’s inquiries? When
Popper remarked that the wonderful thing about humanity’s place in evolution was
that our theories could die in our stead, he was alluding precisely to this
missing sensibility, that risking an idea is not the same as risking a life.
To portray scientific revolutions in
apocalyptic terms - as Feyerabend does for fun and defenders of science do in
fear - is to overlook the potentially invisible character of such
revolutions. My choice of terms here is
quite deliberate, as “The Invisibility of Revolutions” is the title of chapter
eleven of Structure. But Kuhn
takes the relevant sense of “invisibility” to involve the following claims: (1)
that the outcome of a revolution is determined not by clashing parties coming to
agreement, but by the research choices subsequently made by their students; (2)
that the revolutionary character of paradigm change is obscured by subsequent
textbook writers who make the transition appear continuous.
I will consider (2) below, but let me
focus now on (1), the Planck Effect, which implies that argumentation over the
scientific research agenda benefits the spectators more than the participants.
In one sense, Kuhn’s point is
undeniable, insofar as the champions of one research agenda rarely take
themselves to be swayed by the arguments of their opponents.
However, to leave the matter at that is
to ignore the ways in which partisan positions shift, often unintentionally and
imperceptibly, in the course of debate, as the stakes and implications of
acceding to one argument over another appear in different contexts.
A position that one would never have
adopted at the start of a dispute may become easier to accept later, in large
part because the very practice of arguing will have made one accustomed
to the other’s position. Moreover, the person may not believe that he or she has
conceded anything “essential” to her position along the way.
Only in retrospect can a historian
detect that a subtle shift in the burden of proof took place that enabled the
acceptance of a previously intolerable point of view.
[41] Thus,
radical change can
40. Dominique Lecourt, philosophical advocate of
“proletarian science” during the French student uprising of 1968, has recently
bemoaned the fact that inquiries into the ends of science have become
monopolized by critics strongly influenced by the right-wing irrationalism of
Spengler and Heidegger. Even when the
critics have had left-wing pretensions, as in the case of the Green movement,
they suppose that science can only be opposed by engaging in practices
contrary to those of science. Feyerabend
has certainly contributed to this sentiment in Europe, which goes against the
self-critical rationalism of both Popperians and Marxists, despite their
disagreement on so many other matters. However,
as Lecourt rightly observes, these rationalists have taken today’s
“technoscience” as having greater facticity than “nature” itself.
See Lecourt, “The Scientist and the
Citizen: A Critique of Technoscience,” Philosophical Forum 23 (1992),
174-178.
41. I develop this point in Fuller, Social
Epistemology, 99-116; and in Steve Fuller, Philosophy of Science and Its
Discontents (Boulder, Cob., 1989), 65-70.
253
occur quite unradically, indeed, invisibly. However, conspicuously absent from Kuhn’s account is any discussion of how argumentation may facilitate this transition. The absence is “conspicuous” because the other historicists in Shapere’s original cohort - Hanson, Toulmin, and Feyerabend - explicitly made argumentation central to an understanding of how scientific change occurs
. [42] Despite their differing emphases on this process, they made a point of distancing what they mean by “argument” from formal logical deduction, in order to convey the idea that the merits of alternative research agendas, or theories, are not already implicit in their ideal formulations, just waiting to be deduced; rather the theories’ respective merits do not become evident until they are articulated publicly in terms of one another. [43] Of course, there are all too many instances in the history of science when the relevant rivals have not directly confronted one another, and so their incommensurability remained until the Planck Effect kicked in. However, a priori there is no reason to take this state of affairs as incorrigible. But was an alternative normative account available in the 1960s? The answer is that crucial elements were available, but they were not brought together into a coherent and persuasive whole. The key lies in following the career of rhetoric during this period; here our main witness is Toulmin.
In the early 1960s, Toulmin was known not only,
and perhaps not primarily, as a philosopher of science but as a moral theorist
and philosophical logician. His
youthful work, The Place of Reason in Ethics, had successfully challenged
the positivist dictum that value issues were emotively based attitudes - “mere
ejaculations,” in A. J. Ayer’s words - not susceptible to rational argument.
[44] In
place of the sharp dualism between scientific rationality and moral rhetoric,
Toulmin proposed that both discourses were “rational” and “rhetorical” in
exactly the same way. In practice, this
meant showing that ethics is an inquiry into what is really good, which
signaled that reasons could be mustered and contested in the same way as in
science. However, it also meant
importing a conception of scientific reasoning that had a strongly rhetorical
character, one
42. Credit for first realizing this point about
Kuhn goes to Israel Scheffler, Science and Subjectivity (Indianapolis,
1967).
43. Unlike the positivists, who portrayed
scientific theories as generating predictions that are then tested against
observations, both Toulmin and Hanson describe scientists more like judges who
look for the rule (theory) under which the case at hand (observation) can be
best subsumed. This reflects a shift in
philosophical thinking from confirmation to explanation as the main business of
science. Philosophers of science, then,
presumably are like the legislators who construct (discover?) the rules by which
the contesting interpretations of the case can be resolved.
For example, in Patterns of Discovery
Hanson follows a strategy, familiar in constitutional law, of eliciting
legislative principles from the conflict that arises from judges deciding “hard
cases” - in Hanson’s case, concerning the motion of elementary particles.
As legal theorists are wont to argue,
Hanson too claims that if the principles he has elicited apply for this hard
case, then a fortiori they apply to the more routine cases of scientific
discovery as well. See Hanson,
Patterns, 2-3. By contrast, the
positivists focused on the logic of these more routine cases, which are
essentially generated as observations by the dominant scientific theory.
Kuhn stands with the positivists on
seeing theory-driven research as mostly “mopping up operations,” but
occasionally turning up Hanson-like phenomena, which are best seen as
“anomalies.”
44. Stephen Toulmin, The Place of Reason in
Ethics (Cambridge, Eng., 1950).
254
in which “reality” defines a pragmatic limit to a particular inquiry, the moment when its participants no longer feel the need to pursue a matter any further. Of course, the inquiry can later be reopened, with “reality” then being the subsequent point of closure. Indeed, science has institutional mechanisms to ensure that that happens. [45] Ethics, Toulmin observed, is not so endowed, but that is only a matter of convention, one perhaps worth revising so that people are not led to think - as the positivist view might suggest - that important value issues are purely personal matters. Toulmin made more explicit his endorsement of a rhetorically based, anti-positivist conception of reason in The Uses of Argument, a book that started to become very influential among Speech Communication scholars in the late 1960s. [46] However, when it was first published in 1958, Toulmin’s wholesale rejection of the concept of formal validity - the idea that there are forms of argument that are rationally acceptable regardless of their content - made the book very unpopular with its primary audience, philosophers, even among those who recognized that formal logic provided an inadequate model of human reasoning. [47]
The point of this brief excursus into Toulmin’s early thought is that, unlike Kuhn and the positivists, Toulmin never drew a sharp line between reasoning about empirical and normative matters. In fact, he was so keen on eliminating any such distinction that he challenged its ultimate philosophical basis, the Humean contrast between empirical content and logical form. However, Toulmin never worked out an alternative conception of scientific reasoning. True, he actually predated Kuhn’s use of “paradigm” by one year, using the word to mean an “ideal of natural order” in terms of which the adequacy of particular explanations would be judged. So defined, a paradigm anchored scientific argument by establishing a presumption, say in the case of Newtonian mechanics, in favor of bodies moving rectilinearly unless impeded. [48] Clearly, Toulmin here was groping toward a theory of rhetoric, with his use of “paradigm” recognizably falling under the rhetorical category of topos
. [49] However, crucially lacking from Toulmin’s account was an understanding of how radical
45. Toulmin would later call practices of
this sort “compact.” See Human
Understanding, 378ff. Toulmin’s discussion of compactness has influenced the
interest that Sociologists of Scientific Knowledge have had with how scientific
disputes are “closed” and then “reopened.” See
Harry Collins and Trevor Pinch, Frames of Meaning (London, 1982); Harry
Collins, Changing Order (London, 1985).
46. Stephen Toulmin, The Uses of Argument
(Cambridge, Eng., 1958). The recent
spate of interest in Toulmin among German philosophers is due to the
incorporation of Toulmin’s ideas about validity in the theory of communicative
action put forth by Jurgen Habermas, who, in turn, learned of Toubmin’s work
from the Speech Communication people.
The canonical status of Toulmin’s work in this field is symbolized by a
place in Handbook of Argumentation Theory, ed. F. van Eemeren, R.
