The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
April 2003
Wendy Faulkner
Conceptualizing
Knowledge Used in Innovation:
A Second Look at
the Science-Technology Distinction and Industrial Innovation
Science, Technology, & Human Values
Volume 19, Issue 4
Autumn 1994, 425-458.
Index
The Science-Technology Distinction
The Early Debate: Blurring the Boundaries
Historical Studies of Technological Knowledge
The Distinctiveness of Technological Knowledge
Knowledge Used in Industrial Innovation
Knowledge from Internal and External Sources: The Evidence
Why Companies Use Internal and External Sources of Knowledge
Categorizations of Knowledge Used in Innovation
Broad Distinctions in the Character of Knowledge Used in Innovation
Detailed Categories of Knowledge Used in Innovation
Some Comments on the Composite Typology
This article reviews empirical and conceptual material
from two distinct research traditions: on the science-technology relation and
on industrial innovation. It aims both
to shed new light on an old debate - the distinction between scientific and
technological knowledge - and to refine our conceptualizations of the knowledge
used by companies in the course of research and development leading to
innovation. On the basis of three
empirical studies, a composite categorization of different types of knowledge
used in innovation is proposed, as part of a broader framework encompassing two
further taxonomic dimensions. It is
hoped that this typology and framework might provide useful research tools in
furthering our understanding of the knowledge transfers and transformations
that occur in the course of innovation. It could also prove useful for organizations
and groups facing difficult strategic choices about technology.
This article joins other recent attempts to
conceptualize technological knowledge and expertise [1] used in the
course of research and development (R&D) [2] and design activities leading
to innovation. It draws together conceptual
and empirical threads from two distinct research traditions in science and
technology studies: on the science-technology distinction and on industrial
innovation. My primary objective is to
propose a composite categorization of different types of knowledge used
in innovation, which, it is hoped, will prove useful as a research tool. As a secondary aim, I also consider
AUTHOR’S NOTE: An earlier version of this article was presented and
discussed at the University of Edinburgh Programme on Information and
Communication Technologies (PICT) workshop “Exploring Expertise” held in
November 1992, and I am grateful to colleagues who provided feedback on that
occasion. I would also like to thank
David Edge, Keith Pavitt, Jacqueline Senker, and Andrew Webster for their time
and effort in reading and commenting on earlier drafts of the article.
425
whether we can distinguish between scientific and technological types
of knowledge, and to what extent each is used in the course of industrial
innovation.
The term knowledge is used here in its broadest
sense, to encompass what we call knowledge, expertise, skills, and information.
Of course, the processes by which
scientific and technological knowledge is created and deemed legitimate are
very political in nature - witness the institutional authority associated with
medical knowledge, for example. My main
concern in this article is more narrowly focused, on the cognitive or
epistemological features of the knowledge used in innovation. These features are never simply “internal,”
however. They are intimately related to
questions of who possesses particular knowledge and how easy it is for
particular groups to access and make use of this knowledge. Indeed, my hope is that a more sophisticated
characterization of technical knowledge - one that identifies specific and
substantive differences of type - will further our understanding of what
happens to knowledge as it moves between, and is developed by, different groups
in the course of innovation.
My interest in this project arose out of a particular
concern with the flows of knowledge between public sector research (PSR)
organizations and industry, which was the subject of a recent study I conducted
with Jacqueline Senker and Lea Velho. [3] This study
sought to identify the particular types of knowledge obtained from academic and
government laboratories by firms in three different technological fields, in
order to understand variations in the extent and nature of industry-PSR
research linkage in different fields. The
findings of this study are reported fully elsewhere (Senker and Faulkner 1992;
Faulkner, Senker, and Velho 1974). However, I present some of our findings here,
together with some findings from a similar study by Gibbons and Johnston
(1974), to examine the range of knowledge types used in the course of
innovation, and to illustrate the general applicability of a research approach
that utilizes detailed categorizations of knowledge.
The first section of the article reviews literature on
the science-technology relation, including work in the history of technology
that highlights a number of important cognitive and epistemological features of
technological knowledge. The second
section reviews literature on knowledge used in industrial innovation, focusing
on the contribution of internal and external sources of knowledge used in
innovation, and on broad differences in the types of knowledge obtained. The following section compares various
attempts to categorize technological knowledge and proposes a composite
typology of knowledge types. Possible
research and policy uses of this typology are outlined in the conclusions.
426
The
Science-Technology Distinction
The science-technology relation was the subject of
recurring debate in the field of science studies, more or less from its
inception until the early 1980s. During
the 1970s interest in the science-technology relation was largely superceded by
a concern with technology per se, in particular, a concern to
characterize more adequately the nature of technological knowledge
(Staudenmaier 1985). Ironically,
whereas the early literature tended to stress the increasing proximity and
overlap of science and technology, the latter work has tended to highlight the
distinctiveness of technology.
The Early Debate:
Blurring the Boundaries
The early literature challenged the prevalent linear
model of the science-technology relation. Within this model, science is the “springhead”
of innovation, as if scientific discovery necessarily implies technological
invention, whereas technology involved the rather humdrum, responsive activity
of applying science (see Barnes and Edge 1982 for a review). Critics of this model pointed to the numerous
occasions - not least, the advent of the steam engine - when technology “led”
science (e.g., Layton 1988). Even where
the reverse appeared to hold, detailed case studies revealed that the linearity
was illusory. For instance, although the
scientific quantum theory of semiconduction was a necessary precondition for
the invention of the transistor, the theory itself did not suggest the
technology: rather, the transistor arose primarily out of the development of
rectifier technology within the fields of radar and radio (Gibbons and Johnson
1982). The linear model was thus shown
to be fundamentally flawed in its perception of both science and technology.
The alternative, “two stream” model, championed by
Derek de Solla Price, accords better with the historical evidence. On the basis of extensive citation analysis of
science and technology publications, de Solla Price (1965) concluded
that science tends to build on old science and technology on old technology,
but there is a weak and reciprocal interaction between the two. He argued that maximum interaction occurs
during the period of training when budding scientists and technologists read
the archival literature of their respective endeavors, “packed down” in
textbooks. Accordingly, the education
cycle accounts for a time lag (of approximately ten years) in the
translation of new science into new technology, and vice versa (de Solla Price 1965).
Later, de Solla Price revised his views somewhat. He argued that “basic and applied research are
linked inseparably to technology by the crafts and
427
techniques of the experimentalist and inventor,” and proposed the term instrumentalities
“to carry a general connotation of a laboratory method for doing something
to nature or to the data in hand” (de Solla Price 1984). A pertinent example is Rosalind Franklin’s ability
to make good X-ray diffraction pictures from very small samples of poorly
crystallizable material: without this instrumentality, Watson and Crick would
not have been able to “see” the double helix. De Solla Price cited numerous instances when
the advent of such instrumentalities has simultaneously opened up major new opportunities
for scientific investigation and technological innovation. [4] At such times at least, he conceded, any time
lag in the interaction between science and technology may be very short indeed.
More recent bibliometric analyses reveal just how
short the time lag can be. In some
technological fields (for example, biotechnology) the citation behavior of
patent applicants (and examiners), in terms of the frequency of references to
basic research publications and the time distribution of these citations, is
very similar to that of researchers in neighboring scientific fields
(Carpenter, Cooper, and Narin 1980; Carpenter, Narmn, and Woolfe 1981; Narin
and Noma 1985). Thus some technologies
are strongly science related. Far from
relying on archival literature, technologists keep up with the “research front”
literature in science. [5] In a study of
solid-state technology publications between 1955 and 1975, Marvin Lieberman
found that the frequency and age of scientific citations followed a pattern of
“overlapping waves” that, he concluded, were associated with “the continual
birth of new science-related technologies within the solid state field”
(Lieberman 1978).
Although this pattern explains the generally high
level of coupling between science and technology evident in many advanced
fields, it also suggests that such coupling is greatest during the early stages
of development of a technological field. This theme is evident in economic theories of
technological development, even though these theories do not explicitly model
the science-technology relation (Dosi 1982; Granberg and Stankiewicz 1978). Empirical evidence that industrial innovation
and growth tend to be “knowledge-led” during the early development of an
industry is provided by Vivien Walsh’s (1984) detailed examination of time
trends in scientific publication, patenting, and output in the chemical
industry.
The emergence of the research-based chemical and
electronics industries (Freeman 1982, chaps. 1-3), and of the more
science-related technologies identified above, indicates that science and
technology have become increasingly intimate endeavors during this century. This trend has its historical roots in the
establishment of R&D laboratories in industry and of specialist science and
engineering departments in universities. Ironically, these developments involved an
institutional separation of science and technology. Hendrick
428
Bode (1965) argued that science was able to overlap with, and
contribute to, technology in the areas of theory, experimental technique, and
specialized knowledge precisely because it had earlier achieved its own
momentum. At a cognitive level, the
institutional changes signaled “a more profound and subtle sort of science...
It meant that by digging deeply enough we could expect to turn up new phenomena
and new relationships not readily predictable from ordinary experience” (Bode 1965,
pt. 2). So, modern scientific
inquiry demands not only lengthy training in the relevant specialisms but also
the use of sophisticated equipment and instrumentation (Bud and Cozzens 1992).
