The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Analytic Philosophy
Encyclopedia Britannica
Britannica 2003 Ultimate CD Reference Suite
also called Linguistic philosophy, a movement, dominant in
Anglo-U.S. philosophy in the 20th century, distinguished by its method, which
has focused upon language and the analysis of the concepts expressed by it.
The methods that have dominated British philosophy for most of the 20th
century and American philosophy since somewhat more recently have been called
Linguistic and Analytic because language and the analysis of the concepts
expressed by language have been a central concern. Though
Moreover, the aims assigned to the philosophical study of language have
often been different. Some philosophers,
among them Bertrand Russell and the early Wittgenstein, have thought that the
underlying structure of language mirrors that of the world - that from an
analysis of language a philosopher can grasp important truths about reality. This so-called picture theory of language,
though influential, is generally repudiated by current Analytic philosophers. Another important dispute concerns whether
everyday language is defective, vague, misleading, and even, at times,
contradictory. Some Analytic
philosophers have thus proposed the construction of an “ideal” language: precise,
free of ambiguity, and clear in structure. The general model for such a language has been
symbolic logic, the growth of which in the 20th century has played a central
role in Analytic philosophy. An ideal
language, it was thought, would resolve many traditional philosophical disputes
that have arisen from the misleading structure of natural languages. At the other pole, some philosophers have
thought that many philosophic problems have come from paying too little
attention to what men say in everyday language about various situations.
Despite such disagreements, Analytic philosophers have much in common. Most of them, for example, have concentrated
on particular philosophical problems, such as that of induction, or have
examined specific concepts, such as those of memory or of personal identity,
without attempting to construct any grand metaphysical schemes - an attitude
that has roots as ancient as those of the Socratic method exemplified in
Plato's dialogues. Almost invariably
Plato began with specific questions such as “What is knowledge?” or “What is
justice?” and pursued them in a way that can be viewed, without undue strain,
as philosophical analysis in the modern sense.
Ideally, a philosophical analysis illuminates some important concept
and helps to answer philosophical questions involving the concept. A famous example of such analysis is contained
in Bertrand Russell's theory of definite descriptions. In a simple subject–predicate statement such
as “Socrates is wise,” he said, there seems to be something referred to
(Socrates) and something said about it (that he is wise). If, instead of a proper name, however, a
“definite description” is substituted, as in the statement “The president of
the
In Russell's view, philosophers such as Meinong
were misled by surface grammatical form into thinking that such statements are
simple subject–predicate statements. In
reality they are complex; in fact, an analysis of the foregoing example shows
that the definite description, “the present king of
General viewpoint of Analytic philosophy
Nature, role, and method of analysis
Analytic
philosophy is concerned with the close and careful examination of concepts.
Status of philosophy in the Empiricist
tradition
In spirit and style Analytic philosophy has strong ties with the
Empiricist tradition, which stresses the data received through the senses and
which, except for brief periods, has characterized British philosophy for some
centuries, distinguishing it from the more Rationalistic trends of continental
European philosophy. It is not surprising, therefore, that Analytic philosophy should find
its home mainly in the Anglo-Saxon countries. In fact, the beginning of modern Analytic
philosophy is generally dated from the time when two of its major figures,
Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore, both
Most Empiricists, though admitting that the senses fail to yield the
certainty requisite for knowledge, hold nonetheless that it is only through
observation and experimentation that justified beliefs about the world can be
gained; i.e., a priori reasoning from self-evident premises cannot reveal how the
world is. This view has resulted in a
sharp dichotomy among the sciences: between the physical sciences, which
ultimately must verify their theories by observation, and the deductive or a priori sciences - e.g., mathematics and logic - the method of which is the deduction
of theorems from given axioms. Thus, the
deductive sciences cannot give justified beliefs, much less knowledge, of the
world. This consequence was one of the
cornerstones of two important movements within Analytic philosophy, logical
atomism and Logical Positivism. In the
Positivist's view, for example, the theorems of mathematics are merely the
result of working out the consequences of the conventions that have been adopted
for the use of its symbols.
The question then arises whether philosophy itself is to be assimilated
to empirical or to a priori sciences.
