The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
The Labour Theory of Value: Economics or
Ethics?
Content | |
2.0
Petty’s two measures of value
3.0 Locke: labour as the origin of value.
4.0 Adam Smith’s labour theories of value.
4.1 The regulation of value in civil society
5.2 Exceptions, qualifications and modifications
5.3
Ricardo’s measure of value
5.5 Ricardo on the “toil” of the landlord and the fruits of capital |
6.2.
The value of commodities.
6.5 The so-called transformation problem. Discussion Paper 2002-2 September 2002
ISSN O831-439X Department of Economics
University of Saskatchewan |
The labour theory of value dominated the
research agenda of economics for more than two centuries, from at least the
time of Sir William Petty in the 1660’s until the 1870’s when Leon Walras,
Carl Menger and William Stanley Jevons established the marginal utility theory
of value. One generation of economists
after another struggled to explain the price of commodities by the labour
required to produce them, but nearly everybody saw errors in the work of their
predecessors. They wanted to keep the
labour theory, because they believed in the philosophical, moral or ethical
implications of it. Its powerful
appeal rests on the self-evident proposition that, when production is traced
back to its origin, all commodities can, in principle, be reduced to land and
labour. Since land is a free gift of
nature that costs no human effort to produce, it cannot explain value, though
it is the source of physical things. From
this perspective, capital goods are merely “past labour,” to quote, Sir
William Petty. John Locke turned this
conception into a theory of property rights. The
“political” agenda of political economy, whether it took the form of
liberalism or Marxism, rests on the moral principle that labour is entitled to
the fruits of its labour. As an
economic theory, however, it raised more problems than Adam Smith, David
Ricardo and Karl Marx could solve when they tried to explain market prices
with it.
The labour theory of value dominated the
research agenda of economics for over two centuries, from at least the time of
Sir William Petty in the 1660’s to the 1870’s when Leon Walras, Carl Menger
and William Stanley Jevons established the marginal utility theory of value.
One generation of economists after
another struggled to explain the price of commodities by the labour required
to produce them. This became the
paradigm of political economy, at least among British economists.
Nearly everybody criticized the
theory, however, because they saw errors in work their predecessors.
Adam Smith, David Ricardo and Karl
Marx all made significant modifications and introduced important exceptions to
the theory. They wanted to keep the
old theory and tried to correct the errors in it, because they believed in the
philosophical, moral or ethical implications of it.
The philosophical foundation of the labour
theory of value rests on a self-evident truth: all commodities are ultimately
produced by labour alone. All the
material things that exist on the face of the earth were originally free gifts
of nature. According to this
theory, things only have value when labour makes them useful to mankind,
including tools and machines, which can be used to make new things.
The labour employed to produce a
commodity today requires tools, materials and supplies made yesterday, which
in turn required labour to produce them beforehand, and so on retrospectively
back to the age of stone axes and flint knives.
From this perspective, all commodities
originally arose from mixing labour with the things of nature.
Petty tried to measure the value of
commodities by the land and labour used to produce them.
He treated capital goods as the
product of “past labour.” John Locke
turned this conception into a theory of property rights and established the
“political” agenda of classical political economy.
Whether classical economics took the
form of Liberalism or Marxism, it rests on the moral principle that people are
entitled to the fruits of their labour. [1]
The purpose of this paper is to show how the
ideas of Petty and Locke can be seen in the works of Adam Smith, David
Ricardo, and Karl Marx. It is not a
commentary on modem commentaries. Petty
may be taken as the starting point on the authority of Karl Marx, who wrote
“the founder of modern political economy is Sir William Petty, one of the most
gifted and original economic investigators.”
1
2.0 Petty’s two measures of value
Sir William Petty gave his economic speculations
an empirical foundation whenever possible. As
a medical doctor who served as professor of anatomy at Oxford, he approached
ecomnics from the natural science point of view.
He called it “Political Arithmetick,”
because he believed economic policy should be based on social statistics.
Petty (1899 [1676]: 244) acknowledged
his debt to Sir Francis Bacon and vowed to express himself “in Terms of
Number, Weight, or Measure; to use only arguments of Sense,
and to consider only such Causes, as have visible Foundations in Nature.”
He wanted to base his work on observed
reality, but the process of classifying observations requires abstract
concepts. Theory comes before the
collection of statistics and the analysis of data.
His economic theory commanded the attention of
his successors, because he asked questions about fundamental issues.
He identified the agents of production
as land, labour and capital, which he called stock; he constructed national
income and national wealth accounts for England and Wales for l665; [2] and he
considered the origin, measure and regulation of value to be distinct
concepts. His theory consisted of
little thought experiments, which often took the form of aphorisms or
parables.
For Petty, land and labour were the original
source of all commodities: “Labour is the Father and active principle of
Wealth, as Lands are the Mother (Petty, 1899 [1662]: 68).”
While the emphasis on land and labour
was not new, Petty turned it into a fundamental notion of classical economics.
Smith (1976 [1776]: 65), for example,
began his hypothetical economic history of the world in an “early and rude
state of society,” where land and labour were the only agents of production.
Petty (1899 [1664]: 110) defined
capital, or “what we call the Wealth, Stock, or Provision of the Nation,” as
“being the effect of former or past labour.”
J.K. Ingram (1893: 51) and Eric Roll (1956:
106-107), among other authorities, have found places where Petty seems to
explain the prices of commodities by the labour embodied in them. [3]
While Petty (1899
[1662]: 50) certainly stressed the role of labour in production, he did not
ignore land. In his parable of a man
trading silver from Peru for corn in England, for example, he appears to
define the natural price of commodities by the labour embodied in them: “If a
man can bring to London an ounce of Silver out of the Earth of Peru,
in the same time that he can produce a bushel of Corn, then one is the
natural price of the other.” This
statement appeared, however, in the context of trying to measure the value of
rent paid in corn by its value in money.
Earlier he had set up a little thought experiment to explain what determines the rent of land in terms of corn:
Suppose a man could with his own hands plant a
certain scope of Land with Corn, that is, could Digg, or Plough, Harrow, Weed,
Reap, Carry home, Thresh, and Winnow so much as the Husbandry of this Land
requires; and had withal Seed wherewith to sowe the same.
2
I say, that when this man hath subducted his
seed out of the proceed of his Harvest, and also, what himself hath both eaten
and given to others in exchange for Clothes, and other Natural necessaries;
that the remainder of Corn is the natural and true Rent Of the Land for that
year (Petty, 1899 [1662]: 43).
Then he asked, “how much English money this Corn
or Rent is worth?”
I answer, so much as the money, which another
single man can save, within the same time, over and above his expence, if he
imployed himself wholly to produce and make it; viz.
Let another man go travel into a
Countrey where is Silver, there Dig it, Refine it, bring it to the same place
where the other man planted his Corn; Coyne it, &c. the same person, all the
while of his working for Silver, gathering also food for his necessary
livelihood, and procuring himself covering, &c.
I say, the Silver of the one, must be esteemed of equal value with the
Corn of the other: the one being perhaps twenty Ounces and the other twenty
Bushels. From whence it follows,
that the price of a Bushel of this Corn to be an Ounce of Silver (Petty, 1899
1662]: 43).
Clearly, the production of corn has requires two
agents: labour and land. The value of
the corn includes both the subsistence of labour and the rent of land. The
silver mine also produced a surplus of 20 ounces over the subsistence of the
miner. The market prices of silver and
corn are regulated by the wages of labour plus a surplus of silver or corn
attributable to nature, whereas in a pure labour theory of value labour alone
regulates values. The subsistence of
the labourer is Petty’s (1899 [1672]: 181) proxy for his labour measure of
value.
The parable of silver and corn was intended to
explain how all things could be measured by either land or labour.
Indeed, Petty’s (1899 [1662]: 13, 49)
table of contents labeled this section “The Par between food or other proceed
of land, and Bullion or Coin;” and, after finishing the parable, Petty called
it “our digression upon the measures of Rents and Values of Lands and Moneys.”
Since value comes from two sources,
Petty (1899 [1662]: 44) thought that it should be measured in two ways: “All
things ought to be valued by two natural Denominations, which is Land and
Labour; that is, we ought to say, a Ship or a garment is worth such a measure
of Land, with such another measure of Labour; forasmuch as both Ships and
Garments were creatures of Lands and mens Labours thereupon”
The claim that both land and labour
create the value of ships and garments entails a theory of the origin of
value, a theory which explains how things become valuable.
The two natural denominations of value
also denote a theory of the measure of value, a theory which explains how to
compare the value of things. The two
measures of value follow logically from the double origin of value.
In The Politica1 Anatomy of Ireland Petty
explains his two measures of value in his parable of the calf.
After the calf is fattened in a field
without the assistance of labour, Petty asked how much food a man could grow
on the same field. The wages of the
workman consist in the excess value of his crop over the increase in the value
of the calf. The two values could,
thus, be measured and compared.
Petty (1899 [1672]: 181) emphasized this double measure of value,
3
for he introduced the parable of the calf by
saying “this brings me to the most important Consideration in Political
Oeconomies, viz, how to make a Par and Equation between
Lands and Labour, so as to express the Value of any thing by either alone”
The measure of value is distinct from
the origin of value and regulation of value. The
origin of value concerns why things have value in principle and in the
abstract, the regulation of value explains what determines market prices.
Petty left these three concepts for
his classical successors to develop.
3.0 Locke: labour as the
origin of value.
John Locke presented nearly all his economic
ideas in two publications: Two Treatises of Government and
Some Considerations of the consequences of the Lowering of interest, and
Raising the Value of Money. As
their titles indicate, they are not primarily concerned with the labour theory
of value. The Two Treatises
deals with political philosophy. Economic
matters arise in connection with the principles of justice, where Locke traced
property rights to the labour spent on the production of things.
Some Considerations is a
political tract on monetary policy, in which he argued that Parliament should
not reduce the rate of interest. While
Locke never wrote a monograph on value theory as such, he directly and
obviously influenced the philosophical foundation and the analytical
perspective of classical economics.
Locke’s (1967 [1690]: 287-88) theory of property
rights begins in a hypothetical state of nature, where men hold the gifts of
nature in common.
Though the Earth, and all inferior Creatures be
common to all Men, yet every Man has a Property in his own Person.
This no Body has any Right to but
himself. The Labour of his
Body, and the Work of his Hands, we may say, are properly his.