Taken together, the case studies and bibliometric
evidence lead to two conclusions about the science-technology relation. First, it is a strongly interactive
relationship between two semiautonomous activities, with instrumentalities as
an important area of overlap. Second,
science and technology are now particularly intimate activities, at least in
some new fields and at times of major change. This latter conclusion obliges us to accept a
blurring of the boundaries between science and technology as these terms are
conventionally understood. Otto Mayr
sums up the issue:
[although] a practically usable criterion for making sharp and neat
distinctions between science and technology simply does not exist... the two
words “science” and “technology” are useful precisely because they serve as
vague umbrella terms that roughly and impressionistically suggest areas of
meaning without precisely defining their limits. (Mayr 1982, 159)
We are left, it seems, with only nuances of
meaning to distinguish science and technology. Indeed, for some, these boundaries are all but
obliterated - witness Bruno Latour’s use of the term technoscience (Latour
1987). It seems pertinent, therefore, to
review what others have to say about what makes technological knowledge
distinct.
Historical Studies
of Technological Knowledge
The demise of the science-technology debate coincided
with the shift of attention within the field of science studies toward the
subject of technology. “Revisionism” in
the understanding of the science-technology distinction has come from scholars
of technology, in particular, historians of technology. They have provided a strong empirical basis
for the critique of the linear model, and much evidence about the
nineteenth-century changes through which technology is held to have become more
closely science related.
Edwin Layton’s (1974) article “Technology as
Knowledge” effectively launched a project to elucidate the nature of
technological knowledge. This
429
project has focused largely on the emergence of engineering as a
distinct academic discipline (e.g., Layton 1976; Channell 1982; Constant
1984a), and we should be careful not to conflate engineering and technology. Walter Vincenti (1991, 6) argues that, whereas
technology properly includes draftspeople, shopfloor workers, and so on,
engineers have a special relationship to technology. In line with the commonly accepted definitions
of engineering, he identifies engineers as those who organize, design,
construct, and operate artifacts that transform the physical world to meet a
recognized need.
Studies of engineering have examined various aspects
of the development of engineering curricula in universities, including the
adoption of scientific methods and principles, and the balance of theoretical
and practical training in different countries. David Channell (1982) concluded that
“engineering science” occupies an intermediate position between “pure”
engineering and science, by translating knowledge and techniques from
one to the other. He thus rejects the
assumption (made, for example, by Musson and Robinson 1969) that engineering
simply “lifted” the scientific methodology. Layton (1976) and Channell (1982) both
stressed that the closer organization and interplay of science and engineering
were ideological as well as practical expedients; engineers were keen also to
acquire some of the image and status that nineteenth-century science enjoyed. Indeed, in a pertinent but rather facetious
critique of Layton’s and Channell’s work, Fores (1988) argued that the transformation
associated with the emergence of modern engineering has been grossly
overstated, precisely because of the “totemic” qualities of the label
“science.” [6]
Layton’s project has been considerably furthered by
the engineer-turned-historian Walter Vincenti. In What Engineers Know and How They Know
It, Vincenti starts from the now traditional view within the history of
technology that engineering is not a derivative of science but an autonomous
body of knowledge that interacts with it (Vincenti 1991, 1). He seeks to develop an epistemology of
engineering based on a series of detailed empirical studies of the growth and
maturation of aeronautical engineering between 1900 and 1950. At the beginning of this period, aircraft
design was largely “cut and try”; by the end, there existed a substantial body
of underpinning theory, experimental techniques, and data. As a result of these developments, Vincenti
argues, the level of uncertainty surrounding design declined dramatically
because “acts of [communicable] skill” increasingly reduced reliance on “acts
of insight,” and aeronautical engineering is now a more or less systematic and
cumulative body of knowledge (Vincenti, 1991, 168).
A number of important conclusions emerge from
Vincenti’s work. First, an extended learning
process is often necessary if the requirements of the
430
user are to be understood and integrated into design specifications. For example, it took twenty-five years of
close interaction between engineers and pilots before flying quality
specifications could be drawn up. The
“hands-on” experience of pilots had to be translated into codified design
parameters. Second, much of the
practical experience and knowledge required was local and tacit in
character: shopfloor experience with different flush riveting techniques, for
example, could not be easily codified or communicated between firms. Third, the generation of data was vital
to improved analytical capability and this required the emergence of vicarious
testing techniques to reduce reliance on the always costly and sometimes
disastrous field trials. A key
aeronautical example here is the use of wind tunnels for simulation tests. Fourth, certain theoretical tools and
ways of thinking (for example, experimental parametric variation) were crucial
to this development.
The Distinctiveness
of Technological Knowledge
Historical work on engineering has highlighted rather
than blurred the distinctions between science and technology. This cannot be entirely due to historians
having a retrospective orientation, because scholars of modern technology reach
similar conclusions (e.g., Sørenson and Levold 1992). Drawing on both the historical and
contemporary literatures, we can point to three closely related areas in which
technology is distinguished from science: (1) in its purpose or orientation,
(2) in its sociotechnical organization, and (3) in its cognitive and
epistemological features.
With respect to orientation, there are familiar
nuances of difference: technology is about controlling nature through
the production of artifacts, and science is about understanding nature
through the production of knowledge. Mayr
(1982, 159) argued that, although this distinction does indeed separate science
and technology, “it is valid only on the level of semantics. If we analyze actual historical events, we
find that the motives behind actions are usually mixed and complex.” Vincenti nevertheless privileged the distinction:
“However phrased, the essential difference is one between intellectual
understanding and practical utility” (Vincenti 1991, 254). In a similar vein, Layton (1988) described
engineering, medicine, and agriculture as “technological sciences” because they
involve the “science of the artificial” in contrast to the “basic sciences” of
the natural.
The practical-artifactual orientation of technology
has important consequences for its organization, both as a body of knowledge
and as a social activity. With respect
to the latter, Edward Constant (1984b) and others have stressed the hierarchical
features of the development of complex technologi
431
cal systems. Once a project
specification has been drawn up and an overall concept design selected, the
task of detailed design is “decomposed” according to major components of the
system, specific problems and subproblems, and specialist disciplines. The technological project is thus highly
structured, but in a way that allows maximum interaction and coordination
between specific groups. Development of
the design is coordinated and iterative, and the end product succeeds in integrating
all of the necessary knowledge.
Scholars of modern technology, working in a
constructivist framework, also stress the socioinstitutional complexity of
technology, but they argue that this extends far beyond the laboratory or
individual company. The recent article
of Sørensen and Levold (1992, 19) is particularly helpful here. They synthesize John Law’s concept of
heterogeneous technology with Constant’s hierarchy, arguing that the
heterogeneity of technology is evident both in the terrain of the
technoscientific - that is, the decomposition into problems requiring expertise
from various groups - and in the sociotechnical - that is, “how they [problems]
are analyzed and integrated” (Sørensen and Levold 1992, 19). Sørensen and Levold conclude that technology
is far more complicated than science on both counts; “technology is usually
surrounded by a larger number of powerful political and economic and political
actors than is science... [thus]... science involves less of the social, and
the social terrain on which scientists manoeuvre is much simpler than that of
engineers” (Sørensen and Levold 1992, 16). [7]
Science can be distinguished from engineering in terms
of five distinct cognitive and epistemological features. First, because of its practical-artifactual
orientation, the central activity in technology is design. In practice, design only sometimes demands
the generation of new knowledge. Although
design always enters into R&D, much of it is quite distinct from R&D
both institutionally and cognitively (Walsh et al. 1992). According to Sørensen and Levold:
Technology... is far more than what can reasonably be subsumed under
the concept of engineering science. Development
of technology still involves activities better described by the metaphor of art
than of science. Practical intuition and
a developed “engineering gaze” are frequently more important than calculation
and analysis. (1992, 19-22).
A second and related distinction is Sørensen and
Levold’s point that problem solving in technology is a more heterogeneous activity
than it is in science. [8] Most
science is also more homogeneous than technology in terms of disciplinarity,
expertise, and social groupings, with the result that knowledge claims in
science are generally far less heterogeneous than are innovations in
technology.
432
A third distinction, which has been widely recognized
since Polyani’s (1966) book on the subject, is the vital importance of local
and tacit knowledge in technological innovation (Senker 1993; Winter 1987). This is demonstrated, for example, in
Vincenti’s (1991, chap. 5) study of flush riveting. James Fleck (1988) showed that the development
of complex information technology (IT) systems demands extensive knowledge of
the contingencies operating in user organizations. The picture that emerges is in stark contrast
to the presumed universality of scientific knowledge. Of course, the work of Harry Collins (1974)
shows that tacit knowledge is also important in scientific experiments. Sørensen and Levold argue, nevertheless, that
its significance is far greater in technology because replication of reported
experiments is not widespread in practice, [9] and because failure to replicate in science merely
raises questions about a knowledge claim, whereas failure of an artifact can
have disastrous social and economic consequences.
The final two areas of distinction are more
problematic. They are the role of theory
and the character of methodology in technology. Another of the nuances of meaning commonly
attached to science and technology is that the former is more theory based and
the latter more empirical. As the debate
between Fores and Layton and Channell indicates, this assumption is highly
contestable. In any case, it would be
wrong to assume that all theory is necessarily scientific. Vincenti argues that the theoretical tools in
engineering lie on a science-engineering spectrum. At the “essentially scientific” end are the
purely mathematical tools, followed by mathematically structured theoretical
knowledge about the physical world. Such
theories generally originate in science and attract scientific interest for
their explanatory powers. However, they
generally need to be reformulated or “recast” in order to make them applicable
to technological problems. The
“essentially engineering” end includes theory “based on scientific principles
but motivated by and limited to a technologically important class of phenomena
or even a specific device” (Vincenti 1991, 214). Interest in such theory depends entirely on
the utility of the artifact to which it relates. At the far end of the spectrum, Vincenti
identifies phenomenological theory, based primarily on ad hoc
assumptions (presumably derived from trial and error practice) and only
marginally on scientific principles. The
explanatory power of such theory is limited, although its practical utility is
high.