Grootendorst, and T. Kruiger (Amsterdam, 1987), 162-207.
47. See, especially, Peter Manicas, “On Toulmin’s
Contribution to Logic and Argumentation,” Journal of the American Forensic
Association 3 (1966), 83-94.
48. Toubmin, Foresight, 56.
49. The topoi surrounding the breakdown of a
paradigm have been explored more recently in Kenneth Zagacki and William Keith,
“Rhetoric, Topoi, and Scientific Revolution,” Philosophy and Rhetoric
25 (1992), 59-78.
255
change could arise in the course of argument: How can people operating with incommensurable paradigms come to see one another as mutually relevant audiences worthy of sustained attention and perhaps even mutual incorporation? Toulmin failed to answer this difficult question because he underestimated the need for arguers (including himself, as aspiring revolutionary) to build ethos with their audiences. There are no captive audiences in science. If the Planck Effect is as prevalent as Kuhn maintained, then obviously scientists can never take for granted that colleagues holding contrary views will listen to them. Traditionally, the function of ethos in rhetoric has been to build community from audiences with little, if any, prior common cause. The need for the different classes of a society to join forces in times of war would thus be a typical test of a leader’s ethos. 50 While this aspect of rhetoric would gain renewed prominence in the l970s, with the reissuance of the works of Kenneth Burke, it was quite the opposite of what philosophers especially, but even some rhetoricians, had only a decade earlier taken the scope of rhetoric to be. [51]
In reducing the voice of reason to that of a
scientific insider, Structure managed to satisfy an aspiration left
unfulfilled by the original logical positivists.
The key was that Kuhn built change into the very logic of science.
Here Kuhn had to revert to a
crypto-Aristotelian distinction between “natural” and “violent” motion, as
captured by the normal/revolutionary science contrast.
[52] This
point
50. The question of leadership is especially acute
in any philosophical attempt to revive a prescriptivist approach to science.
One traditional rhetorical source of ethos is kairos, that
is, a pressing occasion that calls for leadership.
But what can be made so pressing that
scientists listen to a philosopher - even if all the philosopher says is that
they should listen to each other? Unfortunately,
the prospect of philosophical legislation continues to carry the old Hobbesian
baggage of a sovereign legislator who not only takes the initiative to propose
laws but also has the will to enforce them.
51. Among noted rhetoricians, for example, I. A.
Richards saw the academic study of rhetoric as a fellow-traveler of logical
positivism, in its ability to identify and correct misunderstandings.
See Richards, The Philosophy of
Rhetoric (Oxford, 1936).
On matters of rhetoric in science, it might seem
appropriate to return to Feyerabend, whose study of Galileo’s rhetoric is the
case in point for the anarchistic epistemology advanced in Against Method.
However, while Feyerabend grants
rhetoric a more prominent place in exemplary episodes of scientific reasoning
than the positivists were inclined to recognize, he nevertheless continues to
portray rhetoric in the same negative light as the positivists saw it.
After all, on Feyerabend’s account,
Galileo used rhetoric to cover up basic gaps in his arguments, which over the
centuries philosophers have supplemented with idealized premises; however, these
gaps did not escape the gaze of Galileo’s Jesuit Inquisitors.
The outrageousness of Feyerabend’s
account pertains to the short and long term of Galileo’s fate.
In the short term, the Inquisitors,
normally the “bad guys” in positivist historiography, are presented as having
offered cogent methodological criticisms of Galileo (much like the positivists
themselves would). Yet, in the long
term, Galileo turns out to have gotten closer to our physics than the
Inquisitors with their methodological niceties.
The Feyerabendian moral, then, is that the positivists mistake rhetoric
for method, but method doesn’t win, either: reality does - and that’s
something that transcends both crafty rhetoric and rigorous method.
If this conclusion seems to mix truth
and long-term survival, it is because Feyerabend shares with Kuhn a certain
unexplained fondness for Darwinian accounts of knowledge growth.
52. Kuhn’s likely source for an Aristotelian
perspective on scientific change was Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the
Modern World (New York, 1925), a popularization of process metaphysics that
enabled Whitehead to portray twentieth-century revolutions in physics as a
neo-Aristotelian revival.
256
informs the necessarily “Orwellian” (Kuhn’s word)
role that he assigns to the rewriting of history, one which erases any trace of
a revolution from science’s institutional memory.
[53] The
political implications of this picture are clear: Scientists govern themselves
adequately under normal circumstances, directed by science’s self-defined ends,
but when a paradigm breaks down under the weight of its own anomalies,
“external,” “non-scientific” intervention is required.
On those occasions, and only
then, larger political considerations play a formative role.
Because Kuhn was convinced that science
flourishes only in its sheltered normal phases, he wanted to dampen any
long-term effects that these considerations might have, which explains his
keenness to prevent scientists who work in the next paradigm from learning about
their traumatic political origins. Contrary
to the drift of much Kuhn commentary, Kuhn does not object to the rational
reconstruction of history - the story of how science should have happened
- that philosophers like Lakatos have promoted.
After all, this is the stuff of which Orwellian history is made.
What is objectionable, however, is for
scientists to be told (as philosophers are wont to do) that such reconstructions
deviate from the actual historical record, as that could inject a measure of
critical self-consciousness that could jeopardize the puzzle-solving process.
Thus, Kuhn would clearly give an
affirmative answer to the provocative question posed by Stephen Brush: Should
the history of science be rated “X” for scientists?
The transitory and suppressible character of the
political in Kuhn’s account has had a decisive impact on the development of the
Sociology of Scientific Knowledge. In
particular, three familiar sociological perspectives simply have no place in
Kuhn’s account of science: (1) the view that science systematically reflects, or
legitimates, specific class interests more generally represented in society,
such that major changes in science are best explained by appealing to larger
societal developments; (2) the view that science lacks any clear integrity as a
social practice, but is rather a loose collection of pre-existing practices that
are held together by a specifically “scientific” way of talking; (3) the view
that science can be exhaustively reduced to a set of variables, drawn from the
larger repertoire of social science, on the basis of which policy for science
can be made as part of comprehensive social policy.
Until very recently and then only tentatively,
these three perspectives have been excluded from the Sociology of Scientific
Knowledge, even as SSK has come to dominate the sociological study of science.
[54] For
example, SSK typically
53. Kuhn, Structure, 167.
54. Three recent textbooks that attempt to
integrate SSK concerns with larger issues of critical science policy, often
within a broader sociological or political economy perspective are: Stephen
Yearbey, Science, Technology, and Social Change (London, 1988); Andrew
Webster, Science, Technology, and Society (London, 1991); John Street,
The Politics of Technology (London, 1992). Note
that all the authors are British and draw their examples from the U.K. and
Europe, which have independent traditions of science criticism, deriving mostly
from Marxism and the Ecology movement. In
all three books, SSK is presented in separate chapters from those devoted to
science criticism and policy, and often the attempt at integration is
perfunctory. For an astute critique of
Yearley, whose own research most clearly straddles the divide, see Govindan
Parayil, “Review of Yearley,” Social Epistemology 6 (1992), 57-64.
257
provides what might be called an “internal sociology” of normal science, in which the SSK practitioner tries to understand the set of practices that constitute what the scientists themselves identify as their lifeworld, a laboratory being the typical site for SSK inquiry. However, SSK practitioners suspend any technical knowledge that they might have of the practices under study. The subversive epistemological consequence, already noted, is that the SSK practitioner often notices things, especially incongruities between word and deed, that escape the practicing scientist’s attention. But the subversion only goes so far, as SSK’s own critical potential is truncated by a symmetrical tendency to suspend any technical knowledge of the social sciences that SSK practitioners might bring to bear to their case. While such methodological asceticism is not without precedent in the sociological literature, it has had the effect of precluding political factors that do not explicitly enter the scientists’ own deliberations
. [55] For example, SSK practitioners employ discourse-analytic techniques to reveal the various voices in a language game played by a community of scientists, but they do not use such techniques to engage in an ideology critique of science that appeals to factors that sustain the game but which transcend the scientists’ control or awareness. This stunted sense of critique has been a constant source of frustration for Marxist and feminist science critics, whose relations with SSK have been chilly, to say the least. [56]
One ready source of friction between SSK
practitioners and these more radical critics of science is the Kuhnian legacy of
treating the study of science as a relatively self-contained project, innocent
of any obvious interest in providing a comprehensive theory of society.