Whatsoever then he removes out of the
State that Nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his Labour
with, and joyned to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his
Property. It being by him
removed from the common state Nature placed it in, it hath by this Labour
something annexed to it, that excludes the common right of other Men.
For this Labour being the
unquestionable Property of the Labourer, no Man but he can have a right to
what that is once joyned to, at least where there is enough, and as good left
in common for others.
Thus, while all the material things of this
world began as the common property of all mankind, they become the private
property of the individuals who appropriated them. [4]
His economic theory improved upon Petty by more
clearly distinguishing between the origin, the measure and the regulation of
value. (1) His theory of the origin or
source of value comes out of his theory of property rights.
It explains how labour produces most
of the value of useful things, which is the philosophical foundation of
classical economics. (2) His measure
of value is more practical than theoretical, for it concerns protecting fixed
incomes like rent against a decline in the value of money, that is, against
inflation. (3) When he turned to the
regulation of value, however, he abandon the labour theory of value and
presented what is often called a
4
supply and demand theory.
These three concepts - the origin,
measure and regulation of value - were discussed by all the important
classical and early neoclassical economists. [5]
A.C. Whitaker (1968
[1904]) has correctly observed in his History and Criticism of the Labor
Theory of Value in English Political Economy that these concepts are the
“key” to understanding the labour theory of value.
First, the theories of the origin of value
presented by Petty and by Locke were similar, but they served different
purposes. Petty wanted to trace the
value of things back to the land and labour embodied in them, so that he could
measure value by its two natural dimensions. He
got rid of capital by supposing that it was merely the past labour embodied in
the accumulated stock of things. Locke
(1967 [1690]: 298) also traces the value of commodities back to a state of
nature.
For ‘tis not barely the Plough-man’s Pains, the
Reaper’s and Thresher’s Toil, and the Bakers Sweat, is to be counted into the
Bread we eat; the Labour of those who broke the Oxen, who digged
and wrought the Iron and Stones, who felled and framed the Timber imployed
about the Plough, Mill, Oven, or any other Utensils, which are a vast Number,
requisite to this Corn from its being seed to be sown to its being made Bread,
must all be charged on the account of Labour, and received as an
effect of that: Nature and the Earth furnished only the almost worthless
Materials, as in themselves. ‘Twould
be a strange catalogue of things, that industry provided and made use of
about every Loaf of Bread before it came to our use, if we could trace
them; Iron, Wood, Leather, Bark, Timber, Stone, Bricks, Coals, Lime. Cloth,
Dying-Drugs, Pitch, Tar, Masts, Ropes, and all the Materials made use of in
the Ship, that brought any of the Commodities made use of by any of the
Workmen, to any part of the Work, all which, ‘twould be almost impossible, at
least too long, to reckon up.
This notion, which accounts for what Petty
called “past labour,” is repeated in one form or another by Adam Smith, David
Ricardo, Karl Marx, and most other classical economists.
His seemingly innocent comment that
all of which “would be almost impossible, at least too long, to reckon up” is
the Achilles heel of any empirical labour theory of value: The past labour
embodied in the production of things today cannot be known.
While Locke (1967 [1690]: 298) attributes value
to both land and labour like Petty, he gives a much greater emphasis to labour,
because labour “puts the greatest part of the Value upon Land,
without which it would scarcely be worth any thing.”
I think it will be but a very modest Computation
to say, that of the Products of the Earths useful to the Life of
Man 9/10 are the effects of Labour: nay, if we will rightly estimate
things as they come to our use, and cast up the several Expences about them,
what in them is purely owing to Nature, and what to labour, we
shall find, that in most of them 99/100 are wholly to be put on the account of
labour (Locke, 1967 [1690]: 296).
5
This may be called a 99 percent labour theory of
value. How Locke made this very modest
calculation is not at all clear, because all labour required to produce
anything going back to an original state of nature “would be almost
impossible, at least too long, to reckon up.”
Second, the practical importance of measuring
values for Locke arose from the problem of inflation, which he described as a
fall in the value of money. Gold and
silver declined in value after the discovery of America, and coins fell
further with the debasement of their gold and silver content.
Since landlords often rented their
land for a tenant’s life, sometimes for many lives, the real value of their
rental income declined when it was fixed in terms of money.
It was, therefore, sensible to find an
invariable measure of value.
A measure of value is a commodity or bundle of
commodities by which we reckon the value of other things.
Any commodity could serve as a measure
of value, here and now, in a particular market, because equal values are given
in exchange; but things are usually given in exchange for money, so that
people customarily think of prices in terms of money.
Money, as Locke (1991 [1692]: 248)
observed, “is the universal measure by which people reckon, and is used by
every body in the valuing of all Things.”
Money is not a steady or unalterable measure of
value, however, because money and every other commodity change in value over
time. No two commodities ever
exchange at the same fixed ratio year after year.
Locke (I99l [1692]: 264) asked, does a commodity exist that has a fixed
absolute value? He answered,
money would be such a commodity,
if in any country they use for Money any lasting
Material, whereof there is not any more to be got, and so cannot be increas’d;
or being of no other use, the rest of the World does not value it, and so it
would not like to be diminished; this also would be a steady standing Measure
of the Value of other Commodities.
This apparently means that a commodity would be
a perfect measure of value if the quantity of it never changed.
But, even if neither the supply of it
nor the demand for it ever changed, the value of all other commodities may
change relative to it, in which ease it would be impossible to determine
whether its value remained constant. The
quest for an invariable measure of value became a common theme of classical
economics. Locke (1991 [1692]:
265) reached the right practical conclusion: “it is impossible to have any
standing, unalterable measure of the value of things.”
Third, Locke explains the regulation of
commodity prices with his “Laws of Value,” which apply to the market period
when the commodities brought to market have already been produced.
Since the quantity supplied is
previously given, the cost of production is a bygone and irrelevant to current
prices. Its value depends on supply
and demand, as the following sketch makes clear:
6
For a Farmer that carries a Bushel of Wheat to
Market, and a Labourer that carries a Half a Crown, shall find that the Money
of the one, as well as the Corn of the other, shall at some times purchase him
more or less Leather or Salt, according as they are in greater Plenty and
Scarcity one to another (Locke, 1991 [1692]: 249).
Locke’s marketable value is Smith’s market
price, the price at which a commodity actually sells.
The whole quantity is evidently offered for sale, perhaps with a
reservation price. While Karen Vaughn
(1980: 21) has criticized Locke for his treatment of supply and called it
“scanty,” which is certainly true, the theory of price for the market period
in Smith, Ricardo, Alfred Marshall and Phillip Wicksteed, among others,
follows the picture sketched by Locke.
Locke did not develop his supply and demand
analysis beyond the market period. While
he noted that farmers adjust their production to demand, he did not have a
long run, competitive, cost of production theory of the natural price.
The farmer has already produced the
wheat when he comes to market, and he sells it for whatever it will fetch.
Locke (1991 [1692]: 259, 237, 328)
understood that where goods are neither engrossed nor monopolized, but are
exposed to “free” trade, the “true market-price” is established in the same
way as weights find their “aequilibrium” on a scale.
4.0 Adam Smith’s labour
theories of value.
Adam Smith (1976 [1776]: 10) began the
Wealth of Nations with the bold assertion that national wealth is due to
labour. The first sentence of the book
states:
The annual labour of every nation is the fund
which originally supplies it with all the necessaries and conveniencies of
life which it annually consumes, and which consist always either in the
immediate produce of that labour, or in what is purchased with that produce
from other nations.
This passage establishes two points.
First, Smith claims that the annual
labour produces the annual consumption of the nation.
This is true in civil society as well
as primitive society, since international trade only occurs in civil society.
The omission of land and capital is
striking, especially in such a celebrated book on capitalism.
Aside from “the spontaneous
productions of the earth,” which Locke (1967 [1690]: 294-5) also mentioned,
Smith (1976 [1776]: 332) treated land as productive only when labour worked it
or gathered things from it. Land
provides the physical things used in production as free gifts of nature.
Second, Smith defines the wealth or
welfare of the nation in terms of consumption.
Elsewhere Smith (1976 [1776]: 660) wrote: “Consumption is the sole end
and purpose of all production.”
7
Capital goods are simply “past labour,” to use
Petty’s expression, as Smith (1976 [1776]: 330) illustrated in his discussion
of productive and unproductive labour:
the labour of the manufacturer fixes and
realizes itself in some particular subject or vendible commodity, which lasts
for some time at least after that labour is past.
t'is, as it were, a certain quantity
of labour stocked and stored up to be employed, if necessary, upon some other
occasion.
Productive labour adds value to physical things
which survive the period of production, whether they are acquired by consumers
or producers. Te analytic significance
of productive labour arises from the fact that only productive labour produces
capital goods, as the title of the chapter implies: “Of the Accumulation of
Capital, or of productive and unproductive Labour.”
Capital accumulation indirectly
increases thee wealth of nations, because it extends the division of labour;
but capital itself is simply so much crystallized or congealed labour-time.
Capital is not an original factor of
production; it is accumulated labour
Smith (1976 [1776]: 65) also presented a pure
labour theory of value-in-exchange, but it only applied in a Lockean state of
nature.
In that early and rude state of society which
precedes both the accumulation of stock and the appropriation of land, the
proportion between the quantities of labour necessary for acquiring different
objects seems to be the only circumstance which can afford any rule for
exchanging them for one another. If
among a nation of hunters, for example, it usually coats twice the labour to
kill a beaver which it does to kill a deer, one beaver should naturally
exchange for or be worth two deer. It
is natural that what is usually the produce of two days or two hours labour,
should be worth double of what is usually the produce of one day’s or one
hour’s labour.
In this state of things, Smith (1976 [1776]: 65)
explained “the whole produce of labour belongs to the labourer.
He has neither landlord nor master to
share with him.” The whole produce is
due to labour, as in Locke’s theory of property rights, which Smith (1976
[1776]: 138) endorsed: “The property which every man has in his own labour, as
it is the original foundation of all other property, so it is the most sacred
and inviolable.”
4.1 The regulation of
value in civil society
When Smith turned to civil society, where
capital is accumulated and land is appropriated, his labour theory of value
broke down as an explanation of market prices. [6]
The whole produce of
labour is then divided between three social classes: labourers, landlords and
capitalists. With the accumulation of
capital comes the profits of stock, which Smith (1976 [1776): 67) explained as
follows:
8
In this state of things, the whole produce of
labour does not always belong to the labourer.