In the area of methodology, most scholars see little
to distinguish science and technology. Sørensen
and Levold (1992), for example, noted that there is much methodological variety
within both science and technology. Constant nonetheless argues that modern
technology may be distinguished from both craft technology and science by the
application of a methodology based on “bold total-system conjecture and
rigourous testing to large-scale, complex,
433
multi-level systems” (Constant 1984a). Vincenti similarly identifies what he calls
“characteristically engineering methodology” suggestive of something akin to
scientific methodology (1991, chap. 5). He cites the use of experimental
parametric variation and scale models to test aircraft propellers - activities
that took place independently of physical theory and that provided vital data
for design and analysis where no useful theory existed to predict performance. [10] Like Channell (1988), Vincenti (1991, 168)
concluded that although elements of engineering methodology appear scientific,
engineering methodology as a whole did not emerge within science.
We should remember that there are important respects
in which science and technology are still generally held to be similar. Both conform to the same natural “laws.” Both are cumulative and diffuse largely
through the same mechanisms: education, publications, and informal communication.
And both are organized around
professional communities with marked disciplinary autonomy. Nonetheless, the studies cited here point to
some quite significant distinctions between these two activities and associated
bodies of knowledge - distinctions that hinge on the practical and artifactual
orientation of technology, and include a number of socioinstitutional and
epistemological differences that flow from this orientation. I would argue that this work does indeed
oblige us to rethink earlier conclusions about the apparently vanishing
boundaries between science and technology. Further support for this position comes from
scholarship on knowledge used in industrial innovation, to which we now turn.
Knowledge Used in Industrial Innovation
Our concern here is with knowledge actually used in
the process of innovation. To the extent
that innovation relates to artifacts and not understanding per se, it is
decidedly technological. However, I am
not assuming that the knowledge used in innovation is exclusively
technological, hence the formulation adopted here. Indeed, it is clear that scientific knowledge
also contributes to innovation. This
section summarizes literature that seeks to calibrate and explain the relative
contribution of internal and external sources to the knowledge used in
innovation. The studies reported here
are based on quite different research questions and methodologies from those
described above. They are contemporary
rather than historical studies, with a specific focus on the innovating firm
rather than on science or technology more broadly. In spite of this, both literatures point to
similar conclusions about the types of knowledge used in innovation.
434
Knowledge from
Internal and External Sources: The Evidence
The early concern in science studies with the
science-technology relation was paralleled in the new field of science policy
by a concern to assess the contribution of public “science” to technological
innovation. This concern underpinned the
celebrated but now widely discredited retrospective studies such as TRACES
(Illinois Institute of Technology Research Institute 1968; Batelle Columbus
Laboratory 1973) and Project Hindsight (Sherwin and Isenson 1967). [12] It also informed many of the early innovation
studies of the 1970s. In contrast to the
retrospective studies, this research focused on the knowledge actually used in
the course of innovation, rather than knowledge that in some abstract and convoluted
way might have contributed to it. The
innovation studies sought to identify the main institutional source of the
original idea for the innovation under investigation and of the major technical
inputs to subsequent problem solving (see Rothwell 1977 for a review).
Averaging across industries, there is remarkable
convergence in the results of these studies. Around two-thirds of the knowledge used by
companies in the course of innovation derives from their own in-house R&D
effort and expertise; the remaining third comes from external sources. The largest single external source of
scientific and technological contributions to innovation is other industrial
companies, especially users or suppliers but also competitors. The contribution of academic and government
laboratories varies across sectors from 5 percent to 20 percent (Rothwell
1977).
The early innovation studies revealed that the
translation of new knowledge into new artifacts is an extremely complex
process; that the relationship between academic and industrial research is
neither obvious nor direct; and that innovation demands knowledge from a range
of internal and external sources. Most
significantly, success in industrial innovation rests on the effective
organizational “coupling” of technical and market opportunities and
intelligence (Rothwell et al. 1974; Freeman 1982, chap. 5). Thus management capability is required in a
range of areas, not simply in research. The
challenge posed by innovation now tends to be seen more as one of organization
than of intellect, and this has become the central preoccupation of the
innovation literature. Perhaps as a
result, there has been little concern to examine further the cognitive features
of industrial innovation.
An important exception was the study by Gibbons and
Johnston (1974) of thirty award-winning innovations. It sought to assess the particular contribution
of “public science” to innovation by asking industrial R&D staff to
identify all of the scientific and technological “information” used by them in
435
Table 1. Content of Scientific and Technological Input
(STI)
to Innovation by Source
|
|
|
Source |
|
Content of Knowledge |
Info Units |
Internal |
Other Companies a |
PSR b ** |
Theories, laws, and general principles |
8% (69) |
52% (36) |
16% (11) |
32% (22) |
Properties of materials, and components |
32% (270) |
74% (200) |
16% (42) |
10% (28) |
Design-based information, Operating principles |
24% (205) |
81% (165) |
15% (30) |
5% (10) |
Test procedures and techniques |
10% (78) |
80% (62) |
12% (9) |
9% (7) |
Knowledge of knowledge |
26% (217) |
57% (124) |
30% (66) |
12% (27) |
Total |
100% (839) |
70% (587) |
19% (158) |
12% (94) |
Source: Gibbons and
Johnson 1974.
a. “Other companies” includes here
the trade and technical literature, plus contacts with organizations such as
British Standards and Research Associations.
b. PSR = public sector research,
which is described by Gibbons and Johnston as or “public science” and defined
as scientific journals, books, and so on, as well as personal contacts in
government and academic laboratories.
* percentage of information units;
numbers in parentheses.
** PSR is referred to as “public
science” by Gibbons and Johnston, and defined as Public Sector Research.
the course of new product development. This yielded 887 units of information that
were then analyzed in terms of the content of the information, the sources from
which that information was obtained, and its impact on problem-solving activity.
Table 1 summarizes their data on the
content of information obtained from different sources. [13]
The results in Table 1 can be compared with those in
Table 2, which analyze the “impact” of knowledge from different sources on
different areas of companies’ innovative activities, grouped under six broad
headings. [14] These data
were generated in our recent study based on 44 interviews with R&D staff in
23 firms, covering three fields of technology. This study investigated the knowledge flows or
scientific and technological inputs (STI) associated with industry-PSR linkage
activity. Following a similar approach
to that of Gibbons and Johnston, it examined the type, source, and impact of
436
Table 2. Impact of Scientific and Technological Input
(STI) on Innovative Activities
Activity |
|
Source |
|
|
|
Internal |
Other Companies |
PSR a |
NR b |
Future innovations |
57% (52.0) |
33% (30.0) |
10% (9.0) |
(5) |
Search activity |
|
|
|
|
Scouting for new applications |
45% (13.5) |
27% (8.0) |
28% (8.5) |
(2) |
Scanning research frontier |
30% (8.5) |
18% (5.0) |
52% (14.5) |
(4) |
Subtotal |
37% (22.0) |
22% (13.0) |
40% (23.0) |
(6) |
Ongoing R&DC |
|
|
|
|
Underpinning knowledge |
40% (12.5) |
2% (0.5) |
58% (18.0) |
(1) |
Routine problem solving |
88% (28.0) |
9% (3.0) |
3% (1.0) |
(0) |
Subtotal |
65% (40.5) |
6% (3.5) |
30% (19.0) |
(1) |
Instrumentalities |
|
|
|
|
Research equipment |
18% (5.5) |
52% (15.5) |
30% (9.0) |
(2) |
R&DC procedures |
47% (14.5) |
24% (7.5) |
29% (9.0) |
(1) |
Skills in experimentation and testing |
55% (16.5) |
17% (5.0) |
28% (8.5) |
(2) |
Subtotal |
40% (36.5) |
31% (28.0) |
29% (26.5) |
(5) |
Production |
51% (23.5) |
46% (21.0) |
3% (1.5) |
(18) |
Technical backup |
73% (14.5) |
10% (2.0) |
18% (3.5) |
(12) |
Overall total |
51% (189.0) |
27% (97.5) |
22% (82.5) |
(47) |
Source: Faulkner, Senker
and Velho (1994).
a. PSR Public Sector research.
b. NR = nonresponses; this includes a
small number of responses that gave equal weight to all three sources.
c. R&D = research and
development.
* percentage of responses; numbers in
parentheses.
** PSR is referred to as “public
science” by Gibbons and Johnston (1974), and defined as Public Sector research
STI to innovation. [15] The
major difference is that we did not attempt to quantify the types of knowledge
used in innovation.
The two studies have a crucial common feature: both
start from an analysis of firms’ total knowledge requirements (or use) as the
most appropriate basis for assessing the particular contribution of PSR. This makes the findings in Tables 1 and 2
interesting for two reasons. First, they
reveal that companies obtain different types of knowledge from different
sources. Second, they provide a quite
detailed picture of the full range of knowledge types utilized in the course of
R&D leading to innovation.
437
The dominant contribution of internal sources to
knowledge used in innovation is confirmed by the data in both tables. [16] Researchers we interviewed reported almost
unanimously that what they called tacit skills, acquired largely on the job,
make a greater overall contribution to innovation than does formal knowledge,
acquired from literature and education. Further
questioning revealed that tacit knowledge is also obtained from other companies
and from PSR (Senker and Faulkner 1993). Significantly, though, industrial R&D
activities demand a synthesis of these diverse contributions from both internal
and external sources.