If anything, Kuhn’s tendency to see
science from a distinctly pedagogical angle has caused him and his SSK
followers to stress acculturation at the expense of every other social process.
[57] In
fact, given Kuhn’s efforts at minimizing the presence of disagreement, or
division of any sort, within a paradigm, he runs perilously close to what
sociologist Dennis Wrong would call an “oversocialized” conception of the
scientist. [58]
Telling in
55. One methodological precedent for SSK’s
practice from American sociology is “grounded theory,” as put forward in Barney
Glaser and Anselm Strauss, The Discovery of Grounded Theory: Strategies for
Qualitative Research Practice (Chicago, 1967).
56. Typical in this regard are Stanley
Aronowitz, Science as Power (Minneapolis, 1988) and Sandra Harding,
Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? (Ithaca, 1991).
Kuhn is explicitly charged with
retarding the sociologization of science in Sal Restivo, “The Myth of the
Kuhnian Revolution,” in Sociological Theory, ed. R. Collins (San
Francisco, 1983), 293-305.
57. Although Kuhn’s pedagogical orientation is due primarily to his experience in the Harvard General Education in Science curriculum, as informed through the lectures of Jerome Bruner, he was also influenced by Wittgenstein and Popper, both of whom were trained as secondary school teachers, an aspect of their lives that carried over to their philosophical practice. For a penetrating analysis that should perhaps be read alongside the one I provide below, see W. W. Bartley III, “Theory of Language and Philosophy of Science as Instruments of Educational Reform: Wittgenstein and Popper as Austrian Schoolteachers,” in Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science XIV, ed. R. Cohen and M. Wartofksy (Dordrecht, 1974), 307-337.
58. An oversocialized conception of people sees
individuals entirely in terms of their group characteristics, as in the Kuhnian
tendency to see all scientists who work in a given paradigm as sharing the same
mindset. In effect, this conception
collapses the micro-macro distinction in sociological theory by making it seem
that an entire community can be studied simply by regarding one of its members.
Not surprisingly, oversocializationists
tend to regard acculturation - the acqui-[sition
of membership rights - as the most important social process.
But upon admission to the group,
sociology ends and individual discretion begins - at least, that is the story
that will be told once Kuhn’s ties to Polanyi and the scientific community are
introduced.]
HHC: [bracketed]
displayed on page 259 of original.
258
this regard are the tasks that Kuhn sets for
sociological inquiry in the postscript to Structure.
He concludes the agenda as follows:
What does the group collectively see as its goals; what deviations, individual or collective, will it tolerate; and how does it control the impermissible aberration? A fuller understanding of science will depend on answers to other sorts of questions as well, but there is no area in which work is so badly needed. Scientific knowledge, like language, is intrinsically the common property of a group or else nothing at all. To understand it we shall need to know the special characteristics of the groups that create and use it. [59]
The urgency with which Kuhn recommends the study of science as a unique and autonomous enterprise prompted Feyerabend to wonder whether Kuhn was not implicitly smuggling a prescription under his description: Should Kuhn be taken to mean that science ought to be maintained in its current state? [60] Kuhn responded, Aristotle-like, that by describing the implicit normative structure of science, we would acquire a better sense of how best to govern science. [61] While some have taken Kuhn to have thereby thumbed his nose at the is-ought distinction, I take him to have simply confirmed Feyerabend’s suspicion - that Kuhn wants to understand science in order to determine what it will take to maintain its status quo
. [62]
A key to fathoming the curious role that the
social dimension of science plays in Structure is David Hollinger’s
recent argument that Kuhn managed to “discover” that science flourishes in
self-governing communities just at the time that democratic societies insist on
greater public accountability from scientists. [63] As
in so many other cases, a sense of “community” emerges among disparate
individuals as soon as they face a common foe. [64] To
put the point in boldest relief (probably bolder than Hollinger would permit),
the construction of science as social served much the same role as
earlier constructions of the scientist as individual - only now
reflecting the potentially more widespread societal opposition that scientists
faced. In both cases, the uniqueness of
science is highlighted as demanding special treatment.
Kuhn stands out for having published a
book that left no clear political trace, one that cloaked a desire for science
to be left to the scientists in the guise of an empirically informed theory of
the nature of scientific inquiry. Thus,
Kuhn succeeded where even autonomous science’s most
59. Kuhn, Structure, 209-210.
60. Feyerabend, “Consolations,” 202-203.
61. Kuhn, “Reflections,” 237.
62. For a charitably radical view of Kuhn on this
point, see Jerome Ravetz, “Ideological Commitments in the Philosophy of
Science,” in Munevar, ed., 355-378.
63. David Hollinger, “Free Enterprise and Free
Inquiry: The Emergence of Laissez-Faire Communitarianism in the Ideology of
Science in the United States,” New Literary History 21(1990), 897-919.
64. I portray the so-called Cognitive Revolution in
psychology in the late l950s as another instance of combining to defeat a common
foe (the behaviorists) in Fuller, End of Knowledge, chapter 5.
259
eloquent champion, Michael Polanyi, had failed. Despite the persuasive case he made for the existence of a “scientific community” (a term of his coinage) and the admiring audiences he secured for penetrating the “tacit dimension” of scientific practice, Polanyi typecast himself as upholding the culture of science in the face of barbarous bureaucrats and creeping socialists
. [65] Participation in the quotidian battles that science fought in the public arena did not permit Polanyi the sort of detached “scientific” rhetoric that characterizes most of the writing in Structure, a point in no small measure responsible for the book’s longevity.
Still, it is not hard to see that Kuhn owed more
to Polanyi than the couple of footnotes to Personal Knowledge would
suggest. Consider the following:
If authority alone, and particularly if
non-professional authority, were the arbiter of paradigm debates, the outcome of
those debates might still be revolution, but it would not be scientific
revolution. The very existence of
science depends upon vesting the power to choose between paradigms in the
members of a special kind of community. Just
how special that community must be if science is to survive and grow may be
indicated by the very tenuousness of humanity’s hold on the scientific
enterprise. [66
As Kuhn proceeds to discuss the special character
of the scientific community, it becomes clear that he trades on the Polanyiesque
trope of converting cognitive virtues to moral ones, qualities of understanding
to qualities of trust. Thus, in place of
scientists holding beliefs on the basis of defeasible evidence, Kuhn finds
scientists committed to a vision of reality on the basis of intuitive judgment.
The sort of radical criticism that is
the philosopher’s stock-in-trade appears, in the Kuhn-Polanyi lexicon, as a
failure to respect the difference between one’s own social station and that of
another inquirer. Thus, if Lakatos’s
charge of “mob psychology” offends, it is because it challenges the soundness of
trusting expert judgment during times of disagreement over the relevant
standards of judgment. [67]
Of
course, Polanyi did not believe that all experts deserved to have their
discretion so respected. In particular,
he believed that social scientists
65. See, in particular, Michael Polanyi, “The
Republic of Science: Its Political and Economic Theory,” Minerva 1(1962),
54-73; “The Growth of Science in Society,” Minerva 5 (1967), 533-545.
The work that most influenced Kuhn,
especially in stressing the craft character of science over its argumentative
side, was Polanyi, Personal Knowledge (Chicago, 1957).
66. Kuhn, Structure, 167.
67. A leading SSK practitioner, Harry Collins,
sides with Polanyi over Lakatos, in a way which reveals the conservative
implications that can be drawn from the day-to-day openness of scientific
inquiry: “Even among the experts themselves, who have been trained to many
levels above what can be expected of the public’s understanding, radically
different opinions are to be found… It is dangerously misleading to pretend that
the citizen can judge between the competing views of technical experts when even
the experts cannot agree” (Collins, “Certainty and the Public Understanding of
Science: Science on Television,” Social Studies of Science 17 [1987],
691). Ironically, then, while
sociologists can step into the breach when philosophers cannot decide among
themselves which methodology best explains a certain historical episode of
scientific theory choice, the sociologists’ lack of scientific expertise
prevents them from intervening in contemporary disputes among scientists trying
to resolve their own theory choices! The
underdetermination of theory choice by the evidence thus licenses, for the SSK
practitioner, not the introduction of specifically sociological variables, but
rather the discretionary judgments of the local experts.
260
could not be left to their own devices because of their tendency to extend some philosophical caricature of scientific practice - a “methodology” - to aspects of everyday life where it played no constructive role and, indeed, where it could be quite destructive if used to challenge established scientific judgment. [68
The elitist undercurrent in Polanyi’s account of
science is unmistakable, especially the unflattering analogy he frequently drew
between, on the one hand, medieval self-governing guilds and indentured servants
and, on the other, basic and applied researchers.