He must in most cases share it with the owner of the stock which
employs him. Neither is the quantity
of labour commonly employed in acquiring or producing any commodity, the only
circumstance which can regulate the quantity which it ought commonly to
purchase, command, or exchange for. An
additional quantity, it is evident, must be due for the profits of the stock
which advanced the wages and furnished the materials of that labour.
With the appropriation of land, Smith (1976
[1776]: 67) continued, comes the rent of the landlord:
As soon as the land of any country has all
become private property, the landlords, like all other men, love to reap where
they never sowed, and demand a rent even for its natural produce.
The wood of the forest, the grass of
the field, and all the natural fruits of the earth, which, when land was in
common, cost the labourer only the trouble of gathering them, come, even to
him, to have an additional price fixed upon them.
He must give up to the landlords
portion of what his labour either collects or produces.
This portion, or, what comes to the
same thing, the price of this portion, constitutes the rent of land, and in
the price of the greater part of commodities makes a third component part
In civil society, prices have three component
parts: wages, profit and rent. Smith
continued to argue, however, that all production was due to labour, that
labour was the origin of value. He
only abandoned the notion that labour regulates value in civil society, that
it determines market prices. He even
developed an elaborate theory of labour as a measure of value.
The theory of market prices presented by Smith
involves three distinct periods of time: (1) a temporary period, like Locke’s
theory, where market prices are determined by supply and demand; (2) a long
period, where competition reallocates land, labour and capital among various
commodities until the market price equals the cost of production, which is the
“natural price” of a commodity; and (3) a secular period, where the
accumulation of capital and the growth of population regulate the cost of
production and the “natural price.” “The
natural price,” Smith (1976 [1776]: 75) explained, “is, as it were, the
central price, to which the prices of all commodities are continually
gravitating.”
The proportions of land, labour and capital that
are employed in a country ultimately determine the natural rates of wages,
profit and rent. As a country
progresses, capital accumulates and population grows, while land is constant,
so that factor proportions of change. Therefore,
the natural rates of wages, profit and rent also tend to change, which causes
the relative value of commodities that are produced with different proportions
of land, labour and capital to vary.
9
Smith’s Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of
the Wealth of Nations required him to measure the value of
production so that he could compare the wealth of different nations.
He considered gold, silver and corn as
measures of value, but concluded that they fluctuated in value overtime.
To get around this problem, Smith
(1976 [1776]: 50) asserted that the sacrifice of the labourer is constant.
Equal quantities of labour, at all times and
places, may be said lobe of equal value to the labourer.
In his ordinary state of health,
strength and spirits; in the ordinary degree of his skill and dexterity, he
must always lay down the same portion of his ease, his liberty, and his
happiness. The price which he pays
must always be the same, whatever may be the quantity of goods which he
receives in return for it. Of these,
indeed, it may sometimes purchase a greater and sometimes a smaller quantity;
but it is their value which varies, not that of the labour which purchases
them. At all times and places that is
dear which it is difficult to come at, or which it costs much labour to
acquire; and that cheap which is to be had easily, or with very little labour.
Labour alone, therefore, never varying
in its own value, is alone the ultimate and real standard by which the value
of all commodities can at all times and places be estimated and compared.
It is their real price; money is their
nominal price only.
He made labour his universal measure of value on
the assumption that the sacrifice of labour is an absolute value that does not
vary over time or space. He assumed
that labourers are homogeneous and make the same sacrifice for any given type
of work at all times and places. Thus,
labour sacrifice is his measure of the wealth of nations.
It is his real price of commodities.
[7]
Smith’s real price of commodities is his labour
command theory of value. It is based
on his theory of the origin of value, for it supposes that labour and labour
alone produces all value. An
individual who exchanges one commodity for another commodity is, according to
Smith (1976 [1776]: 47), exchanging one quantity of labour for another.
The value of any commodity, therefore, to the
person who possesses it, and who means not to use or consume it himself, but
to exchange it for other commodities, is equal to the quantity of labour which
it enables him to purchase or command. Labour,
therefore, is the real measure of the exchangeable value of all commodities.
Similarly, the wealth of any individual can be
measured by the quantity of labour that he can command, which, Smith (1976
[1776]: 48) wrote, is the same thing as the total output that he can command.
His fortune is greater or less, precisely in
proportion to the extent of this power; or to the quantity either of other
men’s labour, or, what is the same thing, of the produce of other men’s labour,
which it enables him to purchase or command.
10
What is the same thing?
The quantity of labour and the produce
of labour are the same thing because labour is the sole value-creating
substance. The real price of
commodities, Smith’s labour-command measure of value, is output per unit of
labour sacrifice.
Smith (1976 [1776]: 51) confused many of his
readers, however, because he also used the wages or subsistence of labour as a
measure of value, which he called the real price of labour.
In this popular sense, therefore, labour, like
commodities, may be said to have a real and a nominal price.
Its real price may be said to consist
in thequantity of the necessaries and conveniencies of life which are given
for it; its nominal price, in the quantity of money.
The subsistence of the labourer cannot measure
the wealth of nations, because it excludes the goods consumed by the landlords
and capitalists. It measures the
wealth of labourers only. [8]
The rent of land is paid for the use of the free
gifts of nature, and those free gifts are inherently heterogeneous and limited
in quantity. Rent, therefore, is
partly determined by the fertility or locality of a tract of land and partly
determined by the advancing, stationary or declining state of society.
As society progresses, Smith argued
(1976 [1776]: 162) that the natural rent of land is price determined, not
price determining.
High or low wages and profit, are the causes of
high or low price; high or low rent is the effect of it.
It is because high or low wages and
profit must be paid, in order to bring a particular commodity to market, that
its price is high or low. But it is
because its price is high or low; a great deal more, or very little more, or
no more, than what is sufficient to pay those wages and profit, that it
affords a high rent, or a low rent, or no rent at all.
As population grows and the demand for food
increases, land becomes increasingly scarce; and the rent of land naturally
tends to rise in all its alternative uses. Corn
land must compete with pasture land and pasture land with forest land.
A man will not plant a forest unless
his harvest of trees promises him as large a rent as the cattle and corn he
must forgo. All rents tend to rise
together. In this case, rent is a
surplus, not a cost of production.
If the market price of a particular crop, such
as barley, should fall below its natural price, however, the rent of that land
will tend to fall below its natural rate. In
this case, Smith (1976 [1776]: 75) explained that rent is a cost of
production, so that “the interest of the landlords will immediately prompt
them to withdraw a part of their land.”
The alternative uses of land make rent a cost of production in each
alternative use, not only to the farmer, but also to society. [9]
Smith did not, perhaps, fully and distinctly formulate his theory of rent, for
Ricardo and others apparently did not understand it.
11
As a moral philosopher, Smith must have been
uncomfortable with the inherent contradiction presented by civil society.
Once land is appropriated and capital
accumulated, “the whole produce of labour does not always belong to the
labourer;” yet, Smith (1976 [1776]: 138) still maintained the moral principle
that “the property which every man has in his own labour, as it is the
original foundation of all other property, so it is the most sacred and
inviolable.” To some extent, his
policy prescriptions on taxation ameliorate this contradiction.
In his theory of the incidence of taxation,
Smith (1976 [1776]: 848) contended that a tax on rent or on profit would not
affect production, provided that the tax on rent applied to all the
alternative uses of land and that the tax on profit applied to only the
interest on capital, excluding any premium that may be necessary to induce the
capitalist to enter risky or disagreeable occupations.
As a tax upon the rent of land cannot raise
rents; because the neat produce which remains after replacing the stock of the
farmer, together with his reasonable profit, cannot be greater after the tax
than before it: so, for the same reason, a tax upon the interest of money
could not raise the rate of interest; the quantity of stock or money in the
country, like the quantity of land, being supposed to remain the same after
the tax as before it.
This is consistent with his theory of rent,
where “high or low wages and profit, are the causes of high or low price; high
or low rent is the effect of it;” but not his theory of growth, where capital
accumulation stops when profits fall too low.
A general tax on the rent of land does not
affect the price of food, because rent is a surplus which costs no effort to
produce. It falls wholly on the
landlord. A particular tax, such as a
tax on barley land, however, would reduce the quantity of land planted in
barley and raise the price of barley until that land yielded the same rent it
would in any other crop. Smith praised
the land-tax of Great Britain, which was assessed according to a fixed
standard that did not vary with the rent of land.
A landlord who improved his land could keep the revenue derived from
the improvements. Such a tax, wrote
Smith (1976 [1776]: 828-29) “as it has no tendency to diminish the quantity,
it can have none to raise the price of that produce.
It does not obstruct the industry of
the people. It subjects the landlord
to no other inconveniency besides the unavoidable one of paying the tax.”
Smith (1976 [1776]: 847-49) divided profits into
three parts: pure interest, a premium for risky employments, and a premium for
disagreeable employments of capital (or discount for agreeable employments).
A tax that reduced the return to
either risky or disagreeable employments would divert capital to other
employments. It would reduce the
output of such industries and raise the price of their products until
investment in them would be as attractive as their alternatives, so that the
tax would ultimately be paid by the consumer.
A tax on the pure interest of a previously accumulated stock of
capital is more like a tax on a fixed quantity of land.
It is a tax on a surplus, but Smith
recommended against such a tax on practical grounds.
12
As a practical matter, capital is commonly
concealed, so that a tax on capital would be difficult to assess.
Furthermore, unlike land, capital can
be removed from the country, if taxes are too high.
Most classical economists accepted the policy of
taxing the rent of land. Ricardo
presented so rigorous a restatement of Smith’s theory that even neoclassical
economists like Walras and Marshall agreed with much of it, despite all the
criticisms of it. Their position reflects the notion that land is a free gift
of nature that costs no effort to produce. Rent
tends to rise as society progresses without any effort or sacrifice by the
landlord. Therefore it could be taxed
away without affecting production. A
tax on pure profits proved less appealing since it may reduce the rate of
saving and retard capital accumulation. Smith’s
theory of this incidence of taxation is consistent his principle of justice.
If rent and pure profit were taxed
away, labour would receive the value of what it creates in civil society just
as it would in a Lockean state of nature.