Early Empiricists assimilated philosophy
to the Empirical sciences. They were
less self-reflective about its methods than contemporary Analytic philosophers
are. Being preoccupied with epistemology
(theory of knowledge) and the philosophy of mind, and holding that fundamental
facts can be learned about these subjects from individual introspection, they
took their work to be a kind of introspective psychology. Analytic philosophers in the 20th century, on
the other hand, have been less inclined to appeal ultimately to direct
introspection. Moreover, the development
of rigorous methods in formal logic seemed to promise help in solving
philosophical problems - and logic is as a
priori as a science can be. It
seemed, then, that philosophy must be classed with mathematics and logic.
Conceptual, linguistic, and scientific analysis
The question remained, however, what philosophy's function and methodology are. For
a great many Analytic philosophers who do philosophy in the minute and
meticulous manner of G.E. Moore and, in particular, for those who have made
Philosophy can be seen either as conceptual or as linguistic analysis. In the analysis of the concept of seeing, for
example, the philosopher is not expressing purely linguistic concerns - with,
say, the English verb “to see” - though an investigation of what can be said
using that verb may be relevant to his conclusions. For a concept is independent of any particular
languages; a concept is something that all languages, insofar as they are
capable of expressing the concept, have in common. Thus, philosophers who stress that it is
concepts that they analyze attempt to rebut the charge that their problems and
solutions are merely verbal.
In contrast, other Analytic philosophers have been concerned with how
expressions are used in a particular, nontechnical,
everyday language. Thus, the term
ordinary language philosophy has been applied by critics as a term of
opprobrium to such philosophers. An
influential study, The Concept of Mind
(1949), by Gilbert Ryle, a prominent Oxford Analyst,
is an example of a work that some critics took to depend in large part on a
trivial appeal to how English speakers talk; but many of Ryle's
arguments could equally well have been given by Analytic philosophers who would
look upon the term ordinary language with horror.
The problem of perception illustrates how Analytic philosophers who do
conceptual analysis think of the goal of philosophy as both different from and
complementary to science. Physiologists,
psychologists, and physicists - through experiments, observations, and testable
theories - have also contributed to man's understanding of perception. There is in the sciences, however, a strong
tendency to advance beyond earlier positions, which seems to be absent from
philosophy. In philosophy, for example,
the account of perception given by such 20th-century Analytic philosophers as
G.E. Moore and the Positivist A.J. Ayer has a close connection with that of
Locke in the 17th century.
The difference between philosophy and science is that, whereas the scientist
investigates an actual occurrence, such as seeing, the philosopher investigates
a concept that he already possesses quite independently of what he might
discover through the occurrence. Whereas
the scientist begins by supposing that he can recognize examples of seeing and
is already exercising the concept, the philosopher wants to know what is
involved in seeing in the sense of what conditions one can use to classify
cases as examples of seeing. He may want
to know, for example, whether certain conditions are necessary or sufficient. In testing the philosophical
theory that, for an observer to see an object, the object must cause a visual
experience in him (the causal theory of perception), one does not set up a
scientific experiment. It would
be of no use to set up situations in which various physical objects are not
causing any visual experiences in order to see whether they still can be seen. For if the theory is correct, no such
experimental situation will be an instance of seeing; and if it is wrong,
merely describing a hypothetical situation would suffice. The question is one about how situations are
classified, and for that purpose hypothetical situations are as good as real
ones.
Therapeutic function of analysis
For some philosophers in the Analytic tradition, especially those
influenced by Wittgenstein, the analysis of concepts has therapeutic value
beyond the intrinsic enjoyment of doing it. Even scientists and laymen in their
philosophical moments generate problems by not understanding the proper
analyses of the concepts that they employ. They are then tempted to formulate theories to
explain these difficulties, when instead they should be sorting out the roles
of the concepts, which would show them that there was no problem to begin with.
Thus, the failure to see how
psychological concepts - sensations, emotions, and desires - are employed has
led philosophers to such problems as how one can know what is going on in
another's mind or how desires and emotions can produce physical changes in the
body, and vice versa. Analysis of the
concepts involved would, in this way of looking at philosophy, “dissolve”
rather than solve the problems, for philosophers would come to see that their
formulations of the problem rest on mistakes about the concepts involved.
This way of looking at philosophy has often been criticized as making
it merely a clearing up of the confusions of other philosophers and therefore a
sterile enterprise. The confusions,
however, need not be only those of other philosophers. Scientists, for example, can also generate
philosophical theories that affect how they design their experiments, which
may, thus, be subjects for philosophical therapeutics. Behaviorism in psychology - which views
emotions, desires, and attitudes as being dispositions to behave in certain
ways - seems to be a philosophical theory and perhaps to be based on a confusion about the analysis of psychological concepts. Yet Behaviorism has influenced psychologists
in their approach to the science. Thus,
in this view, philosophy can have a therapeutic value beyond the sphere of
philosophical games.