(He seemed to think that all social
scientists could be fitted into the latter category.)
However, that undercurrent can also be
channeled into a conception of democracy that has become increasingly prominent
in the twentieth century, namely, pluralism.
Pluralism emerged as an alternative to the pseudo-democracy of
self-styled socialist regimes, whose idea of “equality under the law” was equal
subordination to a central authority. The
pluralist aims to diffuse power from a central authority to voluntary
associations, which, under ideal conditions, are sufficiently divided in their
labors that the members of any such association must rely regularly on the
expertise of the members of other such associations.
[69] Explicit
rules of law play less of a governing role in this system than relations of
trust born of mutual dependency. Pluralists
see themselves as presenting a version of the “open society” suitable to
democracies much larger and more heterogeneous than those modeled on the
Athenian polis. Instead of questioning
authority that strays beyond its bounds, as Popper might
68. During the 1950s and 1960s, Polanyi was not
alone in thinking that the authority of the natural sciences was threatened by
the social sciences. Indeed, Vannevar
Bush wanted the U.S. government to fund a “National Science Foundation” that
specifically excluded the social sciences, not out of a philosophical sense that
the social sciences were “unscientific,” but as a result of private foundations
becoming reluctant to fund natural science research after its involvement in the
atomic bomb project. Moreover, Bush had
to fight off the impression created in the minds of several senators, notably
Harley Kilgore, that the social sciences were needed as watchdogs to ensure that
natural scientists served the public interest. See
Nathan Reingold, Science American Style (New Brunswick, N.J., 1991),
284-333. Aside from the atomic bomb, the
public image of the natural sciences was tarnished by the attempts of leaders of
the scientific community to suppress without testing Immanuel Velikovsky’s
best-selling Worlds in Collision, which challenged the received wisdom of
physics and chemistry by psychoanalyzing the creation myths of several cultures.
When it turned out that some of
Velikovsky’s astronomical predictions were correct, several social scientists
took the opportunity to chastise natural scientists for failing to live up to
their own avowed standards. This episode
simply led Polanyi to retrench his own position about the necessarily inexplicit
character of true scientific expertise. See
Polanyi, “The Growth of Science.”
69. There are a plurality of pluralisms, divided
mainly according to the degree of conflict between the interest groups, or
voluntary associations, in the society. A
good survey is David Held, Models of Democracy(Stanford, 1987), 186-220.
The model emphasized here is relatively
peaceful, drawing on a coordinated division of labor, based on knowledge being
distributed across the members of the society. This
is the sort of polity that SSK seems to countenance.
A genealogy of the position can be
traced from Adi Ophir and Steven Shapin, “The Place of Knowledge: A
Methodological Survey,” Science in Context 4 (1991), 3-21, through Peter
Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality (Garden
City, N.Y., 1967), to Alfred Schutz, [1932] “The Well-Informed Citizen: An Essay
in the Social Distribution of Knowledge,” in Collected Papers (The Hague,
1964), II, 120-134. Schutz, in turn,
wanted to provide a phenomenological basis for Austrian economics as part of the
microfoundations for unifying the social sciences.
The pluralist polity would thus be a
minimal state. See Christopher
Prendergast, “Alfred Schutz and the Austrian School of Economics,” American
Journal of Sociology 92 (1986), 1-26.
261
advise, pluralists advocate tolerating authority
that stays within its bounds. This
is a subtle, but significant, shift in the sense of “openness” required of the
open society in a world of, so to speak, Big Democracy.
In the case of science, it marks a shift
away from criticizing products to understanding practices.
Kuhn participated in educating Americans
to this new sense of “democratic control” of science during Structure’s
fifteen-year incubation period (1947-1962), during much of which he taught in
the General Education in Science curriculum designed by Harvard President James
Bryant Conant, who wrote the foreword to Kuhn’s first book and to whom
Structure is dedicated. [70]
Conant’s vision of post-World War II America was
one in which scientific research would be making greater demands on the public
coffers as the pace of progress quickened. As
the pace picked up, there would be greater disagreement among scientific experts
about the path that science should take. Consequently,
the public (and Conant typically had in mind the typical Harvard-trained
corporate executive or government official) needs to become “expert in judging
experts.” [71]
Here,
in his characteristically no-nonsense manner, is how Conant put the matter:
Whether we like it or not, we are all immersed in
an age in which the products of scientific inquiries confront us at every turn.
We may hate them, shudder at the thought
of them, embrace them when they bring relief from pain or snatch from death a
person whom we love, but the one thing no one can do is banish them.
Therefore every American citizen in the
second half of this century would be well advised to try to understand both
science and the scientists as best he can. [72]
Conant’s key presumption that survives in Kuhn and, as we shall see shortly, in SSK is that the bridge between science and society is best constructed by the public growing more accustomed to science - rather than by scientists growing more accustomed to the public. [73]
Conant’s vision was operationalized by the chemist
Leonard Nash, with
70. Conant describes when he adopted the pluralist
conception of democracy in his autobiography, James Conant, My Several Lives
(New York, 1970), 366. Conant wrote
the foreword to Thomas Kuhn, Copernican Revolution (New York, 1957), in
which he explained Kuhn’s book as an outgrowth of the Harvard General Education
curriculum.
71. James Conant, “Foreword,” in General
Education in Science, ed. I. B. Cohen and F. G. Watson (Cambridge, Mass.,
1952), xiii.
72. James Conant, Science and Common Sense
(New Haven, 1961), 3.
73. I do not mean to deny that Conant was concerned
that scientists be properly “socialized.” However,
he responded by offering courses that exposed scientists to the old liberal arts
culture which dominated the elite colleges prior to World War II.
See Richard Freeland, Academia’s
Golden Age: Universities in Massachusetts, 1945-1970 (Oxford, 1992), 79.
It would be unfair to imply that all of the
outreach work inspired by SSK has tended to reinforce an uncritically positive
image of science. For example, a series
of booklets published by Deakin University Press are designed to enable
Australian citizens to interrogate the role of science and technology in their
lives, often by drawing on the critical questions asked by philosophers and
sociologists of science in their inquiries. Especially
noteworthy is W. Randall Albury, The Politics of Objectivity (Victoria,
1983).
262
whom Kuhn co-taught “Natural Sciences 4,” and to
whom Kuhn dedicated his first book:
The goal of our course [is] the development of a healthy and informed attitude toward, an appreciation and understanding of, science… In discussing the earlier and the more recent activities of science it is carefully pointed out to our students that the urgency of the desire for the solution of a particular scientific problem constitutes no guarantee that it will be or even can be solved…That great strides will be made in science cannot be doubted, but that they will lead immediately to a desired end… can be legitimately questioned. This unbounded optimism can be tempered by the suggestion that unlimited scientific progress in a specified direction cannot be bought or otherwise induced. Favorable conditions for an advance can be created, and the advance may be accelerated; but the advance itself cannot be created. [74]
It should come as no surprise that when Nash goes on to diagnose “two delusions” that cause students to ask of science more than it can reasonably give, he arrives at suspiciously philosophical disorders: “the cult of the fact” and “the cult of the method.” The remedy that Nash proposed as “the case approach” involves presenting students with carefully edited versions of classic experimentalist writings that will enable them at least to follow, and perhaps even to re-enact, the experiment in question. [75] Using a line of argument that Kuhn would later adopt in explaining his Gestalt-based notion of paradigm, Nash defended the suitability of the case approach on the grounds that to understand science is to understand how patterns can be extracted from ambiguous data, a cognitive process that has basically remained unchanged since the rise of experimentation. [76] Thus, Nash had no qualms about selecting experiments only from before the mid-nineteenth century. Indeed, such experiments had the additional advantage that their accompanying texts presupposed relatively little esoteric background knowledge. Even so, the amount of pedagogical guidance involved in this process - “preparation of the materials,” in Nash’s own clinical terms - must have been considerable, as Nash anticipates and meets charges of “spoon-feeding” the students. [77
A comparison of the original texts with Nash’s
“prepared” versions reveals that left on the cutting-room floor was any trace of
the social production of knowledge, especially as expressed in appeals to
disciplinary audiences and other potential readers.
Of course, such excisions become more
difficult to
74. Leonard Nash, “The Use of Historical Cases in
Science Teaching,” in Cohen and Watson, ed., 116-117.