Table 1 shows that internal sources make a
particularly high contribution to design and to test procedures and techniques,
and contribute substantially to properties of materials and components. Similarly, in Table 2, internal sources
dominate in routine problem solving (as well as technical backup) and
contribute substantially to skills in experimentation and testing. Thus the type of knowledge obtained from
internal sources is primarily associated with the core activities of R&D
and design. Gibbons and Johnston found
that half of all knowledge from internal sources is collectively generated, as
a result of in-house activities (mostly experimentation and analysis), and half
is personal in the sense that it is already known to the individual researcher,
as a result of previous education and work experience. [17]
Instrumentalities are an important aspect of R&D. Table 2 shows that the impact of internal
sources in this area is slightly less than average. This, in part, reflects the fact that other
companies make a major contribution to research equipment (and a relatively
high contribution to production and knowledge of knowledge). A second factor is the slightly
greater-than-average contribution of PSR to the procedures and skills used in
R&D (although this is not particularly evident in Table 1). Other evidence from our study highlights the
practical help with experimentation provided by contacts in PSR, which supports
de Solla Price’s contention that instrumentalities are an important area of
overlap between academic and industrial research.
Table 1 indicates that internal sources contribute
less to theory than to any other category of knowledge, although still more
than external sources. Conversely,
theory is the only category in which PSR makes a greater-than-average
contribution: one-third of all theory-related knowledge comes from this source.
This is consistent with our finding that
PSR contributes most significantly in two areas: scanning the research frontier
and underpinning knowledge. [18] In Table 1,
design is the category to which PSR contributes least, whereas Table 2
indicates that PSR can contribute materially to product design and development
(at least in the more design-based fields) and to scouting for new
applications. Nonetheless, our finding
that PSR has only a very minor impact on future innovation supports the
conclusion of Gibbons
438
and Johnston that “public science” is generally “not the springhead of
innovative ideas” (1974).
It is not possible to separate scientific and
technological knowledge within the various categories used in these two
studies. However, the data presented
here do shed light on the relative contribution of each to innovation, which is
relevant to the science-technology debate outlined earlier. First, it is clear that scientific knowledge
(as defined earlier) is a part of the theory, knowledge of properties, and
methodology used in the R&D that leads to innovation. Second, at least some of this scientific
knowledge comes from internal sources (and, sometimes, other companies): there
is a considerable in-house contribution in the areas of theory, underpinning
knowledge, scanning the research frontier, and instrumentalities. Third, PSR also contributes some technological
knowledge through its input to research equipment and, in some fields, to
engineering research and design.
Biotechnology is an interesting case in point because
the boundaries between science and technology appear particularly indistinct in
this field. Yet our study and my own
earlier research (Faulkner 1986, 1989) reveal that even here the nuances of
distinction between scientific and technological knowledge still have some
meaning. Significantly, industrial
researchers in this field - unlike those in advanced ceramics and parallel
computing - unambivalently call
themselves scientists.
The various threads of evidence presented here lead to
three broad conclusions. First, with
regard to the overall knowledge used in innovation, the dominant contribution
of internal sources is confirmed; this knowledge is primarily associated with
design and R&D activities. Second,
the more significant contribution identified as coming from PSR is in research
rather than in design and development; PSR contributes new knowledge,
theoretical knowledge, and knowledge related to research techniques, which is
consistent with the idea that the balance of frontier research occurs within
PSR. Third, these studies clearly show
that industrial research is by no means exclusively concerned with
technological knowledge, any more than public sector research solely
constitutes “public science.”
Why Companies Use
Internal and External Sources of Knowledge
Keith Pavitt (1984) noted that by privately funding
R&D activities, companies add to the total stock of knowledge as well as
drawing on knowledge that is publicly available. Three factors explain the dominant role of
internal knowledge. First, firms need to
appropriate technology related to specific artifacts, normally by patenting or
trade secrecy, in order to extract a reasonable rent from them. When a product is a radical improvement on the
439
existing ones, obtaining proprietary advantage may even secure the
innovator monopoly profits for a while. Appropriating
external technology is often necessary but problematic. The experience of technology transfer reveals
that ownership of intellectual property alone is inadequate, because additional
tacit knowledge and skills are generally needed in order to effect the
transfer. [19] And in this,
as in other forms of external knowledge acquisition, an understated but
significant irony is that companies must have some related in-house expertise
if they are to make sense of and to fully exploit external knowledge
(Gambardella 1992).
This relates to the second reason for the dominant
role of internal sources of knowledge in innovation, namely the cumulative
nature of technological development. This
is a recurring theme in economic histories of technology, and one I would
stress. [20] At the level
of technological fields, the cumulative nature of development is reflected in
“path dependence” whereby one development appears to suggest the next. Path dependence is captured in the now common
use of the terms technological trajectories and paradigms (Dosi
1982). [21] Knowledge acquisition and
generation are also strongly cumulative at the level of the firm. It is easier for companies to build on
existing capability than to start afresh, and organizational learning is
necessary to build up capability. Learning
is particularly crucial in relation to difficult-to-acquire tacit and
skill-based knowledge, which may explain why tacit knowledge is often
identified as being derived primarily from in-house capability and efforts.
The third reason for the dominance of internal sources
of knowledge is the role of specific, as opposed to general, knowledge in
innovation. Pavitt (1984), for example,
explains the overriding importance of internally generated knowledge by the
specificity of the knowledge inputs necessary for product differentiation in
the marketplace and for appropriability. Giovanni Dosi (1988) relates the concept to
the breadth of in-house R&D, arguing that low product specificity in
R&D enables companies to achieve synergy across product areas, whereas high
firm specificity is more likely to secure appropriability. These comments on specific knowledge in
product innovation resonate with Fleck’s (1988) concern with contingent
knowledge in complex process innovation.
Specificity pertains primarily to design and
development work, some three quarters of industrial R&D expenditure. By contrast, industrial research is likely to
have a broader remit; it may be characterized as a search activity, undertaken
to identify new opportunities and to resolve attendant problems. Nathan Rosenberg (1992) stressed that
companies are simply unable to know fully in advance what they should be
searching for, or to pursue all possible alternatives in their search efforts. Richard Nelson (1982) conceptualizes
440
knowledge as “capability for efficient search” and argues that
corporate expenditure on basic research “enhances the productivity of applied
research and development” by helping companies to establish where they should
be looking. This is likely to be
especially crucial at times of technological discontinuity or paradigm shift. Nevertheless, companies tend to underinvest in
basic research because of the uncertainty surrounding its outcome and the
difficulty of appropriating any benefits (Nelson 1959).
Both the knowledge contribution of PSR to innovation
and the “division of labor” between industrial R&D and PSR are broadly
explicable within this framework (Rosenberg 1990; Pavitt 1991). In effect, government funding of basic
research underwrites the long-term interests of industry by conducting an
open-ended and speculative search operation on its behalf.
The contribution of other companies is most easily
explained in terms of the importance to innovation of knowledge flow among
companies in the supply chain. Innovations of all types may demand knowledge
from suppliers of materials or components incorporated into the final product
(von Hippel 1988). Moreover, success in
innovation depends crucially on the quality of knowledge flow about user needs
(Rothwell 1977). The relationship is of
course particularly strong with specialist users of complex technologies (Fleck
1988, 1993). Such considerations should
not blind us to the importance of knowledge flow between competitors, however. Nelson (1982) argued that, in addition to
companies’ interests in securing proprietary advantage by keeping certain
knowledge private, companies have a collective interest in keeping much
technological knowledge in the public domain. Without this knowledge, no companies on their
own would be innovative. Of course, the
patent system and other publications are formal mechanisms by which
technological knowledge is shared. Our
field experience suggests that, although industrial staff are careful not to
disclose commercially sensitive information, some types of technological
knowledge (for example, knowledge of instrumentalities) are quite extensively
shared through informal interaction. [22]
The question why some knowledge is generated
internally and other knowledge is obtained from external sources is very
significant for economists of technology. A useful conceptual framework for addressing
such issues has come from the field of evolutionary economics, in particular
from the recent work of Stanley Metcalfe and Michael Gibbons (1989) who write
about the organizational knowledge base that companies must “articulate” in
order to produce a given set of artifacts. This framework seeks to explain the dual
occurrence of continuity and change in technological innovation. Path dependence and cumulative knowledge
acquisition within the firm explain why companies articulate knowledge most
effectively in fields that are
441
familiar to them, and why they find it difficult to extend their
existing knowledge base into new areas of innovative activity. Metcalfe and Gibbons suggest that external
sources of knowledge will be especially important in cases of radical
innovation because movement into new fields is strongly constrained, not only
by the existing capability of a firm but also by technological paradigms. According to Dosi (1982, 155), technological
paradigms have a “powerful exclusion effect” and so limit the ability of firms
to “see” knowledge (including technological options) that is available outside.
Firms’ external search activity and
research linkages are important means to overcome these constraints.
Categorizations of Knowledge Used in Innovation
Given that companies use a range of knowledge types in
the course of R&D leading to innovation, how should we best conceptualize
this epistemological variety? Five
different attempts to categorize knowledge used in innovation are summarized in
Tables 3 and 4. As indicated, these
categorizations differ in terms of the disciplinary perspective of their
authors and the purposes for which they were devised. They also fall into two distinct groups in
terms of the level of conceptualization attempted. The contributions in Table 3 concern what we
might call broad distinctions in the character of knowledge used in innovation,
whereas those in Table 4 represent more specific categories of knowledge. The latter categorizations provide the basis
of the typology proposed here, and the broader distinctions provide a useful
context for this typology.