David Ricardo accepted the general framework
presented by Adam Smith. He
believed that society was divided into three classes: labourers, capitalists
and landlords. The principal problem
of political economy for Ricardo was to determine the laws which regulate the
distribution of income among these classes in the form of wages, profit and
rent. As capital accumulates and as
population grows the income allotted to the different classes changes.
Before he turned to the question of
income distribution, however, he sought to correct and rehabilitate the labour
theory of value presented by Adam Smith.
Ricardo quoted and endorsed Smith’s (1976
[1776]: 65) example of the beaver and the deer, where “the proportion between
the quantities of labour necessary for acquiring different objects seems to be
the only circumstance which can afford any rule for exchanging them for one
another.” Whereas Smith restricted his
labour theory of value to a primitive society which precedes the accumulation
of capital and the appropriation of land, Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 24-25) sought
to apply it to civil society where income is divided among wages, profit, and
rent:
If we look to a state of society in which
greater improvements have been made, and in which arts and commerce flourish,
we shall still find that commodities vary in value conformably with this
principle: in estimating the exchangeable value of stockings, for example, we
shall find that their value, comparatively with other things, depends on the
total quantity of labour necessary to manufacture them, and bring them to
market.
Even though he alludes to the metaphysical
concept of labour as the origin of value, he was not much interested in such
philosophical abstractions. His theory
focused on the regulation and measurement of market prices.
Ricardo (1951 [1821]:l3) wanted to
explain the empirical phenomenon of value-in-exchange with a logically
consistent theory that was based on the
13
doctrine that labour “is really the foundation
of the exchangeable value of all things, excepting those which cannot be
increased by human industry,”
5.2 Exceptions,
qualifications and modifications
This ambitious agenda soon led him into a long
series of exceptions, qualifications and modifications to his theory, which
take up most of Chapter 1 “On Value” in the third edition of his Principles
of Political Economy and Taxation.
First, he noted where commodities are naturally
scarce or artificially monopolized, their values are unrelated to the labour
required to produce them, so he treated them as exceptions to his theory and
explained their value by scarcity. His
labour theory of value only applies to newly produced goods that are sold in
competitive markets,
Second, Ricardo (1951 [18211: 12) qualified both
the scarcity and labour theories of value by stating that an article must be
useful before it can be valuable: “Possessing utility, commodities derive
their exchangeable value from two sources: from their scarcity, and from time
quantity of labour required to obtain them.”
Third, he took account of the fact that
labourers are not all identical. Some
types of labour are more productive than others and, for that reason, they are
paid higher wages than others.
In speaking, however, of labour, as being the
foundation of all value, and the relative quantity of labour as almost
exclusively determining the relative value of commodities, I must not be
supposed to be inattentive to the different qualities of labour, and the
difficulty of comparing an hour’s or a day’s labour, in one employment, with
the same duration of labour in another. The
estimation in which different qualities of labour are held, comes soon to be
adjusted in the market with sufficient precision for all practical purposes,
and depends much on the comparative skill of the labourer, and intensity of
the labour performed. The scale, when
once formed, is liable to little variation. (Ricardo, 1951 [1821]: 20).
Adam Smith reached the same conclusion in his
chapter on the inequality of wages, but Ricardo did not follow Smith, who had
assumed that labour is homogeneous which means that all labourers have the
same innate abilities and preferences for different occupations.
Ricardo used the market wages of labour to measure the quantity of
labour embodied in any commodity. Labour
only contributes to the value of commodities in proportion to the market wages
paid to labour. This proposition
undercuts the notion that values are determined by labour-time.
As Ricardo unraveled the logic of his
theory, the role that relative wages govern relative values did not survived
to the end of Chapter 1.
14
Fourth, the quantity of labour employed in
production includes not only current labour, but also “past labour,” to repeat
Petty’s phrase. In a passage
reminiscent of Locke, Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 24) traces the value of stockings
back to all the things that were necessary to manufacture them and bring them
to market.
First, there is the labour necessary to
cultivate the land on which the raw cotton is grown; secondly, the labour of
conveying the cotton to the country where the stockings are to be
manufactured, which includes a portion of the labour bestowed in building the
ship in which it is conveyed, and which is charged in the freight of the
goods; thirdly, the labour of the spinner and weaver; fourthly, a portion of
the labour of the engineer, smith, and carpenter, who erected the buildings
and machinery, by the help of which they are made; fifthly, the labour of the
retail dealer, and of many others, whom it is unnecessary further to
particularize. The aggregate sum of
these various kinds of labour, determines the quantity of other things for
which these stockings will exchange, while the same consideration of the
various quantities of labour which have been bestowed on those other things,
will equally govern the portion of them which will be given for the stockings.
If Ricardo had continued this retrospective
rationalization of the quantity of labour bestowed on the production of the
things used to manufacture stockings, he would have found it necessary to
particularize a catalogue that “would be almost impossible, at least too long,
to reckon up,” to quote John Locke (1967 [1690]: 298) again.
The list would carry him back to early
times.
Fifth, while Ricardo repeatedly stated that the
value of commodities is almost exclusively attributable to labour, he thought
the capital also regulated the value of commodities.
Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 23) made this clear in his criticism of Adam
Smith example of the beaver and the deer.
Without some weapon, neither the beaver nor the
deer could be destroyed, and therefore the value of these animals would be
regulated, not solely by the time and labour necessary to their destruction,
but also by the time and labour necessary for providing the hunter’s capital,
the weapon, by the aid of which their destruction was effected.
This section bears the heading “Not only the
labour applied immediately to commodities affect their value, but the labour
also which is bestowed on the implements, tools, and buildings, with which
such labour is assisted.” Since both
current and past labour contribute to the production of commodities, they both
affect the value of commodities.
Sixth, the value of commodities is, therefore,
regulated by labour and capital. While
wages and profits are both component parts of price, Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 46)
explained that the relative value of different commodities is governed by the
relative amounts paid to labour alone.
15
It is necessary for me also to remark, that I
have not said, because one commodity has so much labour bestowed upon it as
will cost £1000 and another so much as will cost £200t that therefore one
would be of the value of~l000 and the other of time value of £2000 but I have
said that their value will be to each other as two to one, and that in those
proportions they will be exchanged. It
is of no importance to the truth of this doctrine, whether one of these
commodities sells for £1,100 and the other for £2,200, or one for £1,500 and
the other for £3000; into that question I do not at present enquire; I affirm
only, that their relative values will be governed by the relative quantities
of labour bestowed on their production.
By this rule, Ricardo could justly be accused of
having a capital theory of value, since commodities would also exchange in
proportion to the relative profits included in the price of different
commodities.
Seventh and finally, relative values will only
be proportional to the labour employed in production, if wages always
accounted for the same percentage of the price of every commodity; but, this
would only be true if the proportions of labour and capital are the same in
every industry. Ricardo recognized
that this is not the case. Some
industries are more capital intensive than others and some commodities take
longer to bring to market than others. This
required Rieardo (1951 [1821]: 37) to introduce “a considerable modification
to the rule, which is of universal application when labour is almost
exclusively employed in production; namely, that commodities never vary in
value, unless a greater or less quantity of labour he bestowed on their
production.” Commodities produced in
more capital intensive industries, like steel making, and those that require a
longer time to bring to market, like well-aged wine, are more valuable than
other commodities, even though the same quantity of labour may be employed in
their production. “The difference in
value,” Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 37) explained, “arises in both cases from the
profits being accumulated as capital, and is only a just compensation for the
time that the profits were withheld.” Profits
accumulate like compound interest as time passes, which increases the value of
commodities. Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 37)
illustrated this principle with a numerical example, which he introduced with
the following statement: “It is hardly necessary to say, that commodities
which have same quantity of labour bestowed on their production, will differ
in exchangeable value, if they cannot be brought to market in the same time.”
Thus, his own logic forced Ricardo to
abandon the labour theory of value, though it appears that at first he
believed in it. He ended up with two
component parts of price, where Adam Smith had three.
5.3
Ricardo’s measure of value
Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 43) criticized Smith’s
universal measure of value on the grounds that “there is no commodity which is
not itself exposed to the same variations as the things, the value of which is
to be ascertained; that is, there is none which is not subject to require more
or less labour for its production.” The
perfect measure of value for Smith, however, was the sacrifice, toil and
trouble, pain, disutility or leisure foregone of labour, not some commodity
with a constant quantity of labour embodied in it.
Smith rendered the sacrifice of labour
constant by assumption. For Ricardo, a
perfect measure of value would always require the same quantity of
16
labour to produce it.
Even if there were such a commodity,
Ricardo argued, it would not be a perfect measure of the value of other
commodities that did not have the same capital structure or that could not be
brought to market in the same time. If
wages rose and profits fell, the value of commodities produced in capital
intensive industries would fall relative to other commodities.
For the sake of exposition, Ricardo (1951
[1821]: 45-46) assumed that gold had a constant quantity of labour embodied it
and that it was produced under average conditions.
It fit “nearly equal distant from the
two extremes, the one where little fixed capital is used, the other where
little labour is employed.” Thus, if
wages rose and profits fell, all commodities produced with more labour
intensive metlhods would rise in value, while those produced under more
capital intensive conditions would fall. Gold
may, therefore, be considered stationary. [10]
Ricardo accepted the view that in a Lockean
state of nature before the appropriation of land, the produce of the earth was
a free gift of nature. Land was held
in common, and natural products cost only the trouble of gathering it or
catching it. There was no rent.
As society progresses and population
grows, land becomes increasingly scarce. First
the best land and then inferior lands come to be private property; and
landlords can begin to demand a rent. For
Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 67], “rent is that portion of the produce of the earth,
which is paid to the landlord for the use of the original and indestructible
powers of the soil.” It is distinct
from the popular use of the word, which includes whatever is paid for the use
of buildings, fences and other improvement to land.
Improvements are capital investments,
which earn profits.
As inferior lands come to be cultivated, rent
arises on all the superior lands, because they yield larger crops than the
inferior lands. If often happens that
before inferior lands are brought into production, Ricardo (1951 [18211: 71)
explained, “capital will be preferably employed on the old land, and will
equally create a rent, because rent is always the difference between the
produce obtained by the employment of two equal quantities of capital and
labour.” As society progresses,
therefore, the tendency is for landlords to claim a growing proportion of the
national product.