75. Although nowadays an appeal to “cases” in
studying science suggests an approach that draws, at least by analogy, on
ethnographic field work, in fact this is quite different in spirit from the
Harvard approach, which was modeled on effective teaching techniques developed
in the law and business schools, whereby stylized episodes would be presented to
students as the basis for deriving relevant, generalizable principles.
For an illuminating discussion of the
political context from which this practice emerged, see William Buxton and
Stephen Turner, “Edification and Expertise: Sociology as a Profession,” in
Sociology and Its Publics, ed. T. Halliday and M. Janowitz (Chicago, 1992).
I draw some implications for normative
philosophy of science from this lineage in Fuller, End of Knowledge,
chapter 6.
76. Nash, 116; Kuhn, Essential Tension,
293-319.
77. Nash, 115.
263
perform on later scientific writings, in which the “logic” of the text is determined almost entirely by the writing conventions of a given discipline, conventions which themselves cannot be understood without delving into the background interests involved in the formation and maintenance of the discipline’s boundaries
. [78] However, the course that Nash and Kuhn taught was designed to introduce such larger social factors only after the students had grasped the “technical detail” and “tradition of work” that are highlighted in the edited texts. Thus, a strong internal-external history of science distinction is manufactured in the student’s classroom experience, in a way that would not be apparent if the students were simply taught the texts in their original form. As Kuhn might put it, the incommensurability that exists between today’s scientists and students is bridged by having students observe historical cases of science as simulations of how science is performed today.Pivotal in extending the “hands-on” understanding of science officially promoted in Conant’s curriculum has been SSK’s pioneering ethnographic approach to science. Traditionally, the cognitive standpoint informing ethnography has been critical, not of the people under study, but of those who would suppress their voices. Thus, implied by SSK’s critique of rationality is that philosophers of science have routinely misrepresented scientists - indeed, in a way that has contributed to the manic-depressive cycle with which Big Science has been received by the public: impossible expectations followed by disappointment and even betrayal. [79] This is a familiar concern from Conant and Nash, but can the connection between their history-based curriculum and SSK’s ethnographic encounters be made any closer? After all, Kuhn himself has professed hostility to the ethnographic turn in SSK. [80] Yet, once again, the key is Conant himself, who explicitly justified the study of past experimental science as “the equivalent of a magic tour of laboratories” in which visitors would be able to observe the scientists in action, interrupting them with questions about their curious practices. [81]
Of course, the currency in which “public
understanding” is traded has changed over the past three decades, now that we
live in what Guy Debord calls “the society of the spectacle.”
For, what Conant originally proposed as
an impossibly ideal vehicle for the public understanding of science has recently
been advanced by one of SSK’s leading practitioners as an idea whose time has
come. 82 As
in Conant, we find here an interest in getting citizens to appreciate the
“ordinariness” of normal scientific work - and hence not to pin too many hopes
or fears on
78. For a cross-disciplinary treatment of the style
manual as contested terrain, see Charles Bazerman, Shaping Written Knowledge
(Madison, Wisc., 1988).
79. The most comprehensive treatment of this
manic-depressive cycle in the popular psyche is John Burnham, How
Superstition Won and Science Lost: Popularizing Science and Health in the United
States (New Brunswick, N.J., 1987).
80. Horgan, citing Kuhn, 49.
81. Conant, Common Sense, 5.
82. Steven Shapin has recently made this argument
in “A Magician’s Cloak Cast Off for Clarity,” The Times Higher Education
Supplement (London, 14 February 1992), 15.
264
it. Perhaps
even more now than in the 1950s, part of the appeal to ordinariness involves
leaving scientists to do their work just as “you,” the average citizen, would
want others to leave you to do yours:
In democratic societies it is always a sound instinct to trust the people with the truth - even if some work has also to be done to overcome institutionalized idealizations. And in this case the truth is that scientists are neither more nor less than our best current experts in their domains. Their workplaces have got all the clutter of your favorite mechanic’s garage, and he is the man you trust with your car. [83]
The analogy threatens to break down, upon considering that you trust the mechanic not because you see him do things to your car that you yourself would never have dreamed of doing. In fact, that alone might invite suspicion that he is incompetent or overcharging you. Rather, you trust the mechanic because your car runs better after he has worked on it. Unfortunately, the connection between workmanship and outcome is not nearly so close in the case of Big Science, a point repeatedly made by Conant, who, for that reason, stresses the need to identify science with the craft of doing science, which is portrayed as something quite distinct from simply being “well-informed” about the results of science, a state of mind that Conant denigrates as instilling a “merely” critical, outcomes-oriented attitude. [84]
The appeals to hands-on experience and on-site
visits to scientific workplaces are part of what the political scientist Yaron
Ezrahi has called the “visual culture” that characterizes modern liberal
democracies. [85]
According
to Ezrahi, the “seeing is believing” brand of empiricism is perhaps the
Scientific Revolution’s chief continuing legacy to our understanding of
democratic governance. However, the
legacy is an ambiguous one that has not generally encouraged a focused critical
attitude toward the objects seen. Opening
the laboratories to the public certainly gives the impression that the
scientists have nothing to hide. As a
result, that gesture of openness may be just enough to discourage the public
from further probing behind the scenes. Moreover,
in cases where members of the public look closely at a scientist’s work, they
are likely to be struck by the distinctive skills on display, while failing to
wonder about the overall ends that those skills serve.
One might say that the epistemological
fallacy associated with spectator culture - a fallacy that has only become more
trenchant with our ability to see more of the world through the “small screen”
of television - is a version of affirming the consequent: namely, “seeing is
believing” generates the conclusion “out of sight, out of mind.”
In the case of science, then, whatever
escapes the spectators’ visual horizon - the networks of power and channels of
information that exist behind and beyond the lab environs - is simply not
factored into their sense of a proper accounting for science.
[86] Indeed,
given that
83. Shapin, 15.
84. Conant, Common Sense, 315-321.
85. Yaron Ezrahi, The Descent of Icarus
(Cambridge, Mass., 1990).
86. Readers intrigued by the figurative imagination
should consider the following association: Nash, originally trained to prepare
sample chemicals, now moves from materials to media, wherein he prepares case
studies, the pedagogical equivalent of staged events.
265
a larger share of the scientist’s time and energy
is being devoted to “entrepreneurial” activities outside the lab, lab work in
today’s world would seem to be little more than a showcase activity - perhaps,
like so many tribal rituals, done primarily for the benefit of the
spectators. [87]
Conant misjudged the long-term impact of the
General Education curriculum. [88]
True,
it was not adopted by many colleges. However,
in Kuhn’s hands, a failed undergraduate course of study turned out to be
remarkably successful in, so to speak, the area of faculty development.
At least, widespread conversion to the
pedagogical perspective of Natural Sciences 4 would explain why certain tensions
in Conant’s original vision have remained unarticulated by those who come to
their understanding of science through Structure.
These tensions may be summarized in
three sets of questions:
(1) If pure science affects us only through its
applications, then why should General Education curricula focus on the creative
process of pure science, rather than on the real “strategy and tactics” by which
the pure and the applied are networked together?
(Conant reserved the military metaphor for the heuristics scientists
used to channel their creativity. [89])
Why continue focusing on individual
achievement, where an understanding of institution building would seem to be in
order?
(2) If the public understanding of science has
become crucial because of the investments and impacts of Big Science, then why
study historical cases of “Little Science”? If
it is indeed true that “the scientific mind” has not changed over the centuries,
then why not simply conclude that the scientific mind is not the crucial
factor in fathoming the workings of Big Science?
(3) If the value of scientific work can only be
judged by fellow scientists (especially if, as Conant insisted, it was to be
judged of the “man,” not even of the project [90]), then how exactly
is the General Education curriculum supposed to contribute to decision-making
about science in a democracy?
The tensions reflected in these questions
represent the tricky ongoing negotiations between science and power in modern
democracies. [91]
The
philosophical movements that most strongly identified with experimental science
prior to World War I, positivism and pragmatism, grounded science’s superior
epistemic status on its alleged ties to socially beneficial technologies.
I say “alleged” because, while science
did much to explain and to legitimate the great technological advances of the
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, it contributed rela-
87. In this discussion, I make the controversial
assumption that there is a viewpoint from which one could comprehend a
significant part of the whole scientific process, a perspective that is, at
least in principle, open to anyone. Ezrahi,
for one, denies it, as do other postmodernists.
I explicitly defend retaining the idea of a public sphere for governing
science in Fuller, End of Knowledge, chapter 8.