Broad Distinctions
in the Character of Knowledge Used in Innovation
Table 3 presents a synthesis of the contributions of
Sidney Winter (1987) and Giovanni Dosi (1988), both of whom attempt to
understand knowledge used in innovation from within the framework of
evolutionary economics. Although not
directly empirically derived, both contributions build on earlier case studies.
The contribution of James Fleck and
Margaret Tierney (1991) is based on a detailed study of the development and
management of expertise in the course of strategic innovations in financial
services that they analyze from a “social shaping of technology” perspective.
Elsewhere, Fleck (1992) proposed a useful framework in
which he characterizes technological expertise as involving a tripartite
relationship along the three axes of knowledge, power, and tradability,
addressed respectively
Table 3: Broad Categorizations of
Knowledge Used in Innovation
Authors |
Fleck & Tierney (1991) |
Winter (1987); also Dosi (1988) |
Perspective |
Social shaping of technology |
Evolutionary economics |
Aim |
To conceptualize knowledge in terms of sociocognitive structures that relate the content of knowledge to how it is distributed among individuals and organizations |
To distinguish features of technological knowledge that impinge on the ease of technology transfer between firms |
Categories |
Metaknowledge Milieu Contingent knowledge Tacit knowledge Informal knowledge Formal knowledge Instrumentalities |
Tacit—articulated (Teachable-nonteachable) (Articulate—nonarticulate) Nonobservable—observable Complex—simple Elements of a system-independent Specific-general
|
by the disciplines of epistemology, politics, and economics. He concluded that, although some work
successfully addresses two of these three axes (one or the other side of the
triad), no existing approach integrates all three. The categorization proposed by Fleck and
Tierney (1991, 12) is an attempt to move in this direction. It explicitly links the social context within
which expertise is generated and utilized with its cognitive character: “Viewing knowledge in terms of components of
socio-cognitive structures provides a means for relating the content of
knowledge to its specific embodiment” (Fleck and Tierney 1991).
Fleck and Tierney’s sociocognitive structures have two
major dimensions: (1) the components of knowledge (identified in Table 3), and
(2) the distribution of knowledge among different carrier groups or
individuals. Issues of power and
tradability clearly enter the latter dimension, because these issues determine
the monetary value and status attributed to particular competence or knowledge.
Labor process factors, for example,
shape both the construction of skills and expertise, and internal and external
labor markets for specific expertise. Similarly, the extent to which knowledge can
be appropriated impinges crucially on the success of the innovating
organization and on the wider diffusion of this knowledge.
As noted earlier, the tradability and ease of transfer
of knowledge between companies are central concerns for economists of
technology. Winter (1987) and Dosi
(1988) separately suggested continua that characterize technologi-
443
Table 4: Detailed Categorizations of Knowledge Used in
Innovation
Authors |
Vincenti (1991) |
Gibbons and Johnston (1974) Faulkner, Senker, and Velho (1994) |
Perspective |
History of technology |
Innovation studies |
Aim |
To develop an epistemology of engineering, in particular to relate categories of knowledge to knowledge-generating activities |
To establish the extent and character of knowledge flows from public sector research into industrial innovation by investigating the full range of knowledge inputs to innovation |
Categories |
Categories of Knowledge
Fundamental design concepts Knowledge-generating activities
Transfer from science |
Content of information Broad Knowledge Types Theories, laws, general principles Knowledge of particular fields Properties, composition, Technical information characteristics of materials and Skills components Knowledge related to artifacts Operating principles or rules Required specifications, technical Impact on company activities limitations New product ideas Design-based information Articulation of user needs Test procedures and techniques Feedback on existing products Existence of equipment or materials Scouting for new applications with particular properties Scanning the research frontier Existence of specialist facilities or Underpinning knowledge services Routine problem solving Location of information New research equipment New R&D procedures Skills in experimentation and testing New process technology New production methods Technical backup |
444
cal knowledge and together have a strong bearing on cross-sector
variety in appropriability regimes and technology transfer. These have been amalgamated in Table 3. (The features listed on the right-hand side
are likely to be associated with ease of transfer.)
These continua echo a number of elements in the Fleck
and Tierney categorization. The concepts
of specific and contingent knowledge refer to the important role of local
knowledge discussed earlier, and they may be contrasted with Fleck and Tierney’s
category of the more taken-for-granted metalevel knowledge that is universal. [23] In addition, their distinction between formal
and informal knowledge appears to be subsumed in Winter’s distinction between
tacit and articulated knowledge. He
elaborates on this aspect by distinguishing between what is nonarticulated and
nonarticulable, and between what is teachable and nonteachable. These distinctions usefully focus on skills
that may be taught (by example) although they are not articulable, and on
articulable knowledge that sometimes gets “lost” because it is never
articulated. [24] The category
“observability in use” describes how easily the underlying knowledge embodied
in a product is revealed in practice. This
is likely to depend both on the capability of the observer and on the
willingness of the producer to cooperate and share relevant tacit knowledge. Finally, Winter suggests that the more complex
and system dependent the particular technological artifact and knowledge, the
less accessible it will be. This
resonates with Fleck’s (1988, 1993) earlier work on configurational technologies
in which he classifies technologies in relation to the complexity of the
knowledge associated with them.
In principle, it should be possible to combine the
elements of the two categorizations in Table 3. The broad character of knowledge could be
related to the wider social and economic factors that influence where knowledge
is located and what knowledge gets transferred between individuals and groups. My purpose here is not to attempt the
synthesis Fleck envisions but to elaborate primarily on the more narrowly cognitive
or epistemological aspects of his triad. However, it should be borne in mind that the
two other axes of expertise identified by Fleck - power and tradability - cut
across the more detailed categorizations of knowledge that we explore below.
Detailed Categories
of Knowledge Used in Innovation
Table 4 lists three sets of categorizations
constructed on the basis of the studies by Vincenti, Gibbons and Johnston, and
ourselves. Differences in emphasis among
these categorizations reflect largely differences in the empirical studies from
which they were derived. Vincenti’s
study was based on case studies of “normal” design in one field of engineering
over an
445
extended period ending in 1950; Gibbons and Johnston’s categorization
was based on individual successful innovations from a range of sectors in the
1970s; and our own categorization was based on R&D into promising new
technologies in the 1980s and 1990s that have not yet yielded significant
innovations. Although they all address
technological processes, these studies highlight different aspects and
different periods of recent history. The
historical research methods of Vincenti are distinct from Gibbons and
Johnston’s and our interview-based methodology. Nevertheless, all three categorizations have
been derived from open-ended and detailed empirical inquiries into the totality
of technical knowledge utilized in the course of innovation. The categories have then been imposed on these
data by the researchers. [25] Both Vincenti
and I have striven to use labels and categories identifiable to, if not
identified by, practitioners (and so meaningful to them) - except for the term
instrumentalities.
Table 5 draws together what I see as the main
elements identified in Table 4. It
presents a composite typology that groups fifteen different types of knowledge
used in industrial innovation, under five headings. These categories should be fairly
self-explanatory, but their main features are briefly outlined below with
reference, where appropriate, to the three studies from which they were
derived.
Knowledge relating to the natural world. This
includes theories and knowledge of the properties of materials, two categories
that are generally easy to identify. The
domains of science and technology are both present. Theory, in the sense described by Vincenti,
includes the theoretical tools (such a parametric variation) used in
engineering experimentation, whereas the category “properties” encompasses
properties of artifacts and of nature.
Knowledge related to design practice. Design-related
knowledge, most evident in Vincenti’s categories and least in ours, [26] constitutes
a vital aspect of technological innovation. Typically, design and development activities
follow four stages (Walsh et al. 1992, chap. 7). First, design criteria are drawn up on
the basis of the dual requirements of the companies and the potential users. Second, more detailed specifications are
then produced on the basis of technical considerations (feasibility, etc.). Third, alternative concept designs are
considered and one is eventually selected. Finally, the detailed design of the product is
elaborated.
The various types of design concepts listed in
Table 5 come from Vincenti. “Fundamental
operating principles” are the principles that make a particular artifact work:
for example, the fixed-wing aircraft that flies because of Cayley’s
446 Index
Table 5. Composite Typology of Knowledge Used in Innovation |
Related to natural world |
Scientific and engineering theory |
“laws” of nature; theoretical tools |
Properties of materials |
Natural and artificial materials |
Related to design practice |
Design criteria and specifications |
Understanding of user requirements |
Demands of company and technology |
Specifications of components |
Design concepts |
Fundamental operating principles |
Normal configurations |
Creative ideas |
Design instrumentalities a |
Design competence a |
General design competence |
Competence in specific product area |
Practical experience |
Related to experimental R&D b |
Experimental and test procedures |
Research instrumentalitiesa |
Ability to utilize experimental techniques and equipment |
Ability to interpret test and experimental results |
Research competencea |
General research competence |
Competence in particular specialism |
Experimental and test data |
Related to final product |
New product ideas |
Operating performance |
Performance of components or materials |
Pilot production, field trials, and so on |
User experience |
Production competencea |
Design requirements for manufacture |
Competence in pilot production/scale-up |
Related to knowledge |
Knowledge of knowledge |
Location of particular knowledge |
Availability of equipment, materials, specialist facilities, or services |
a. Indicates knowledge that is heavily skill based. b. Research and Development |
principle that one can “make a surface support a given weight by the
application of power to the resistance of air” (cited in Vincenti 1991, chap.