As more capital and labour are employed on old
land and more new land is cultivated, the extra output (or marginal product)
of each additional dose of labour and capital is smaller, so that more labour
and capital are required to produce an extra bushel of corn.
This raises the cost of production on
both the intensive margin of cultivation on old land and the extensive margin
of cultivation on new land. As a
consequence, the price of food rises, which Ricardo (1951 [1821]: 74) explains
in a passage that echoes Smith.
The reason then, why raw produce rises in
comparative value, is because more labour is employed in the production of the
last portion obtained, and not because a rent is paid to the landlord.
The value of corn is regulated by the
quantity of labour bestowed on its production on that quality of land, or with
that portion of capital, which pays no rent. Corn
is not high because a rent is paid, but a rent is paid because corn is high;
and it has
17
been justly observed, that no reduction would
take place in the price of corn, although landlords should forego the whole of
their rent. Such a measure would only
enable some farmers to live like gentlemen, but would not diminish the
quantity of labour necessary to raise raw produce on the least productive land
in cultivation.
On the margin of cultivation, the price of food
is regulated by the wages of labour and the profit of capital.
In this way, Ricardo got rid of rent.
Rent is not a component part of price.
It could all be taxed away without affecting production. [11]
During the course of the nineteenth
century, the idea of financing government with a tax on land had many
advocates, not least John Stuart Mill (1965 [1848]) and Henry George (n.d.
[1879]), though David Ricardo, as we shall see, was opposed to a
disproportionate tax on land.
5.5 Ricardo on the “toil” of the landlord and the fruits of capital
John Locke justified private property on the
grounds that labour is entitled to fruits of its labour.
If the value of commodities is almost
exclusively due to labour, the rent of land and the profits of capital appear
to be unfair and unjust. This line of
reasoning gave rise to the doctrine that Property is Theft, which was made
famous by Proudhon (n.d. [1840]). Ricardo
accepted the principle that all people were entitled to what they produce, but
he extended this principle to the sacrifices of the landlord and the
capitalist.
In the case of a tax on rent, he accepted
Smith’s argument that such a tax would not affect production, but Ricardo(195l
[1821]: 203) thought it would be unjust to tax land exclusively; and he turned
Smith’s maxim that taxes should be assessed according to the ability to pay
against him.
It must be admitted that the effects of these
taxes would be such as Adam Smith has described; but it would surely be very
unjust, to tax exclusively the revenue of any particular class of a community.
The burdens of the State should be
borne by all in proportion to their means: this is one of the four maxims
mentioned by Adam Smith, which should govern all taxation.
Rent often belongs to those who, after
many years of toil, have realised their gains, and expended their fortunes in
the purchase of land or houses; and it certainly would be an infringement of
that principle which should ever be held sacred, the security of property, to
subject it to unequal taxation.
This adds the “toil” of the landlord to the
“toil” of the labourer discussed by Locke and Smith.
Ricardo’s (1952 [1820]: V, 68-69) real
concern, however, was “the sacredness of property, which constituted the great
security of society.” He thought a
disproportionate tax on property would be a disincentive to industry.
18
He explained this principle more thoroughly in a
posthumous article in the Scotsman, in which he advocated extending the
suffrage to more people. He
stopped short of endorsing Universal Suffrage, however, because he thought the
franchise should only be extended to people who believed that the rights to
property should be sacred. To do
otherwise, Ricardo (1952 [1823]: V, 501) wrote, would sacrifice good
government and economic prosperity.
The man of a small income must be aware how
little his share would be if all the large fortunes in the kingdom were
equally divided among the people. He
must know that the little he would obtain by such a division could be no
adequate compensation for the overturning of a principle which renders the
produce of his industry secure.
Whatever might be his gains after such a principle had been admitted would be
held by a very insecure tenure, and the chance of his making any future gains
would be greatly diminished; for the quantity of employment in the country
must depend, not only on the quantity of capital, but upon its advantageous
distribution, and, above all on the conviction of each capitalist that he will
be allowed to enjoy unmolested the fruits of his capital, his skill, and his
enterprise. To take from him this
conviction is at once to annihilate half the productive industry of the
country, and would be more fatal to the poor labourer than to the rich
capitalist himself,
Ricardo does not even suggest that the whole
produce of society should belong to the labourer.
Good government required that the
capitalist, the landlord and the labourer should all be entitled to the fruits
of their occupations. He had what
might be called a real sacrifices theory of property rights. [12]
Karl Marx praised Adam Smith for his
comprehensive vision of political economy, but criticized him for his
contradictory theories of value: a labour theory of value for primitive
society and a cost of production theory for civil society.
Marx (1969:2, 165-66) described the
labour theory of value as the “esoteric” part of Smith’s work.
It reveals the real relations of
production and “fathoms the inner connection, the physiology, so to speak, of
the bourgeois system.” The cost of
production theory is the “exoteric” part.
It addresses the superficial manifestation of competition and “takes
the external phenomena of life, as they seem and appear and merely describes,
catalogues, recounts and arranges them under formal definitions.”
Whether his successors pursued the
esoteric or exoteric part of his work, they adopted his language and his
abstract concepts to describe and analyze economic phenomena.
Ricardo began his theory of value with Smith’s
example of the beaver and the deer, in which the quantity of labour realized
in commodities regulates their exchangeable value.
Marx (1969: 2, 166) said Ricardo’s
labour theory of value represented his “great historical significance for
science.”
19
But at last Ricardo steps in and calls to
science: Halt! The basis, the
starting-point for the physiology of the bourgeois system - for the
understanding of its internal organic coherence and life process - is the
determination of value by labour-time.
Marx endorsed Ricardo’s approach to the theory
of value because he thought it exposed the inherent conflict between the
classes under capitalism. If value is
determined by labour-time, then the capitalist must earn surplus value by
exploiting labour. He was not alone in
seeing class conflict and injustice buried in Ricardo.
Marx (1969:2, 167) noted that H.C.
Carey had denounced Ricardo as the “father of communism.”
Carey (1848: 75) had written that
Ricardo’s Principles “is the true manual of the demagogue, who seeks
power by means of agrarianism, war, and plunder.”
In some ways, however, Marx was closer to Smith
than Ricardo, Smith presented a labour theory of the origin of value in which
the whole product was due to labour not only in primitive society but also in
civil society. In a similar way, Marx
maintained that labour was the sole “value-creating substance.”
In contrast, Ricardo did not argue
that labour was the only source of value even in primitive society.
He criticized Smith’s example of the
beaver and the deer, because the hunter needed a weapon, which is a produced
means of production and, therefore, a capital good, to catch the beaver or
kill the deer. Wages plus profits
ultimately regulate the prices of most commodities for Ricardo.
In Volume I of Capital, Marx presented a
pure labour theory of the exchangeable value of commodities under capitalist
production. In the first place,
for a thing to be a commodity, it must be useful.
Its utility makes it a use-value,
which is qualitative. In the second
place, for a thing to be a commodity, it must possess exchange-value, which is
quantitative. Marx (1961 [1867]: I,
38) explained that the exchange-value of a commodity is created, measured and
regulated by the quantity of labour embodied in it.
A use-value, or useful article, therefore, has
value only because human labour in the abstract has been embodied or
materialised in it. How, then, is the
magnitude of this value to be measured?
Plainly, by the quantity of the value-creating substance, the labour,
contained in the article. The
quantity, however, is measured by its duration, and labour-time in its turn
finds its standard in weeks, days, and hours.
Labour is the origin of value, because labour is
the sole value creating substance. The
regulation of value is due to labour, because the exchangeable value of
commodities rises or falls as more or less labour is embodied in them.
Labour is also the measure of value,
though, for the sake of exposition, Marx (1961 [1867]:I, 85) took gold to be
his measure of value, because “it is the socially recognised incarnation of
human labour.”
Labour will only bestow value on an article if
it is employed efficiently. If labour
takes more time or uses more materials than necessary, the extra cost does not
add value to the article.
20
Only the socially necessary labour time required
for production creates value, which Marx (1961 [1867]: I, 39) defined as “that
required to produce an article under the normal conditions of production and
with the average degree of skill and intensity prevalent at the time.”
The labour power of all the individual labourers
in society counts as a homogeneous mass of labour power.
The heterogeneous collection of
individual labourers in society is converted by Marx (1961 [1867]: I, 170-71)
into a homogeneous mass of unskilled labourers using the labour theory of
value itself. Labour is simply a
commodity like any other commodity, and its value is determined in the same
manner as all other commodities.
The value of labour-power is determined, as in
the case of every other commodity, by the labour-time necessary for the
production, and consequently also the reproduction, of this special article.
So far as it has value, it represents
no more than a definite quantity of the average labour of society incorporated
in it.
The labour-time embodied in the production of
labour power can in turn be reduced to the value of the subsistence necessary
to raise and maintain the labourer. If
it take more time to raise and bring a philosopher to market than it does a
common street porter, one philosopher counts as so many street porters.
By this rule, which corrects Ricardo,
who weighted different labourers by their wages, all labour-time can be
reduced to unskilled labour-time. Unlike
the labour embodied in the production of other commodities, however, the
subsistence of the labourer varies from country to country and from age to
age. As Ricardo and Malthus had
earlier explained, subsistence depends on the habits and customs of a people.
Similarly, Marx (1961 [1867]:I, 171)
wrote that “there enters into the determination of the value of labour-power a
historical and moral element.”
Finally, in addition to being useful and having
labour embodied in it, an article must be exchanged in the market to be a
commodity. His theory of value does
not explain the value of the free gifts of nature, like the air and natural
meadows; and it does not explain the value of the quit-rent corn or the
tithe-corn that the medieval peasant produced for his feudal lord or his
parson. It applies to the value of
commodities produced in a society where capitalists employ free labourers to
produce commodities for sale in the market, where a free labourer is
free in the double sense, that as a free man he
can dispose of his labour-power as his own commodity, and that on the other
hand he has no other commodity for sale, is short of everything necessary for
the realisation of his labour-power (Marx, 1961 [1867]: I, 169).
His theory does not concern the labour of
someone whose hobby is his gardening, because his labour is not employed to
produce a commodity for sale in the market; and it does not pertain to the
family farm, which has its own land, buildings, and machinery.