88. Conant, Several Lives, 373.
89. James Conant, On Understanding Science
(New York, 1946), 102ff.
90. Conant, Common Sense, 323.
91. See Proctor, Value-Free Science?, for
the relevant history in Germany and America.
266
tively little to their actual invention. [92] Science becomes instrumental in the construction of “progressive” technologies around the time that it also participates in the construction of war machines. After World War I, most notably in the case of logical positivism, rationalist philosophers start to distance the theoretical trajectory of science from its real or potential applications, which were, in turn, typically presented as deflecting science from its natural trajectory. [93] Yet, this turn comes just as science is increasingly driven by military and industrial concerns, indeed, with major conceptual breakthroughs often arriving as the spinoffs of what would ordinarily be regarded as “applied” research. [94] At the very least, then, Conant needed to ground a strong sense of what was “internal” and “external” to science in order to prevent public exposure of what ethicists call “the problem of dirty hands,” namely, the ambivalence that arises from a practice (in this case, natural science) that unavoidably issues in both good and bad consequences. [95]
Clearly, Conant had his work cut out for himself.
It was a much harder job than, say,
Polanyi had in Britain, where the aesthetic line of “science for its own sake”
still held the keys to the coffers.
In America, funding for pure science ultimately had to be justified in terms of
its long-term public benefits. Yet, if
pure science were forced to compete in the capitalist marketplace, it would
easily lose to industrial based research, which could also use higher salaries
to attract keener intellects. All of
this Conant openly acknowledged. In that
case, what would the public do, once it becomes “expert in judging experts”?
Conant argued that these lay
meta-experts would provide a pool of funds large enough to enable all
professionally approved practitioners in a field to compete among themselves,
according to established rules of scientific evaluation.
[96] This
process, now known as “peer review,” was not much different from what Polanyi
advised, but it served to circumvent the problem of dirty hands.
For even if Conant could not prevent the
prospect of more science producing equal amounts of evil and good, he could help
manufacture an asymmetry in the amount of accountability demanded of research
designated “pure” (relatively low) vis-à-vis that designated “applied”
(relatively high). [97]
Thus,
the ultimate goal of Conant’s General Education curriculum was a lay public
capable of discriminating between instances of these two types of research - a
public conditioned to see the dirt in one set of hands but not in the other.
92. Michael Mulkay, “Knowledge and Utility:
Implications for the Sociology of Knowledge,” Social Studies of Science 9
(1979), 69-74.
93. Of course, irrationalist antiscientific
philosophers continued to see a close connection between theory-driven research
and technological consequences, as physicists were at pains to learn in the
Weimar Republic. See Paul Forman,
“Weimar Culture, Causality, and Quantum Theory: 1918-1927,” in Historical
Studies in the Physical Sciences, ed. R. McCormmach (Philadelphia, 1971).
94. See Big Science, ed. Peter Galison and
Bruce Hevly (Stanford, 1992).
95. For a philosophical discussion of the
issues involved in “dirty hands,” see Bernard Williams, Moral Luck
(Cambridge, Eng., 1981), chapter 4.
96. Conant, Common Sense, 321ff.
97. I mean quite literally that the basic-applied
research distinction originated in accountancy, specifically that used by the
U.S. National Science Foundation. See
Daniel Greenberg, The Politics of Pure Science (New York, 1967), 31-36.
267
If Conant’s writings persuaded U.S. government officials and much of the lay public to support the funding of pure science without requiring too much accountability in return, Kuhn’s Structure occluded the tensions in Conant’s vision for the potentially more critical audience that was brewing within the academy, namely, professional sociologists, who strove throughout most of the century - with decidedly mixed results - to acquire the mantle of science
. [98] By the second term of the Eisenhower administration, sociologists such as C. Wright Mills and Alvin Gouldner had started a backlash, distancing the goals of the social sciences from those of the natural sciences, with the latter being increasingly portrayed as amoral, if not immoral, technologies of control available to the highest bidder, complicitous in what Mills called the emerging “scientific-military-industrial complex.” [99] An assumption that united Mills and Gouldner was that, since the world is causally too complex to afford any unmitigated goods, the only intellectually responsible attitude to the status quo, including science itself, was reasoned skepticism. Here was full recognition of science’s dirty hands.
The distinction that Mills and Gouldner drew
between the natural and social sciences did not aim (as it so often does today)
to replay the cluster of turn-of-the-century Natur-Geisteswissenschaft
debates (generalizing versus particularizing methodologies, matter-based versus
mind-based ontologies). Rather, they
elaborated two types of reasoning that Karl Mannheim had identified at the
outbreak of World War II: a free-standing “functional” rationality that operated
without consideration of the ends it served (natural sciences) and a socially
embedded “substantive” rationality that extended inquiry into the ends that
reason served (social sciences). [100]
Substantive
rationality was no less scientific than its functional counterpart, if by
“scientific” one meant systematic empirical inquiry; but it was more
comprehensively critical, “reflexive” (in Gouldner’s sense), by virtue of
placing the status of the inquirer within the scope of inquiry.
Thus, in addition to wanting to know why
X is the case, the substantively rational scientist would also ask: Who
wants to know? However, Structure
deflected much of sociology’s critical gaze on the natural sciences by showing
(once again, unwittingly) how it, too, could legitimate itself as a “real”
science, and thereby (presumably) no longer be excluded from the ruling power
structure. [101]
An
apt slogan for this turn of events is the subtitle of another movie
98. See Stephen Turner and Jonathan Turner, The
Impossible Science: An Institutional Analysis of American Sociology (Newbury
Park, Calif., 1990).
99. See, especially, C. Wright Mills, The Power
Elite (Oxford, 1956), and Alvin Gouldner, “Anti-Minotaur: The Myth of a
Value-Free Sociology” [1961] in The Relevance of Sociology, ed. Jack
Douglas (New York, 1970).
100. Karl Mannheim, Man and Society in an Age of
Reconstruction (London, 1940).
101. A rather optimistic analysis of Kuhn’s use by
social scientists is given in Peter Weingart, “T.S. Kuhn: Revolutionary or Agent
Provocateur?” in Deutsch, Markovits, and Platt, eds., 265-277.
It is worth noting here that, in his
later writings, Gouldner explicitly distanced “critical intellectuals” from
normal scientists in the Kuhnian mold. See
Gouldner, The Future of Intellectuals and the Rise of the New Class
(London, 1979), 48-49.
268
starring Peter Sellers, the one in which he played
Dr. Strangelove: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb.
Although Kuhn, no less than Polanyi, wanted to
restrict both the interrogation and appropriation of scientific authority, this
concern remains muted in the pages of Structure.
Indeed, social scientists were
attracted to Kuhn’s book precisely because it seemed to provide a blueprint for
how a community of inquirers can constitute themselves as a science,
regardless of their subject matter. The
fact that Structure draws its historical examples almost entirely from
physics and chemistry was conveniently overlooked.
[102] In
short, Kuhn’s interest in generalizing Polanyi’s account of scientific authority
meant that he had to detach that account from the local squabbles in which
Polanyi first developed it. However,
this move, in turn, created a free-floating legitimating narrative - a “myth,”
properly speaking - that could be used by any discipline in need of boosting its
status: quite the opposite of what either Polanyi or Kuhn would have wanted.
The disembedded character of
Structure’s narrative was not lost on fellow historicists Hanson and Toulmin,
both of whom suspected Kuhn of having interdefined his key terms, especially
“paradigm” and “revolution,” to such an extent that there was no way for a
discipline to have a paradigm without a revolution, and vice versa.
[103] The
twin specters of tautology and unfalsifiability that Hanson and Toulmin raised
against Kuhn were, of course, bugaboos to the philosophical mind, but safe
havens for fields in need of legitimation.
Here it is worth recalling an astute account of
the social function of narrative recently suggested by literary critic J. Hillis
Miller. [104] Miller
argues that narratives can sublimate the potentially disruptive character of
social change in two ways. On the one
hand, a narrative can script such change through the re-enactment of a sequence
of events that in the past had enabled others to reach a social status similar
to the one currently desired. The
clearly labeled plot structure of Kuhn’s account of scientific change
contributes to this function well, as it allows others to see that one’s
discipline is behaving as a science would at a certain stage in its development.
On the other hand, a narrative can
effect a subtler social channeling, one that operates as a safety valve for
dissipating subversion. In this case,
the wording of the narrative incorporates, typically by extended metaphor,
elements that threaten the social order which sustains the narrative’s
legitimacy. An evocative expression (not
Miller’s) that captures this function is verbal co-optation.