447
7). “Normal configurations” are
the arrangements and shapes commonly taken to be the best embodiments of
operating principles; they represent the framework of “normal” design. Such knowledge is intrinsically technological
rather than scientific and is often taken for granted, having been absorbed
from earlier engineering. The role of
creative ideas in both concept design and detailed design is everywhere
acknowledged, even if “creative ideas” are a little awkward as a category of
knowledge. Good ideas rarely emerge in a
vacuum.
The category design instrumentalities adopted
by Vincenti encompasses structured procedures (such as decomposing a problem
into subproblems), ways of doing things and thinking (for example, the use of
analogy and “what would happen if?” approaches), and judgmental skills (for
example, the ability to balance conflicting design requirements) (Vincenti
1991, chap. 7). The role of skills or competence
in all aspects of design - general and specific - is self-evident (although
there is arguably considerable overlap between design skills and design
instrumentalities). Practical
considerations, in Vincenti’s use, imply knowledge drawing more on
experience than skill (1991, chap. 7). They
include the vital elements of user experience of operation, shopfloor
experience of construction or production, and the “rules of thumb” from
previous design experience. [27]
Knowledge related to experimental R&D. Experimental and test procedures are accepted ways of setting up experiments and tests.
[28]
Research instrumentalities, following
de Solla Price (1984), are knowledge and skills related to the techniques and
artifacts used in the course of experimental R&D. As with the example of Rosalind Franklin’s skill
at X-ray crystallography, instrumentalities include the ability to use research
instruments effectively. Senker’s work
on advanced engineering ceramics demonstrates that the ability to interpret
test results obtained from sophisticated equipment is also crucial (Senker and
Faulkner 1992).
The nature of general and specific research
competence is self-evident, as is the category of experimental and test
data. The latter is perhaps the most
tangible knowledge output of R&D. Vincenti’s
work stressed the importance of data to engineering capability and showed that
quantitative data may be either theoretically or empirically derived and may be
either descriptive or prescriptive (Vincenti 1991, chap. 7). Our study and Gibbons and Johnston’s reveal
that data often relate to both properties of materials and to operating
performance (see below).
Knowledge related to the final product. We have
found that new product ideas rarely emerge in a single step from a
single source but rather “coalesce”
448
over a period of time. Knowledge
about the operating performance of the product is clearly vital and is
obtained variously through pilot production, direct trials, and user
experience. Knowledge about the performance
of components and materials is obtained from suppliers and users, and from
experience. Production competence contributes
to early concept design (ideally), as well as to later detailed design through
pilot production.
Knowledge related to knowledge. The category “knowledge of knowledge” comes from
Gibbons and Johnston’s study. It
captures the facility to find out things that are necessary to new product
development but that are not known to those immediately involved. Our study confirmed that, in the course of
search activity and problem solving, external contacts are widely used to
locate facilities, literature, and other contacts in particular specialisms.
Some Comments on
the Composite Typology
Because of the quantitative methodology employed by
Gibbons and Johnston, their data (in Table 2) give some indication of the
relative importance of different knowledge types. Thus information relating to design accounts
for one quarter of knowledge used in innovation, as does knowledge of
knowledge. Knowledge of the properties
of materials and components together account for one-third (unfortunately,
we do not know the distribution between materials and components). And knowledge of test procedures and theories
together account for nearly one-fifth.
There is a fair degree of overlap and fluidity between
the fifteen categories in the typology. This
is in the nature of the beast: knowledge used in innovation does not come in
watertight boxes but is mutable and multidimensional, precisely because of the
complex social processes by which it is generated and utilized. In an attempt to “get a handle” on some of
this complexity, I would tentatively suggest that at least two taxonomic axes
cut across the specific categories of knowledge listed in Table 5. The first axis concerns the object of
the knowledge in question, which may be the knowledge of:
1. the natural world
2. design practice
3. experimental R&D
4. the final product
5. knowledge itself
These headings provide a convenient and relatively
straightforward way of grouping specific knowledge types, as indicated in Table
5.
449
The second axis cutting across these categories refers
to the more slippery but nonetheless significant distinctions concerning the
broad character of knowledge. To these I
would add the frequently cited distinction between knowing and doing, and a
distinction that, in my view, is still not sufficiently grasped in this
“Information Age,” namely, that between knowledge and information (Wildavsky
1983). This suggests a three-way
distinction between knowing as understanding, knowing as holding information,
and knowing as holding skills, alongside the main dualistic distinctions
identified in Table 3:
1. understanding—information—skill
2. tacit—articulated
3. complex—simple
4. local—universal
5. specific/contingent—general/metalevel
The importance of these broad distinctions is likely
to vary with different specific categories of knowledge. Thus, for example, skill-based knowledge
appears in my typology under Design, R&D, and Production. Specific and local knowledge is likely to be
particularly significant in Design, Production, and Operating performance (see
Vincenti 1991, chap. 6), as is tacit knowledge, which is also likely to be
dominant in Practical experience.
In summary, we may usefully conceive of the knowledge
used in innovation in terms of three taxonomic dimensions, namely:
1. specific types of knowledge (the typology)
2. the object or activities with which they are
associated (product, R&D, etc.)
3. broad distinctions in the character of knowledge
(tacit, specific, etc.)
Although elements in the last two dimensions relate closely to the
social and economic issues of power and tradability noted by Fleck, these
dimensions do not in themselves account adequately for the more external
aspects of knowledge. They do, however,
provide a reasonably rich and rounded framework for conceptualizing the
cognitive and epistemological aspects of knowledge used in innovation.
On this basis, I suggest we need a conceptualization
that integrates the three dimensions of type, object, and character. The approach developed by us to investigate
knowledge flows between industry and public sector research begins to achieve
such an integration empirically. As
indicated in Table 4, we asked three sets of questions about the knowledge
inputs to innovation. First, we asked
interviewees to specify the types of knowledge they use, under four headings:
knowledge of particular fields, technical information, skills,
450
and knowledge related to artifacts. [29] We then asked
them to characterize these types of knowledge in terms of whether they were
predominantly tacit or formal in nature. Finally, we asked them to indicate the
“impact” or contribution of knowledge from various sources in terms of
different company activities (also indicated in Table 4). It is not difficult to see how each of these
steps could be refined or extended by application of the composite typology
proposed here, together with further questioning on the broad distinctions of
character suggested above.
To further our conceptualization of the types of
knowledge used in innovation, I have reviewed the literature on the
science-technology distinction and on industrial innovation. This review led to the conclusion that there
is a strongly interactive relationship between science and technology, instrumentalities
being an important area of overlap. In
some new fields, such as biotechnology, the relationship between science and
technology is so intimate that the boundaries between them appear blurred, if
not obliterated. Nonetheless, technology
can be distinguished from science because of its practical, artifactual
orientation. This has implications for
both its sociotechnical organization and its cognitive or epistemological
character.
Empirical findings confirm that what we commonly take
to be scientific knowledge is used in the course of R&D leading to
innovation, and that industrial organizations and PSR institutions both contribute
to this knowledge. Such conclusions must
be placed in context, however, because the contribution of science is
relatively small. Other, more strictly
technological, knowledge plays a greater role in innovation. Moreover, technology also contributes to
science - at least to the extent that instrumentalities relate to artifacts - and
may thus be considered to encompass both scientific and technological
knowledge. With respect to the
institutional distinction between industry and PSR, in-house R&D and
expertise generally make a greater contribution to knowledge used in innovation
than PSR, which is often less important than knowledge originating from other
companies. The dominance of knowledge
from internal sources is explained by the need to appropriate knowledge, by the
cumulative nature of innovation, and by the importance of specific knowledge. Significantly, though, industrial R&D
activities demand a synthesis of tacit and formal knowledge from internal and
external sources.
This article has compared various attempts to capture
the heterogeneity of technological knowledge. The categories proposed by
Winter, Dosi, and
451
Fleck and Tierney identify broad distinctions in the character of
technological knowledge (tacit-articulated, specific-general, etc.). To a degree, these categories relate to the
wider economic and power-related factors shaping the distribution of knowledge
among individuals and organizations, although they do not account for them. The categories developed by Vincenti, Gibbons
and Johnston, and my colleagues focus in greater detail on the content of
knowledge utilized in innovation. The
composite typology proposed here draws together the main features identified in
these latter categorizations. It
identifies fifteen different types of knowledge, grouped under five headings
that reflect the different activities or objects to which each knowledge type
relates: the natural world, design, R&D, the final product, and knowledge
itself. It is argued that the broad
distinctions in the character of knowledge identified by Winter, Dosi, and
Fleck and Tierney also cut across the more specific categories in the proposed
typology. Thus a more complete conceptualization
of technological knowledge should incorporate three taxonomic dimensions: the
specific knowledge types (viz., our typology), the object or activities to
which they relate, and the broad differences of character.
This conceptualization is a refinement of the
categories used in our empirical study. I
believe that this refinement strengthens and extends the applicability of a
research approach that seeks to characterize in detail the range of knowledge
used in the course of R&D leading to innovation. The studies by Gibbons and Johnston and ourselves
have utilized this approach to good effect as a means of examining the
particular knowledge contribution of PSR to innovation. But there is a real need, and considerable
scope, to improve and refine our conceptualization of the knowledge flows associated
with all aspects of industrial innovation, not solely public-private research
linkage. For example, collaborations
between user and supplier companies may also be addressed in terms of science
and technology flows. Indeed, work being
conducted at Edinburgh specifically focuses on different types of expertise
utilized in the development and modification of complex IT systems (Fleck
1992b). There is also a connection with
recent work at Manchester that investigates technology strategy in terms of the
relationship between companies’ knowledge base and corporate strategies (Coombs
and Richards 1991).