They enjoy the fruits of their own
labour. The free labourer, in
contrast, must sell his labour power to the capitalist in order to buy his
subsistence. He produces a commodity
that does not belong to him; and, therefore, he is alienated from the product
of his labour.
21
Exchange occurs when the use-value of a
commodity to a buyer exceeds its exchange-value in the market, and the
exchange-value to the seller exceeds its use-value.
What they buy is worth more to them
than what they sell. This takes two
forms: selling in order to buy, which Marx (1961 [1867]: I, 149) denoted
C-M-C; and buying in order to sell, M-C-M.
The circuit starts C-M-C with one commodity, and finishes with another, which
falls out of circulation and into consumption.
Consumption, the satisfaction of wants, in one word, use-value, is its
end and aim. The circuit M-C-M, on the
contrary, commences with money and ends with money.
Its leading motive, and the goal that attracts it, is therefore mere
exchange-value.
Surplus value emerges even though equal values
are given in exchange. The capitalist
starts out with one sum of money and ends up with a larger sum of money.
This process can be written M-C-M´,
where M´ = M +ΔM. The increment over
the original sum of money is called surplus value.
Surplus value does not come from selling a thing
for more than it is worth. All things
exchange at full value, which is simply the value of the labour power embodied
in them. Surplus value flows from the
consumption of a commodity. Its source
is its value-in-use rather than its value-in-exchange, which Marx (1961
[1867]: I, 167) put rather vividly.
In order to be able to extract value from the
consumption of a commodity, our friend, Moneybags, must he so lucky as to
find, within the sphere of circulation, in the market, a commodity, whose
use-value possesses the peculiar property of being a source of value, whose
actual consumption, therefore, is itself an embodiment of labour, and,
consequently, a creation of value. The
possessor of money does find on the market such a special commodity in
capacity for labour or labour-power.
The exchange-value of labour is the subsistence
of the labourer. However, the
capitalist hires the labourer for the whole working day, which is the
use-value of labour. If subsistence
takes half a day’s labour to produce, the capitalist earns surplus value equal
to the other half of the day’s labour. The
whole working day is, in this way, divided into two parts: one to produce the
necessary subsistence for the labourer, the other to produce the surplus value
for the capitalist.
Marx called the means of subsistence the
variable part of capital or, simply, variable capital.
It is variable because labour is
the value creating substance. Labour
not only reproduces its own means of subsistence but it also produces surplus
value for the capitalist. He called
the means of production, that is, materials, supplies, equipment and
structures used in production, the constant part of capital, or constant
capital. It is constant because it
merely transfers its value to the commodity as it is used up in production.
22
The means of production are equal in value to
the labour embodied in them. They are
the product of “past labour,” to repeat Petty’s phrase again.
The value of tools or machines today
includes the value of the labour embodied in the tools and machines used up in
their production yesterday, and so on, back in time.
Marx (1961 [1867]: I, 187) illustrated
this principle with the example of cotton yarn.
Hence, in determining the value of the yarn, or
the labour-time required for its production, all the special processes carried
on at various times and in different places, which were necessary, first to
produce the cotton and the wasted portion of the spindle, and then with the
cotton and spindle to spin the yarn, may together be looked on as different
and successive phases of one and the same process.
The whole of the labour in the yarn is
past labour; and it is a matter of no importance that the operations necessary
for the production of its constituent elements were carried on at times which,
referred to the present, are more remote than the final operation of spinning.
The notion that labour, past and present,
produced all commodities is the logical and empirical foundation on which the
labour theory of value rests.
Marx (1961 [1867]: I, 713) traced the accumulation of labour-power back to “a
primitive accumulation (previous accumulation of Adam Smith) preceding
capitalist accumulation; an accumulation not the result of the capitalist mode
of production, but its starting point.”
The exchange value of a commodity for Marx
consists of three parts: the constant capital (c) used up in production, the
variable capital (v), and the surplus value (s).
The constant capital used up in
production simply transfers the labour already contained in it to a new
commodity. It is the product of past
labour and adds no new value to production. Current
labour creates new value. When the
commodity is sold on the market, its value replaces the constant capital used
up in production plus the variable capital paid to labour and yields surplus
value that is expropriated by the capitalist.
Marxian values = c + v + s.
Current labour produces both the means of
subsistence of the labourer and the surplus value of the capitalist.
Marx (1961 [1867]: I,218) defined the
ratio of labour-time spent to produce the surplus value of the capitalist to
the labour-time necessary to produce the subsistence of the labourer (s/v) as
the rate of surplus value. “The rate
of surplus-value is therefore an exact expression for the degree of
exploitation of labour-power by capital, or of the labourer by the
capitalist.” The rate of profit equals
surplus value divided by the total capital employed in production.
The profit motive leads the capitalist to pursue
surplus value. He can increase his
surplus by two processes, which Marx (1961 [1867]: I,315) called absolute
surplus value and relative surplus value.
23
The surplus-value produced by prolongation of
the working. I call absolute
surplus-value. On the other
hand, the surplus-value arising from the curtailment of the necessary labour-time,
and from the corresponding alteration in the respective lengths of the two
components of the working-day, I call relative surplus-value.
On the one hand, the capitalist wants the
labourer to work as long as possible. The
working day has a maximum limit of 24 hours, however; and without time to
sleep, eat, wash and attend to the daily needs of life as well as to pursue
social and intellectual interests, labour could not continue working for long.
On the other hand, labour wants to
work as little as possible. The length
of the working day, Marx (1961 [1867]: I,235) explained is ultimately
determined by a struggle, “a struggle between collective capital, i.e., the
class of capitalists, and collective labour, i.e., the working class.”
The length of the working day is the
immediate focus of the class struggle.
Relative surplus value is created by improving
the productivity of labour. The
capitalist increases productivity by providing the individual labourer with
more tools and better machinery, that is, by increasing the ratio of constant
to variable capital, which Marx called the organic composition of capital,
c/v. By increasing the means of
production per labourer, the labourer can reproduce the means of subsistence
in a shorter time. At first, the
surplus value of the capitalist grows as the necessary part of the working day
declines. In this way, the capitalist
becomes rich.
Accumulate, accumulate!
That is Moses and the prophets!
“Industry furnishes the material which
saving accumulates.” Therefore, save,
save, i.e., reconvert the greatest possible portion of surplus-value, or
surplus-product into capital! Accumulation
for accumulation’s sake, production for production’s sake: by this formula
classical economy expressed the historical mission of the bourgeoisie, and did
not for a single instant deceive itself over the birth-throes of wealth (Marx,
1961 [1867]: I,595).
However, as capital accumulates, the socially
necessary labour time embodied in production declines, so that competition
causes prices to fall. Therefore, the
capitalist must accumulate capital to reduce his cost of production.
Accumulation reduces costs by
extending the division of labour, by allowing the construction of vast systems
of machinery and by applying science to the technological of production.
Just as the free labourer, who owns no capital,
must sell his labour power to the capitalist in exchange for his subsistence
and, thereby, become alienated from the product of his labour, so too the
capitalist must accumulate and innovate to avoid failing into the ranks of the
proletariat, though ultimately many fail.
The battle on competition is fought by the
cheapening of commodities. The
cheapness of commodities depends, ceteris paribus, on the productiveness of
labour, and this again on the scale of production.
Therefore, the larger capitals beat
the smaller (Marx, 1961 [1867]: I,626)
24
Competition, wrote Marx (1961 [1867]: 1,619),
“makes the immanent laws of capitalist production to be felt by each
individual capitalist, as external coercive laws,”
Schumpeter (1950 [1942]: 81-86), who
was a close reader of Marx, later referred to this as “the process of creative
destruction.” The means of production
gradually becomes obsolete as capital accumulates, as Marx (1962 [1894]: III,
112) explained. With the introduction
of improved machinery, old capital “continually becomes antiquated before it
has time to reproduce its own value.” Old
antiquated capital goods are technologically obsolete.
Old capital goods that are still in
use may not and, sometimes, cannot be reproduced.
They sells for less than the value of
the labour embodied them.
6.5 The so-called
transformation problem.
In Volume III of Capital, Marx addressed
the same issue which had confronted Ricardo. Competition
tends to produce a uniform rate of profit in all industries as capital moves
from low to high profit industries. If
the capital structure is the same in every industry, that is, if the organic
composition of capital is the everywhere the same, then market prices of
commodities are proportional to the labour embodied in production.
They are proportional to the variable
capital plus constant capital used up in production.
But, if the capital structure is not
the same in every industry, market prices tend to exceed labour values in
those industries which are relatively intensive in the use of constant
capital. This theoretical possibility
required Marx to introduce his own considerable modification to his labour
theory of value in Volume III of Capital when he discussed how
competition transforms labour values into the prices of production.
This is the so-called transformation
problem.
Surplus value arises from the exploitation of
labour and is proportional to the variable capital employed in production,
whereas the rate of profit is proportional to the whole capital employed.
Thus, the rates of surplus value and
profit are explained by different principles and are not in general the same.
Marx argued that competition tends to
allocate the total surplus value created in society among the different
branches of production in proportion to the total capital they employ.
Marx (1962: III, 156) wrote
the rates of profit prevailing in the various
branches of production are originally very different.
These different rates of profit are
equalized by competition to a single general rate of profit to any capital of
a given magnitude, whatever its organic composition, called the average
profit.
“Hence,” Marx (1962: III, 156) concluded, “the
price of production is equal to the cost-price plus the profit.”
Even though Marx sought to explain the
prices of production by the labour embodied in production, he ended up with a
cost-plus-profit theory of value like Adam Smith and David Ricardo.
Marx’s transformation turns profits
into a necessary cost of production, because any industry that did not receive
the “average profit” would see its capital diverted to other industries.
Adam Smith simply abandoned the labour
theory of value when he moved beyond the beaver and deer of primitive society.
For Smith, the natural prices in civil
society are regulated by
25
wages, profits and rents, all of which must be
paid at their natural rates for production to be forthcoming.
Ricardo insisted that even the beaver
and the deer required capital to hunt and to kill, so that profits were a
component part of price for him even in primitive society.
Many authors tried to solve the so-called
transformation problem even before Volume Ill of Capital appeared, but
Engels thought they all failed (Marx, l961: III, 8-21).
Marx’s own solution is seriously
flawed, because he transformed output prices without transforming input
values, which were labour values, not market prices.