The desired effect is that the
threatening elements are contained by severing any connection that they might
have to a world outside
102. The restriction of Kuhn’s examples to physics
and chemistry reflects the experimental emphasis that Conant placed in designing
Natural Sciences 4. Most of these
examples are given more extended treatment in Understanding Science,
which was later expanded (with Kuhn’s acknowledged help) in Common Sense.
103. Hanson, “A Note on Kuhn’s Method,” Dialogue
4 (1965), 371-375. Toulmin, Human Understanding, 98-130.
104. J. Hillis Miller, “Narrative,” in Critical
Terms for Literary Study, ed. F. Lentricchia and T. McLaughlin (Chicago,
1990), 66-79.
269
the narrative. In the Kuhnian narrative, with its talk of “crises” issuing in “revolutions,” the political economy of science has been so verbally co-opted that Kuhn’s sociological followers, be they Mertonian or SSK, have been able to cast several models of scientific activity in the discourse of political economy without either making links with the larger political and economic scene that sustains Big Science or even drawing much on the empirical and explanatory resources of political science and economics
. [105]
As evidence for this pseudopolitical economy of
science that has been sustained by Kuhn’s work, I will focus on the simple
locution, “Big Science,” coined by the historian Derek de Solla Price, as that
forms the basis for much of the other work in this vein.
[106] Price
is generally recognized as the founder of “scientometrics,” the discipline that
designs quantitative measures for tracking the growth of knowledge, typically
with an eye to science policy concerns. Although
Price’s original work was independent of Kuhn’s, scientometricians have
subsequently focused on identifying the “life cycle” of scientific specialties,
deriving the stages in this cycle from Kuhnian categories of old paradigm –
anomalies – crisis – revolution - new paradigm.
[107] Notwithstanding
the merit of much of this work, it rests on simplifying assumptions about the
international political economy of science that cannot help but contribute to
the image of science as a self-contained, self-sufficient enterprise.
For example, the major “product” of
science is presumed to be the journal article, whose value is measured in terms
of the other articles that cite it as instrumental in their own production.
What makes today’s science so “big,”
then, is the number of articles produced, and especially the exponential rate at
which they are being produced. Price
justifies his circumscription of scientometrics by appealing to a contrast
between the politically motivated accounting procedures that governments use to
estimate “research and development” expenditures and the policy of “free trade”
and “open markets” demonstrated by the publication practices of scien-
105. Followers of the postmodern scene will
recognize a pronounced Baudrillardian element in the success that social
scientists have had in acquiring legitimacy by means of the Kuhnian narrative.
Once enough research programs have
persuaded enough audiences that they constitute sciences, even if it is
impossible that they could all be right (because a true science has only one
paradigm at any given time), and even if an increasing number of historians
doubt that the Kuhnian narrative is itself right, those new “sciences” have
already acquired lives of their own - hyperrealities - which create similar
expectations in other fields desirous of becoming sciences.
See Jean Baudrillard, Simulations
(New York, 1983).
106. Derek de Solla Price, Big Science, Little
Science… and Beyond [1963] (New York, 1986).
Among those influenced by Price, some
(such as Warren Hagstrom, who credits his knowledge of the history of science to
Kuhn’s tutelage at Berkeley) paint an orderly Mertonian picture whereby
science’s “reward structure” is governed by internally generated status-markers,
such as citation counts. Others, such as
Bruno Latour, revive Conant’s original military metaphor of “strategy and
tactics” to paint a more competitive picture of science.
See Warren Hagstrom, The Scientific
Community (New York, 1965); Bruno Latour, Science in Action
(Cambridge, Mass., 1987).
107. Marc De Mey, The Cognitive Paradigm (Dordrecht,
1982), 111-170, esp. 148-170. One
scientometric indicator of where a field is in the Kuhnian life cycle is
“Price’s Index,” which measures the obsolescence rate of journal articles in
terms of diminishing citation patterns. A
rapid obsolescence rate means a rapidly advancing research front, a paradigm at
top puzzle-solving performance levels.
270
tific journals. [108] Price
seems to be impressed with the fact that out of a myriad of national interests
can emerge a global picture of science that is reducible to fairly simple and
intuitive logistic curves, thereby testifying to the existence of science as a
spontaneously generated and self-sustaining organism.
Price’s thinking here is by no means
idiosyncratic. It would be hard to
overestimate the grip that Kuhn’s Aristotelian picture of science-as-organism
has had on science policy thinking and research over the last thirty years.
As in the philosophy of science, the
idea has likewise served to diminish the normative dimension of the policy-maker
from prescriber to evaluator. The
analogous contrast here is between planner and forecaster.
In the case of scientometrics, it
caters to a “clinical” picture of science policy, whereby the policy-maker
attempts to diagnose and treat an objective condition of a science on the basis
of key symptoms, or “indicators.” The
science in question is taken to have a natural trajectory, which the
policy-maker can then slow or hasten, or, more drastically, divert in some other
direction, perhaps halting progress in the science altogether.
Each more substantial intervention is
seen as incurring a greater risk to the delicate balance of factors needed for
the science to flourish. [109]
It
has become common in Western countries for science policy-makers to see
themselves primarily in the business of adjusting the tempo of scientific
change, and preparing the public for absorbing the intended and unintended
technological consequences of that change. The
burden of planning is taken to lie in reconstructing, not the scientific
enterprise, but the larger society, presumably because a society’s ordinary
institutions are safely manipulable to meet the public interest, whereas the
“natural” ends of science can be easily perverted if forced to serve interests
other than its own. [110]
A case can be made that Structure was used
to legitimate this view of science policy even before it had substantially
transformed more strictly academic con-
108. Derek Price, 137—138.
109. Thus, in concluding about “the future of
science,” Hagstrom says: “The central problem facing society with regard to all
of the professions is the same: how can they be controlled without having their
effectiveness destroyed?” Hagstrom, 294.
An interesting project for the cultural
theory of risk pioneered by Mary Douglas and Aaron Wildavsky would be to examine
which groups would be placed “at risk” by a stronger sense of science planning
than the forecasting approach countenances. My
guess is that at risk are the social scientists, whose legitimacy rests on their
having correctly followed a presumptively universal pattern of scientific
development! For a survey of the social
causes and effects of forecasting over the last thirty years, see Max Dublin,
Futurehype (New York, 1989). Dublin
argues that, contrary to its own hype, forecasting has politically conservative,
not liberating, consequences, because it is based on extrapolating from current
trends. The high degree of likelihood
attached to the future resembling the past artificially raises the level of risk
in potential deviations.
110. Even in West Germany of the 1970s, where
Structure was read largely through the critical Marxism of Habermas, the
call for “state planning” of science amounted to waiting for a paradigm to
“mature” before redirecting (or “finalizing”) research from “basic” to
“applied.” In practice, this policy
touched only the sciences that have reached an advanced stage of puzzle-solving,
whereby the prospect of technological spinoffs from solving additional puzzles
becomes less economical than simply having the scientists address public needs
directly. This is a far cry from the
specters of planned science that set Polanyi on the warpath during the early
years of the Cold War. See
Finalization in Science, ed. Wolf Schaefer (Dordrecht, 1984).
271
ceptions of science.
One of the most influential policy
theorists of the post-World War II period, Don K. Price, discusses Kuhn’s views
in some detail in a 1965 book, the critical acclaim of which soon afterward
propelled Price into the presidency of the American Association for the
Advancement of Science. [111] Reflecting on
his experience as an officer in the Ford Foundation’s program of technical
assistance for developing countries, Price argued that both science and politics
had their own proper ends, and that effective science policy was forged by
keeping communication channels open, while respecting the inherent differences
between these two spheres of activity. Price
appeals to Kuhn in order to draw a connection between scientists’ instinctive
rejection of nonparadigm-based accounting procedures, such as a federal budget,
and their ability to get at the nature of some subject matter.
Defending those instincts, Price
proceeds to argue that if, on the contrary, scientists were driven primarily by
political imperatives, they would be engaging solely in applied research,
leaving more discipline-based pursuits to grow fallow.
[112] Unfortunately,
this argument obscured the delicate fact that modern governments have been just
as eager (if not more so) to support research that scientists deem “pure” as
that which they deem “applied.” In the
name of pure science, they could get high quality information (“intelligence”)
that might someday serve to legitimate otherwise dubious political acts, in
return for the scientists’ assurances that they will not feign competence in
determining the appropriate uses for their work.