These developments appear to signal a more “holistic”
approach to the study of industrial innovation that, in the spirit of this
journal, genuinely spans sociological and economic approaches to the subject. Moreover, the kind of work I have in mind
offers a possibility to explore how knowledge itself changes during the
innovation process. For example, it is
already widely recognized that technology transfer involves a transformation
of knowledge (Gold 1980; Peláez 1991). Perhaps our most exciting challenge is to “get
452
inside” the processes of knowledge transformation, using research tools
like the typology proposed here.
Substantial policy and management benefits could
result from such work. or example, the
typology could be used by companies to investigate the extent and nature of
their knowledge base and knowledge requirements in specific areas - perhaps in
areas that are new to them - or to assess whether they are making the best use
of available sources of knowledge to meet their requirements. Similarly, government organizations might use
this approach to assess the strengths and weaknesses of the R&D system in a
particular field - perhaps one of strategic interest - or to assess the
effectiveness of policy measures geared to enhancing the R&D system and
flows of knowledge around it. Discussions
of these important issues are often lamentably superficial and policy
interventions are not sufficiently targeted.
Perhaps the greatest need for more sophisticated tools
for understanding the knowledge required in innovation lies in those countries
and firms least advantaged in terms of scientific and technological
infrastructure. In such cases, technology
strategy demands a means to address questions such as:
What types of knowledge about available technologies
do we need and how do we gain access to them? What types of knowledge do we need if we are
to acquire an external technology, or to develop our own internally? In principle at least, the conceptualization I
have proposed here could act as a checklist and enable organizations to make
informed decisions that avoid wasting limited scientific and technological
resources.
1. An earlier version of
this article was presented to a workshop entitled “Exploring Expertise,” which
sought to draw together different conceptualizations. See especially Fleck 1992 and Winter 1987.
2. I am using the
conventional shorthand of research and development (R&D) to include design,
but I would stress that design and development are often more important to
innovation than R&D.
3. The study was titled
“Public-Private Research Linkage in Advanced Technologies.” It was funded by the U.K. Economic and Social
Research Council under the Science Policy Support Group Initiative on Public
Science and Commercial Enterprise. Dr.
Jacqueline Senker of the Science Policy Research Unit, University of Sussex,
and Dr. Lea Velho, now of the University of Campinas, conducted most of the
fieldwork for this study. I am grateful
to them both for permission to use some of the findings here.
4. Utterback(1971) and
Rosenberg(1992) make a similar point about innovation in scientific
instruments.
5. They also, contrary
to de Solla Price’s assumptions, contribute to this literature (Hicks, Isard,
and Martin 1993).
453
6. Fores may be
justified in stressing the primarily empirical character of engineering, but it
is hard to refute the case that the transition from craft to modern technology
represents two “epochs” (Constant 1 984b) in the history of technology, even
though elements of the former inevitably remain an important part of what we
today call technology. See Layton (1988)
and Channell (1988) for their responses to Fores.
7. The greater number
and importance of “relevant social groups” was, of course, also recognized in
Pinch and Bijker’s seminal call for a sociology of technology built on
conceptual frameworks from the sociology of science. As David Edge (1992) notes, the greater social
complexity of technology makes it more difficult to study than science. More forcefully, Sørensen and Levold (1992)
argue that scholars who transfer conceptual frameworks from the study of
science to the study of technology are likely to have “blind spots” concerning
technology. Indeed, sociologists of
technology have been strongly criticized for failing to grasp macrolevel forces
shaping technology (e.g., Russell and Williams 1988).
8. This view is
explored empirically in Edge (1992 seep. 158).
9. Collins (1974)
himself does problematize what constitutes replication in science.
10. These techniques
involve some theory (e.g., laws of similitude and dimensional analysis), but
such theory is more engineering than scientific in character, in the sense
outlined above.
11. Although, as
Vincenti (1991, chap. 4) noted, it may involve an act of considerable reduction
to reveal this in the case of engineering theory.
12. These studies
attempted to identify the key cognitive or research “events” that contributed
to specific innovations (in industry and defense, respectively) and then to
analyze what proportion of these events took place in publicly funded
laboratories. The studies were
criticized because the time frame adopted had a crucial bearing on the results
produced, because the method of retrospective reporting was highly selective
and assumed that the origin of an idea or “piece” of knowledge
could be sensibly identified, and because of the inadequacies of the linear
model on which the approach was based (Barnes and Edge 1982).
13. Their data have
been reworked in two ways. First, their
content categories have been grouped under five headings, to reflect more
closely the composite categorization developed below. Second, their external sources have been
broken down as far as the data allow to reveal the respective contributions of
public sector research (PSR) and other companies. A small proportion of their data could not be
easily categorized in this way, and so only 254 of the total 300 units of
information for external sources are represented in this table, and only 94 of
the total 107 obtained from “public science.”
14. Originally,
thirteen subheadings were used under these six main headings, but there was
little variation between sources for the subheadings under Future Innovations,
Production, and Technical Backup, so these have been aggregated. The numbers of responses sometimes include
halves because many of our respondents were unable to identify a single source
as having the major impact on an activity and so gave dual responses; these
numbers have been allocated equally between each source involved.
15. A full account of
the methodology developed can be found in Faulkner (1992).
16. It should be
stressed that the unit of analysis in Table 2 is numbers of responses and not
units of information as in Table 1. Also,
the responses are to categories that are in no way equally weighted. As a result, the absolute values are not
significant although the relative ones are - at least within each “impact”
category.
17. Our study revealed
some variation in the relative importance of collectively derived and
individually held knowledge, but we did not examine this systematically.
18. PSR accounts for 53
percent of the reported impact on scanning the research frontier and 43 percent
of that on underpinning knowledge.
19. This explains the
importance of “on the hoof’ or “person embodied” mechanisms of transfer.
454
20. See, for a review,
Rosenberg (1982, chap. 1); also his early work on the nineteenth-century
machine tool industry (1976).
21. These terms have
perhaps been adopted too easily: Fleck, Webster, and Williams (1990)
demonstrates that trajectories of technological development do not always
follow the path anticipated for them and that alternative trajectories can
exist side by side.
22. We have found that
industrial R&D workers and designers communicate quite frequently with
their opposite numbers in competitor companies (Senker and Faulkner 1993). Barden and Good (1989) found such discussions,
although not frequent, to be highly influential in terms of the direction of
projects.
23. They give as an
example assumptions of technocratic rationality.
24. A common example is
the failure to document fully programming code.
25. Although in the
case of our categories, this took place at the pilot stage of the research.
26. This largely
reflects our initial decision to subsume design into R&D, and the fact that
our categories derived primarily from a study of biotechnology, where design is
relatively unimportant compared with research. The gap became particularly evident in our
study of parallel computing and represents an obvious area of improvement for
future work.
27. Vincenti (1991,
chap. 7) gives as an example the knowledge that successful jets require a ratio
of engine thrust to loaded aircraft weight of between 0.2 and 0.3.
28. Note that this
category might be subsumed under research instrumentalities. Although this would parallel Vincenti’s use of
instrumentalities in relation to design, it would create a rather large
category and so potentially lead to a loss of “resolution.”
29. Knowledge of
particular field includes scientific theory, engineering principles, and
knowledge of knowledge (after Gibbons and Johnston 1974); technical
infonnation includes specifications and operating performance of products
or components, plus experimental or test procedures and results; skills includes
specific skills, such as programming, and more general research or production
competence; artifacts includes knowledge relevant to process or research
instrumentation (overwhelmingly the latter), and other intermediates used in
R&D.
Barden, P., and B.
Good. 1989. Information flows into industrial research. London: Centre for the Exploitation of
Science and Technology.
Barnes, B., and D.
Edge. 1982. The interaction of science and technology. In Science in context: Readings in the
sociology of science, edited by B. Barnes and D. Edge, 147-54. Milton Keynes:
Open University Press.
Battelle Columbus
Laboratory. 1973. Interactions of science and technology in the innovative
process: Some case studies. Final report to the National Science Foundation (NSF-C667).
Ohio: Battelle Columbus Laboratory.
Bode, H. W. 1965.
Reflections on the relation between science and technology. In National Academy
of Science, Basic research and national goals; A report to the Committee on
Science and Astronautics, U.S. House of Representatives. Washington, DC:
Government Printing Office.
XXX Bud, R., and S.
Cozzens, eds. 1992. Invisible connections: Instruments, institutions and
science. Bellingham, WA: SPIE Optical Engineering Press.
Carpenter, M. P., M.
Cooper, and F. Narmn. 1980. Linkage between basic research and patents. Research
Management 23 (2):30.
Carpenter, M. P., F.
Narmn, and P. Woolfe. 1981. Citation rates to technologically important
patents. World Patent Information 3 (4):160-63.
455
Channell, D. F. 1982.
The harmony of theory and practice: The engineering science of WJM Rankine. Technology
and Culture 23 (l):39-52.
___________ . 1988.
Engineering science as theory and practice. Technology and Culture 29
(1): 98-103.
Collins, H. 1974. The
TEA set: Tacit knowledge and scientific networks. Science Studies 4:165-86.
Constant, E. 1984a.
Scientific theory and technological testability: Science, dynamometers, and
water turbines in the 19th century. Technology and Culture 24(2):l83-98.