He needed to know the market prices of
the capital used in production to show how competition tends to equalized the
rate of profits on capital. Ladislaus
von Bortkiewicz (1949 [1907]) offered an early solution to this problem, but
he did not follow Marx’s method. His
method is correct as far as it goes, but it does not go far enough.
He restricted his analysis to the
special case of simple reproduction, in which past labour and current labour
are the same. He does not consider how
the labour-power embodied in today’s constant capital has accumulated over
historical time. The past labour
embodied in things that are no longer being produced, but which are still
being used up and embodied in the production of new commodities, cannot be
transformed into market prices using today’s prices.
Technologically obsolete constant
capital may have no current cost of reproduction, though it may continue to
earn what Marshall called a quasi-rent. The
value of old capital goods is simply the present value of their quasi-rents,
which is unrelated to the labour embodied in them.
The debate continues to this day. [13]
The powerful appeal of the labour theory of
value rests on the self-evident proposition that, when production is traced
back to its origin, all commodities can, in principle, be reduced to land and
labour. Since land is a free gift of
nature which cost no human effort to produce, it cannot explain value, though
it is the source of physical things. From
this perspective, capital goods are merely “past labour.”
Therefore, all commodities are
produced by labour alone: labour is the origin of value.
The truth of this proposition captured
the imagination of classical economists, and it lingers on in the theory of
rent. It gave Locke’s theory of
property rights and Marx’s theory of exploitation a persuasive ethical
foundation, but it raised more problems than it could solve in the economic
theory of market prices.
Locke did not carry this line of thought beyond
the realm of moral philosophy, however.
He had a supply and demand theory of market prices.
Smith began with a labour theory of the origin of value and presented a
universal measure of value based on labour sacrifice, but he restricted his
labour theory of exchange-value to primitive society where the labour embodied
in production regulates the value-in-exchange of the beaver and the deer.
When he turned his eye to the market
place in civil society, he did not even attempt to reconcile the labour
embodied in the production of commodities with their market prices.
He abandoned the labour theory of
exchange-value and explained how the cost of production ultimately regulates
market prices.
26
Ricardo began with Smith’s example of the beaver
and deer and tried to show that labour is “really the foundation of the
exchangeable value of all things,” but his own logic led him to a cost of
production theory. While he got rid of
rent, he maintained that profit is a necessary cost of production.
Marx followed Ricardo.
He presented a pure labour theory of
value in Volume I of Capital, but could not escape the conclusion that
profit was a component part of price in Volume III.
Ricardo and Marx both had trouble with the
concept of fixed or constant capital, which they viewed in terms of what Petty
had called “past labour.” This
conception requires a retrospective accounting for the labour embodied in
capital goods going back in historical time. It
encounters two serious obstacles. First,
as Locke (1967 [1690]: 298) observed, such an accounting for the labour
embodied in things would produce a list that would “be almost impossible, at
least too long, to reckon up.” If
the “past labour” embodied in commodities produced today is not knowable, the
total quantity of labour bestowed on Ricardo’s stockings and Marx’s socially
necessary (or average) labour-time embodied in a commodity are not knowable.
“Past labour” cannot be the basis of
any calculation. Second, “past labour”
is backward looking. Whatever any
thing may have originally cost to produce need have nothing to do with its
market price, which depends on what is expected to happen in the future.
Old capital goods sell at the present
value of the quasi-rents that they are expected to eam in the future.
In the market place, where prices are
actually determined, bygones are forever bygones.
27
[1] Marx
(1969: I, 356) justly maintained that Locke’s “philosophy served as the basis
for all the ideas of the whole of subsequent English political economy.”
The influence of Locke on the
philosophical foundations of classical economics is treated by James Bonar
(1893: 91-103) and by Werner Stark (1944: 1-30), though they do not always
agree with each other. Gunnar Myrdal
(1953: 71) wrote that “In its purest form, the theory demands laissez-faire,
for it implies the view of the ‘sacred’ might of man to the fruits of his
work.” Schumpeter (1950 [1942]:
298-99) went even further: “The ideology of classical socialism is the
offspring of bourgeois ideology. In
particular, it fully shares the latter’s rationalist and utilitarian
background and many of the ideas and ideals that entered the classical
doctrine of democracy.”
[2] In the 1665 National Wealth Account that
Petty (1899 [1667]: 105-I 10) constructed for England and Wales, he estimated
the value of the capital stock at £106 million (consisting of housing,
shipping, livestock, coins and goods), the land at £144 million and the
capitalized value of labour at £417 million. In
the economy of 1665, housing would include agricultural, commercial and
industrial structures. In his
corresponding National Income Account, he put wages at £25 million, rent at £8
million and the yield of “Money and other personal estates,”that is, capital,
at £7 million.
[3] Notable commentators on Petty include Karl
Marx (1969-72:1, 361), C.H. Hull (1899: lxxiii; 1900:330-331), E.A.J. Johnson
(1937: 102-13), J.A. Schumpeter (1954:211-15), T. Aspromourgos (1986: 28-45)
and T, Hutchison (1988).
[4] C.B. MacPherson (1962, p. 264) has called
this “possessive individualism.” He
argues that the assumptions of possessive individualism received their
“clearest and fullest” expression from Hobbes.
His model of man, as the sum of man’s powers to get gratifications,
reduces the human essence to freedom from others’ wills and proprietorship of
one’s own capacities. His model of
society, which follows from his model of man plus the assumption that every
man’s powers are opposed to every other man’s, we have seen to be a full
possessive market model.
MacPherson traces this philosophy from Hobbes to
Locke, but it clearly extends to Adam Smith and beyond.
This is an ethical theory, not an
economic theory; and it also has an obvious religious basis.
Locke (1967 [1690]: 172) noted how God
made Adam a day labourer for life when He cast him out of Paradise: “In time
sweat of thy face shalt thou eat thy bread, till thou return unto the ground,
for out of it wast thou taken, for dust thou art, and unto dust shalt thou
return”
28
[5] A theory of the origin of value is an
explanation of a cause of causes. The
classical economists saw labour as the cause of value, for which they were
severely criticized by the early neoclassical economists.
The early neoclassical economists, who
developed the marginal utility theory, thought they had found the truth when
they claimed that utility is the origin of value.
In his Principles of Economics,
Carl Menger (1950 [1871]) claimed that value originates in the relation
between man’s needs for various things and the quantities of them that are
available. Friedrich von Wieser (1956
[1888]: 3) began Natural Value with a chapter on “The Origin of Value,”
in which he asked: “Whence do things get their value?”
Where goods are scarce, von Wieser
(1956 [1888]: Xxxii) said, “utility creates value.”
Leon Walras (1954 [1874-77]) included
a lesson entitled “Exposition and Refutation of Adani Smith’s and J.B. Say’s
Doctrines of the Origin of Value in Exchange” in his Elements of Pure
Economics, in which he traced the origin of value to rareté, the
Walrasian term for marginal utility. W.
J.. Jevons (1957 [1871], 2) also included a section “On the Origin of Value”
in his Theory of Political Economy, in which he asserted that “value
depends entirely upon utility.” By
early in the twentieth century, discussion of the origin of value disappeared
from the economic literature, because there is no such thing.
In a competitive economy, exchange
values depend on the complex of wants, technical knowledge, resources and
their distribution among the people. Dooley
(1900) compares the classical and neoclassical theories of the origin, measure
and regulation of value.
[6] For further discussion of classical
price theory, see E. Roll (1956), G.J. Stigler (1965 [1958]), M. Blaug (1978),
D.P. Levine (1977), D. O’Brien (1975), S. Hollander (1973, 1979), M.H. Dobb
(1973), R. Meek (1956, 1977), V. Bladen (1938, 1975), and P. Douglas (1966
[1928]), Walsh and Gram (1980), R. O’Donnell (1990) and T. Peach (1993), among
many others.
[7] What Smith (1976 [1776]: 47, 50) meant by
“labour” is not entirely clear. His
language vacillates between something akin to Jevons’ “disutility” of labour,
which the utilitarians called “pain,” and the more modern concept of leisure
forgone: “toil and trouble” suggests disutility, whereas “he must always lay
down the same portion of his ease, his liberty, and his happiness” implies the
principle of opportunity cost. Since
Smith had a theory of occupation choice, where different occupations involved
different degrees of hardship or ingenuity, he emphasized the disutility of
labour more than leisure forgone.
Both disutility and leisure forgone may be considered sacrifices, Smith’s
theory of occupation choice clearly implies that labour is homogeneous.
In contrast to Senior (1965 [1836]: I
29-30, 21 7.-20), Smith does not consider the possibility of some individuals
receiving a “rent of ability” because they possess extraordinary natural
talents or of some occupations, such as nursing, earning permanently low wages
because some people strongly prefer these occupations to others; and he treats
“acquired and useful abilities (l976 [1776]: 282)” as a species of capital,
which receives the ordinary rate of profit. Where
labour is homogeneous, an hour of work is an objective phenomenon.
29
[8] Meek (1956), Hollander (1973), Blaug (1978)
and others have contended that labour command refers to the wages or
subsistence of the labourer, which, however, Smith called the real price of
labour. It was his rough index of
economic welfare. Bladen (1938, 1975)
maintained, in contrast, that Smith measures the value of commodities as well
as wages, profit and rent by the real price of commodities, not the real price
of labour.
[9] Knight (1965 [1935]:150) has explained this
principle with great clarity: “The cost of any alternative (simple or complex)
chosen is the alternative which has to be given up; where there is no
alternative to a given experience, no choice, there is no economic problem,
and cost has no meaning.” See also
Buchanan (1946 [1929]) for a clear discussion of the classical theory of rent.
[10] Ricardo’s theory of value
gave rise to academic industry in the history of economic thought after the
publication of Production of commodities by Means of commodities by
Piero Sraffa. Sraffa’s influence is
evident in many articles in The New Palgrave Dictionary, in which the
article on “Sraffian economics” is by Paul A. Samuelson (1987).
See also the survey by Schefold
(1998).
[11] The Ricardian theory of rent is based on
severe and unrealistic assumptions. If
all land remains in production whether it is taxed or not, the services of all
land must be put on the market at whatever rent they may fetch.
While the quantity of land may be
considered practically fixed, the supply of it depends on the preferences of
landlords. They may prefer to plant
rose gardens or keep deer parks rather than rent their lands to farmers.