Thus, the problem of science’s dirty hands is solved by the principles
of democratic pluralism, as midwived by Thomas Kuhn!
Last Didactic Macrohistory of
Science
A measure of Structure’s unwitting
effectiveness is that no book of its kind has since been written, even though
such books were quite common from the late eighteenth to the mid-twentieth
centuries. The genre I have in mind may
be called didactic macrohistory of science. A
book of this sort purports to draw general lessons from the unfolding of our
collective cognitive development. Even
when the sequence of events displays a stepwise “logic,” the stress is
consistently placed on the need to prepare for a future that will be
significantly different from the present, but which, with some ingenuity, can be
gleaned by studying the past. The
presumption is that “being later” always carries an epistemic advantage.
The argument in these books often
proceeds by arranging historical precedents in a suitably illustrative manner,
and contesting the arrangements that others have made.
Thus, such
historian-philosopher-scientists as Auguste Comte, William Whewell, Ernst Mach,
Charles Sanders Peirce, Pierre Duhem, Emile Meyerson, and Gaston Bachelard would
assess whether a certain scientific practice would generalize across all the
sciences and even into the regimentation of everyday life, they would pass
judgment on the value of such a thing happening, and they would offer advice on
what can be done to
111. Don K. Price, The Scientific Estate
(Cambridge, Mass., 1965), 172-177.
112. Here Price is following the original reasoning
that Vannevar Bush used to establish the National Science Foundation as an
outpost for “pure science.” See Hollinger, 901.
272
encourage the more propitious prospects they have
divined. Often a book of this sort would
be the way by which a philosopher communicated with a wider audience, showing
how, in Hegelian fashion, history dramatizes one’s favorite abstract arguments.
In the first half of this century, the
cases of Russell, Whitehead, and Dewey come readily to mind.
However, unlike Hegel’s dialectic, the life cycle
of a Kuhnian paradigm merely repeats without making progress.
Moreover, not only does Kuhn confine
progress to a given paradigm, he also throws up formidable epistemic barriers to
anyone wishing to peer beyond the current one. The
risks entailed by revolution and the uncertainties of the Planck Effect have
been emphasized here.
Retrospectively, the didactic historian would have to contend with what Lakatos
dubbed “Kuhn Loss,” the phenomenon whereby problem areas deemed important in an
earlier paradigm simply disappear from a later one, only perhaps to reappear
still later on. I do not take issue with
these astute historiographical insights, but rather with Kuhn’s failure to offer
more guidance on what to make of them. In
effect, Kuhn exhibits a marked insensitivity to his own historicity, that
is, the elementary hermeneutical point that his understanding of the past is
predicated on his living when and where he does.
[113] That
Kuhn wrote Structure in the United States in 1962, and not in Germany in
1862 or in France in 1762, does not seem to tell him any more (or less) about
where science might be heading. The
message is the one originally promulgated in the General Education curriculum:
the scientific process remains essentially the same whenever and wherever it
occurs. While Kuhn is hardly the first
historian to overlook his own historicity, the contagiousness of his perspective
has been most remarkable, contributing to the present-day absence of histories
of science comparable in scope to, say, Paul Kennedy’s The Rise and Fall of
the Great Powers - a book I choose deliberately for reasons that will become
clear below.
Historians of science have made a point of
decrying the influence that Structure has had on how non-historians think
of their field. [114]
Nevertheless,
two styles of doing the history of science are traceable to Kuhn’s work.
Both derive from his experience in the
Conant curriculum. One style
harkens back to Kuhn’s fledgling efforts at Natural Sciences 4.
It takes off from Kuhn’s own
oft-repeated story of how, given his own recent physics training, he originally
found the texts he had to teach by Aristotle and even Newton unintelligible.
[115] This
characterizes the “relativistic” style that SSK picked up, which conceptualizes
the past as a foreign country separated by time as if by space, requiring
acculturation into native customs quite unlike our own.
But once Kuhn became a proficient
instructor, the second, more Piagetian style predominated, which focused the
student’s attention only on salient aspects of scientific episodes that were
neces-
113. Here I must take exception with the excess
hermeneutical insight that Richard Bernstein ascribes to Kuhn.
See Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and
Relativism (Philadelphia, 1983), esp. 20-34.
114. See, especially, Reingold, 389-409.
115. See, for example, Kuhn, Essential Tension,
xi-xiii.
273
sary for recognizing and resolving some paradigmatic tension. [116] Here we find the Orwellian historical perspective that enabled the students in Kuhn’s course to acquire the kind of “understanding” of science that Conant sought. Although few professional historians have adopted this style, it is well represented by philosophers and psychologists who profess a “cognitivist” approach to the history of science. [117] Both of these styles strike most workaday historians as betraying undue philosophical influence: extreme relativism on the one hand, and extreme universalism on the other. However, the one philosophical influence that is missing is the one that continues to inform didactic macrohistories of politics, such as Kennedy’s. It is a perspective that confers epistemic privilege on “being later” without presuming that what one now sees is better than before. Such a perspective involves neither obscurantism nor Whiggism - to invoke the swear words that historians are prone to use for the Kuhn-generated extremes. Rather, it prods the audience to convert a usable past into a viable future. [118]
In hindsight, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions unwittingly achieved for its audiences much of what Daniel
Bell’s The End of Ideology tried but failed to do for his, namely, to
alleviate the anxieties of alienated academics and defensive policy-makers by
teaching them that they could all profit from solving their own paradigmatic
puzzles. But I have also argued that
Kuhn’s lesson has exacted its own substantial Kuhn’s Loss, as the triumph of his
paradigm of scientific change has marginalized the forums for a radically
critical rationalism, one that questions the ends of science as well as the
means. However, if the reception of
Kuhn’s book were just another case of Hegel’s Cunning of Reason passing through
the world, it would not merit this essay’s subtitle, “a parable for postmodern
times.” At the start, I commented on
Kuhn’s peculiar reaction to his success. Equally,
there is Kuhn’s audience’s peculiar reaction to Structure.
A common thread that runs through
the formal and informal comments that people make about the book is that it is
quite thin in their own field of expertise,
116. Kuhn picked up his Piaget from Jerome Bruner,
lecturing at the Harvard School of Education. The
link that Kuhn implicitly draws between a Piagetian child advancing to the next
stage of cognitive development and a student reenacting a gestalt switch from
the history of science comes out most clearly in Kuhn, “A Function for Thought
Experiments,” in Essential Tension, 240-265.
117. Like Kuhn himself, only twenty years later,
Marc De Mey gained a grounding in cognitive psychology while attending Jerome
Bruner’s lectures at Harvard. De Mey’s
The Cognitive Paradigm is the most comprehensive attempt at a
“cognitivist” understanding of science that is in Kuhn’s spirit.
The best single historical monograph in
this vein is Howard Margolis, Patterns, Thinking, and Cognition (Chicago,
1987). Today, “cognitive history of
science” covers a wide variety of approaches, most of which are rather un-Kuhnian
in that they draw more on artificial intelligence than on developmental
psychology. A good sense of the range is
provided in Cognitive Models of Science, ed. Ronald Giere (Minneapolis,
1992).
118. The only didactic macrohistory of science of
recent vintage to have garnered some attention is Philip Mirowski, More Heat
than Light (Cambridge, Eng., 1989). This
excellent work (which deserves to become a historiographical paradigm) not only
shows the steady decline of neoclassical economic theory as it develops a
metaphor drawn from defunct physics, but it also points the way toward
redeploying resources from the institutionalist tradition to constitute a new
social theory of economic value.
274
but truly enlightening in some other field, one in
which they have had an interest for a long time, but could not locate a suitable
point of scholarly intersection. We
might say, then, roughly speaking, that Structure has a philosopher’s
sense of sociology, a historian’s sense of philosophy, and a sociologist’s sense
of history. A text with these
characteristics is assured a good reception just as long as the practitioners of
the different disciplines continue talking only to their own colleagues and not
to those of the field which Kuhn supposedly represents so well for them.
At that point, the day when (if!)
inquiry despecializes, the attraction of Kuhn will fade.
Moreover, precisely because Structure
is not a perfect text, and does not cloak its imperfections in
jargon, it invites further participation by the reader to correct its flaws and
complete its argument. This perhaps
explains why everyone finds it important to position themselves in terms of Kuhn
without feeling compelled to follow in his footsteps.
Virginia Polytechnic University
275