______________ . l984b.
Communities in hierarchies: Structure in the practice of science and
technology. In The nature of technological knowledge: Are models of
scientific change relevant? edited by R. Laudan. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Coombs, R., and
Richards, A. 1991. Technologies, products and firm strategies: Part II-
Analysis of three cases. Technology Analysis and Strategic Management, 3
(2):157-75.
de Solla Price, D. J.
1965. Is technology historically independent of science? A study of statistical
historiography. Technology and Culture 6 (4): 553-68.
Dosi, G. 1982.
Technological paradigms and technological trajectories: A suggested interpretation
of the determinants and direction of technical change. Research Policy 11:147-62.
_____ .1988. The nature
of the innovative process. In Technical change and economic theory, edited
by G. Dosi, C., Freeman, R., Nelson, L., Soete, and G. Silvetherg, (eds.)
London: Pinter.
Edge, D. 1992. Mosaic
arrays in infrared astronomy. In Invisible connections: Instruments,
institutions and science, edited by R. Bud and S. Cozzens. Bellingham, WA:
SPIE Optical Engineering Press.
Faulkner, W. 1986.
Linkage between industrial and academic research: The case of biotechnological
research in the pharmaceutical industry. D.Phil. Thesis, Science Policy
Research Unit, University of Sussex, Brighton.
_________ . 1989.
Industry-academic linkages in the case of biotechnology in the UK: Practice and
policy. Paper presented at ECPR workshop on Technology Transfer and
Techno-Industrial Innovation, 12-14 June, Como, Italy.
_______ . 1992.
Understanding industry-academic research linkage: Towards an appropriate
conceptualisation and methodology. Edinburgh PICI’ Working Paper no. 35.
Edinburgh: Research Centre for Social Sciences, University of Edinburgh.
Faulkner, W., J.
Senker, and L. Veiho. (1994). Knowledge frontiers: Industrial innovation and
public sector research in biotechnology, engineering ceramics and parallel
computing. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Fleck, J. 1988. The
development of information-integration: Beyond CIM? Edinburgh PICT Working Paper
no. 9. Edinburgh: Research Centre for Social Sciences, University of
Edinburgh.
______ . 1992.
Expertise: Knowledge, tradability and power. Paper presented at P1CT Workshop
on Exploring Expertise, November, Edinburgh.
______ . 1993.
Configuration: Crystallising contingency. International Journal of Human Factors
in Manufacturing, 3 (1): 15-36.
Fleck, J., and M.
Tierney. 1991. The management of expertise: Knowledge, power and the economics
of expert labour. Edinburgh PlCT Working Paper no. 29, Edinburgh:
Research Centre for Social Science, University of Edinburgh.
Fleck, J., Webster, J.,
and Williams, R. 1990. The dynamics of IT implementation: A reassessment of
paradigms and trajectories of development. Futures, 22 (6):618-40.
Fores, M. 1988.
Transformations and the myth of “engineering science”: Magic in a white coat. Technology
and Culture 29 (1): 62-81.
Freeman, C. 1982. The
economics of industrial innovation. 2nd ed. London: Pinter.
456
Gambardella, A. 1992.
Competitive advantages from in-house scientific research: The U.S.
pharmaceutical industry in the 1980s. Research Policy 21:391-407.
Gibbons, M., and C.
Johnson. 1982. Science, technology and the development of the transistor. In Science
in context: Readings in the sociology of science, edited by B. Barnes and
D. Edge, 177-85. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Gibbons, M., and R.
Johnston. 1974. The roles of science in technological innovation. Research
Policy 3 (3):220-42.
Gold, B. 1980. On the
adoption of technological innovations in industry: Superficial models and
complex decision processes. Omega 8 (5):505-16.
Granberg, A., and R.
Stankiewicz. 1978. The production of knowledge in technological fields. Research
Policy Studies Discussion Paper no. 122. Lund: Research Policy Institute.
Hicks, D., P. Isard,
and B. Martin. 1993. An analytical comparison of research in European and
Japanese corporations. Proceedings of the Kyoto Meeting of the R&D Dynamics
Network, May, Kyoto, Japan.
Illinois Institute of
Technology Research Institute. 1968. Technology in retrospect and critical
events in science; Final report to the National Science Foundation (NSF-C535).
Illinois: Illinois Institute of Technology Research Institute.
Latour, B. 1987. Science
in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through society. Milton
Keynes: Open University Press.
Layton, E. T. 1974.
Technology as knowledge. Technology and Culture 15 (1):31-41.
_________ . 1976.
American ideologies of science and engineering. Technology and Culture 17
(October):688-700.
________ . 1988.
Science as a form of action: The role of the engineering sciences. Technology
and Culture 29 (1):82-97.
Lieberman, M. B. 1978.
A literature citation study of science-technology coupling in electronics. Proceedings
of the IEEE 6(1):5-13.
Mayr, 0. 1982. The
science-technology relationship. In Science in context: Readings in the
sociology of science, edited by B. Barnes and D. Edge, 155-63. Milton
Keynes: Open University Press.
Metcalfe, J. S., and M.
Gibbons. 1989. Technology, variety and organisation: A systematic perspective
on the competitive process. In Research on technological innovation, management
and policy, edited by R. S. Rosenbloom and R. Bergelman. JAI.
Musson, A. E., and E.
Robinson. 1969. Science and technology in the industrial revolution. Manchester:
Manchester University Press.
Narmn, F, and E. Noma.
1985. Is technology becoming science? Scientometrics 7 (3-6): 369-8 1.
Nelson, R. 1959. The
simple economics of basic scientific research. Journal of Political Economy (June):297-306.
_______ . 1982. The
role of knowledge in R and D efficiency. Quarterly Journal of Economics 388:453-70.
Pavitt, K. 1984.
Sectoral patterns of technical change: Towards a taxonomy and a theory. Research
Policy 13(6):343-74.
______ . 1991. What
makes basic research economically useful? Research Policy 20:109-19.
Peláez, E. 1991. From
symbolic to numerical computing: The story of thinking machines. Edinburgh
PICT Working Paper no. 23. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh, Research
Centre for Social Sciences.
Polanyi, M. 1966. The
tacit dimension. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
457
Rosenberg, N. 1976. Perspectives
on technology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
__________ . 1984. The
science/technology relationship, the craft of experimental science, and policy
for the improvement of high technology innovation. Research Policy 13
(l):3-20.
__________ . 1982. Inside
the black box. Technology and economics. Cambridge: Cambridge Uniersity
Press.
__________ . 1990. Why
companies do basic research (with their own money)? Research Policy 19:
165-74.
__________ . 1992.
Scientific instrumentation and university research. Research Policy 21:381-90.
Rothwell, R. 1977. The
characteristics of successful innovators and technically progressive firms. R&D
Management 7 (3):191-206.
Rothwell, R., C.
Freeman, A. Horsley, V.T.P. Jervis, A. B. Robertson, and J. Townsend. 1974.
SAPPHO updated—project SAPPHO, phase II. Research Policy 3 (3):258.
Russell, S., and R.
Williams. 1988. Opening the black box and closing it behind you: On
micro-sociology in the social analysis of technology. Edinburgh PICT Working
Paper no. 3. Edinburgh, United Kingdom: University of Edinburgh, Research
Centre for Social Sciences.
Senker, J. 1993. The
contribution of tacit knowledge to innovation. AI and Society, (7):
208-24.
Senker, J., and W.
Faulkner. 1992. Industrial use of public sector research in advanced technologies:
A comparison of biotechnology and ceramics. R&D Management 22
(2):157-75.
_____________________ .
1993. Networks, tacit knowledge and innovation. Paper presented at ASEAT Conference
on Technology Collaboration: Networks, Institutions and States. Manchester:
University of Manchester Institute for Science and Technology (UMIST) and
Manchester University.
Sherwin, C. W., and R.
S. Isenson. 1967. Project Hindsight. Science 156:571-77.
Staudenmaier, J. M.
1985. Technology’s storytellers: Reweaving the human fabric. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Sørensen, K., and N.
Levold. 1992. Tacit networks, heterogeneous engineers, and embodied technology.
Science, Technology, and Human Values 17 (1):13-35.
Utterback, J. M. 1971.
The process of innovation: A study of the origination and development of ideas
from new scientific instruments. IEEE, Transactions on Engineering Management
18: 124.
Vincenti, W. 1991. What
engineers know and how they know it: Analytical studies from aeronautical
history. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
von Hippel, E. 1988. The
sources of innovation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Walsh, V. 1984.
Invention and innovation in the chemical industry: Demand-pull on
discovery-push. Research Policy 13 (4):211-34.
Walsh, V., R. Roy, M.
Bruce, and S. Potter. 1992. Winning by design: Technology, product design
and international competitiveness. Oxford: Blackwell.
Wildavsky, A. 1983.
Information as an organisational problem. Journal of Management Studies 20
(1):29-40.
Winter, S. 1987.
Knowledge and competence as strategic assets. In The competitive challenge: Strategies
for industrial innovation and renewal, edited by D. Teece, 159-83.
Cambridge, MA: Balhinger.
Wendy Faulkner trained in biology and, at the Science Policy Research
Unit, Sussex, in science and technology policy. She is now based in the Science
Studies Unit at the University of Edinburgh (Edinburgh EH8 9LN), where she
convenes a postgraduate program in Technology Studies. Her research has
explored various aspects of industrial innovation in both large and small firms.
She has also written on gender, science, and technology.
458
The Competitiveness of Nations
in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
April 2003