If the supply of land coincides with the quantity of it, the supply
curve would be perfectly inelastic. Dooley
(1991) gives an analysis and criticism of Marshall’s treatment of Ricardian
rent. E.J. Mishan (1981) has shown it
implies that the income and substitution effects of all landlords must be
zero.
[12] Later in the century, J.B. Clark (1956
[1899]: v) employed the Law of Diminishing Returns, which Ricardo had refined,
in order to demonstrate that on the margin of production, where the last unit
of labour or capital is employed, all factors of production tend to receive
the value of what they create. By this
device, Clark thought he had extended Locke’s justification of private
property to capital, land being treated as a species of capital by him.
At the point in the economic system where titles
to property originate, - where labor and capital come into possession of the
amounts that the state afterwards treats as their own, - the social procedure
is true to the principle on which the right of property rests.
So far as it is not obstructed, it
assigns to every one what he has specifically produced.
Clark’s theory was well-received in America,
because it purported to justify late 19th century industrial capitalism.
He did not, however, explain how the
wealthy came into possession of
30
their property.
Marx (1904 [1859]: 285-287) correctly observed the real basis for the
distribution of income is the distribution of property, which is a matter of
economic history, not economic theory.
[13] See, for example, F. Scion
(1957), R. Meek (1977), P.A. Samuelson (1971), L. Pasinetti (1977), J.
Robinson (1977), I. Steedman (1977), A. Freeman (1984), F. Moseley (l993) and
C. Carchedi (1993), among a great many others.
Aspromourgos, T. 1986. “Political Economy and the
Social Division of Labour: The Economics of Sir William Petty,” Scottish
Journal of Political Ecomomy, 33: 28-45.
Bladen, V. (1975) “Command over labour: a study
in misinterpretation,” Canadian Journal of Economics 8: 504-19.
Bladen, V. 1938. “Adam Smith on value,” Essays
inPolitical Economy in Honor of E.J. Urwick, ed. by HA. Innis
(Toronto: University of Toronto Press).
Blaug, M. 1978. Economic Theory in Retrospect,
3rd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Bonar, J. 1893. Philosophy and Political
Economy in Some of Their Historical Relations (London: Swan Sonnenschein).
Bortkiewicz, L. von, 1949 [1907]. “On the
correction of Marx’s fundamental theoretical construction in the Third Volume
of Capital,” trans, by P.M. Sweezy, Karl Marx and the Close of His
System, byE. von Böhm-Bawerk (New York: Kelley).
Buchanan, D.H. 1946 [l929]. “The Historical
Approach to Rent and Price Theory,” Readings in the Theory of Income
Distribution, ed, W. Fellner and B.F. Haley (Philadelphia: Blakiston).
Carchedi, C. (1993). “Marx’s Logic of Inquiry and
Price Formation,” Marx’s Method in Capital, ed. F. Moseley (New Jersey:
Humanities Press).
Carey, B.C. 1848. The Past, The Present, and
the Future (Philadelphia: Carey & Hart).
Clark, J.B. 1956 [1899]. The Distribution of
Wealth (New York: Kelley and Millman).
Dobb, M.H. 1973. Theories of Value and
Distribution since Adam Smith: Ideology amid Economic Theory (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press).
Dooley, Peter C. 1991. “Marshall’s Parable of the
Meteoric Stones: Rent, Quasi-Rent and Interest,” The American Journal of
Economics and Sociology, 50:197-206.
Dooley, Peter C. 1990. “Value,” Foundations of
Economic Thought, ed. by John Creedy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).
Douglas, PH. 1966 [1928]. “Smith’s theory of
value and distribution,” Adam Smith, 1776-1925 (New York: Kelley).
32
Freeman, A. 1984. “The Logic of the
Transformation Problem,” Ricardo. Marx, Sraffa (ed. by E. Mandel and A.
Freeman (London: Verso).
George, Henry. 1966 [1879]. Progress and
Poverty’ (New York: Modern Library).
Hobbes, Thomas, 1968 [1651], Leviathan,
ed. by C.B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth, U.K.:Penguin).
Hollander, S. 1973. The Economics of Adam
Smith (Toronto: University of Toronto Press).
Hollander, S. 1979. The Economics of David
Ricardo (Toronto: University of Toronto Press).
Hull, C.H. 1899. “Introduction,” The Economic
Writings of Sir William Petty, ed. C.H. Hull (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
Hull, C.H. 1900. “Petty’s Place in the History of
Economic Theory,” Quarterly Journal of Economics.
Ingram, J.K. 1893. A History of Political
Economy (New York: London).
Jevons, W.S. 1957 [1871]. The Theory of
Political Economy (New York: Kelley and Millman).
Johnson, E.A.J. 1937. Predecessors ofAdam
Smith: time Grout/i of British Economic Thought (New York: Prentice-Hall).
Knight, F.H. 1965 [1935]. “Notes on Utility and
Costs,” The Economic Organization (New York: Harper & Row).
Levine, D.P. 1977. Economic Studies:
Contributions to the critique of Economic Theory (London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul)
Locke, John. 1967 [1690]. Two Treatises of
Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press),
Locke, John. 1991 [1692]. Some Considerations
of the Consequences of the Loitering of Interest, and Raising the Value of
Money in Locke on Money, ed. Patrick Hyde Kelly (Oxford: Clarendon
Press).
MacPherson, C.B. 1962. The Political Theory of
Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (Oxford: The Clarendon Press)
Malthus, T.R. 1986 [1798]. An Essay on
the Principle of Population, The Works of Thomas Robert Mahthus, ed. by
E.A. Wrigley and D. Souden (London: William Pickering).
33
Marshall, A. 1961 [1890]. Principles of
Economics, ed, by C.W. Guillebaud, 2 vols. (London: Macmillan).
Marx, Karl. (1904 [1859]). A Contribution to
the Critiques of Political Economy, translated by N.E. Stone, 2nd. (New
York: International Library Publishing).
Marx, Karl. 1969-72. Theories of Surplus
Value, 3 parts (London: Lawrence & Wishart).
Marx, Karl 1951 Theories of Surplus Value,
translated by GA. Gonner and Emile Bums from Theorien über den Mehrwert
edited by Karl Kautaky (London: Lawrence & Wishart).
Marx, K. 1961-1962 [1867-1894]. Capital, 3
vols. (Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House).
Meek, R.L. 1977. Smith, Marx, and After
(London: Chapman and Hall).
Meek, R.L. 1956. Studies in the Labour Theory
of Value (London: Lawrence & Wishart)
Menger, C. 1950 [1871]. Principles of
Economics, trans. and ed. by .J. Dingwall and B.F. Hoselitz (Glencoe,
Ill.: Free Press).
Mill, John Stuart, 1965 [1848]. Principles of Political Economy with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy (ed. by J.M. Robson), 2 vols. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press).
Mishan, E.J. 1981. Introduction to
Normative Economics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Moseley, F. 1993. “Marx’s Logical Method and the
‘Transformation problem’,” Marx’s Method in Capital, ed. F. Mosehey
(New Jersey: Humanities Press).
Myrdal, G. 1953. The Political Element in the
Development of Economic Theory (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul).
O’Brien, D.P. 1975. The Classical Economists
(Oxford: Clarendon Press).
O’Donnell, Rory. 1990. Adam Smith’s Theory of
Value and Distribution (New York: St. Martin’s Press).
Peach, T. 1993. Interpreting Ricardo
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Petty, Sir William. 1899 [1662]. Treatise of
Taxes amid Contributions, The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty,
ed. C.H. Hull (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
34
Petty, Sir William. 1899 [1664]. Verbum
Sapienti, The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty, ed. C.H. Hull
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Petty, Sir William. 1899 [1672]. The Political
Anatomy of Ireland, The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty, ed.
C.H. Hull (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Petty, Sir William. 1899 [1676]. Political
Arithmeiic, The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty, ed. C.H.
Hull (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Proudhon, P.3. 1970 [1840] What is Property?
(New York: Dover).
Ricardo, David. 1951-73 [1821]. The
Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, The Works and Correspondence of
David Ricardo, ed. by P. Sraffa with the collaboration of MB. Dobb, II
vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Roll, Eric. 1956. A History of Economic
Thought (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall).
Samuelson, PA, 1978. “Understanding the Marxian
notion of exploitation: a summary of the so-called transformation problem
between Marxian values and competitive prices,” Journal of Economic
Literature 9, 399-431.
Samuelson, P.A. 1987. “Sraftian economics,”
The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, ed, by J. Eatwell, M. Milgate
and P. Newman (London: Macmillan) 4,452-461.
Schefold, 8. 1998. “Piero Sraffa,” Italian
Economists of the 20th Century, ed. by F. Meacci. (Chetlenham, U.K:
Edward Elgar).
Schumpeter, J.A. 1950 [1942]. Capitalism,
Socialism amid Democracy, 3rd ed. (New York: Harper & Row).
Schumpeter, J.A. 1954. History of Economic
Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press).
Seton, F. 1957. “The transformation problem,”
Review of Economic Studies 25, 149-60.
Smith, Adam 1976 [1776]. An Inquiry into the
Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, ed. by RH. Campbell and AS.
Skinner, 2 vol. (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Sraffa, Piero. 1960. Production of Commodities
by Means of Commodities. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Stark, Werner, 1944. The Ideal Foundations of
Economic Thought (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Steedman, I. 1977. Marx after Sraffa
(London: Verso).
35
Stigler, G.J. 1965 [1958] “Ricardo and the 93 Per
Cent Labor Theory of Value,” Essays in the History of Economics
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
Vaughn, K.l. 1980. John Locke: Economist and
Social Scientist (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
Walras, Leon. 1954 [1874-77). Elements of Pure
Economics, trans. W. Jaffé. Homewood, II., Richard D. Irwin.
Walsh, V. and Gram, H. 1980. Classical amid Neoclassical Theories of General Equilibrium Historical Origins amid Mathematical Structure. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Whitaker, AC. 1968 [1904] .History and
Criticism of the Labor Theory of Value in English Political Economy New
York: Kelley)
Wicksteed, P.1!. 1933. The Common Sense of
Political Economy: Selected Papers and Reviews on Economic Theory (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul).
Wieser, F. von 1956 [1888]. Natural Value,
trans. by CA. Malloch and ed. by W. Smart (New York: Kelley and Millman).
36