Philosophy, in spite of its abstractness, has traditionally been
concerned with human needs, and the therapeutic model may even fulfill this
ideal. Laymen, as well as philosophers,
for example, are bothered by the thought that their actions are determined not
by themselves but by prior conditions. This is a problem that, if the therapeutic
view is correct, rests on the misunderstanding of such concepts as causation,
responsibility, and action, which need clarification.
Formal versus ordinary language
The role of language as a central concern of Analytic philosophers is
the dimension most involved in disputes about the methodology employed. Philosophers outside the Analytic movement
tend to think that its preoccupation with language is a departure from
philosophy as classically conceived. Yet
Plato and Aristotle, medieval philosophers, the Empiricists - and, in fact,
most of the philosophers whose works have been considered important - have
found it essential to talk about language. There are serious differences, however, about
what role language should play. One such
difference concerns the importance of formal languages (in the sense employed
in symbolic logic) for philosophical problems.
Development of mathematical logic
Since the time of Aristotle, logic has been allied to philosophy. Until the late 19th century, however, logic
was largely confined to formulating elaborate rules for one fairly simple form
of argument - the syllogism; and there was a lack of systematic development of
the subject along lines that had been taken in mathematics since early times.
Almost from the beginning, mathematicians had rigorously exploited two
important techniques: (1) the use of the axiomatic method (as in Euclid's
geometry) in developing the subject; and (2) the use of schematic letters or
variables for stating general truths in the subject (thus, one can write “A + B
= B + A”, in which any names or numbers whatsoever can be substituted for A and
B, and the result will still be true).
It is surprising that logicians through the ages failed to grasp the
power of the use of schematic letters. When
they finally began to employ these and other mathematical techniques, they made
great contributions to man's understanding of the subject.
Among the developments that occurred in the 19th century, primarily
through the work of mathematicians, those of the Englishman George Boole, creator of Boolean algebra, and of Georg Cantor, the Russian-born creator of set theory, are
especially important inasmuch as they gave promise of bringing logic and
mathematics closer together. The one
figure who was both a mathematician and a philosopher and so might be credited
with the marriage of logic as a philosophical subject with the techniques of
mathematics was Gottlob Frege
(died 1925), of the University of Jena in Germany. Historically, Frege,
whose works are now appreciated in their own right, was important principally
for his influence on Bertrand Russell, whose monumental work, Principia Mathematica
(1910–13), written in collaboration with Alfred North Whitehead, together with
Russell's earlier Principles of
Mathematics (1903), awakened philosophers to the fact that the use of
mathematical techniques in logic might prove to be of great importance for
philosophy. Its symbolism had the
advantage of being closely connected with ordinary language, whereas its rules
can be precisely formulated. Moreover,
work in symbolic logic has produced many distinctions and techniques that can
be applied to ordinary language.
Divergence of ordinary language from formal logic
Ordinary language, however, seems to differ from the artificial
language of symbolic logic in more respects than its lack of precisely stated
rules. On the surface, it often appears
to violate the rules of symbolic logic. In
the English statement “If this is gold [symbolized by p], then this will
dissolve in aqua regia [symbolized by q],” for
example, which in symbolic logic is expressed in a form known as the material
conditional, p ⊃
q (in which ⊃
means “If . . . then . . . ”), one of the rules is that the statement is true
whenever “This is gold” is false. In
ordinary language, on the contrary, one would not count the statement as true
merely on formal logical grounds but only if there were some real connection in
the world of chemical reactions between being gold and dissolving in aqua regia - a connection that plays no role in symbolic logic.
Among Analytic philosophers the existence of many such apparent
divergences between symbolic logic and ordinary language has generated
attitudes ranging from complete mistrust of symbolic logic as relevant to non-artificial
languages to the position that ordinary language is not a proper vehicle for
the rigorous statement of scientific truths.
Interpretations of the relation of logic to language
Symbolic logic has been viewed by many Analytic philosophers as
providing the framework for an ideal or perfect language. This statement can be taken in two ways:
1. Russell and the early Wittgenstein thought of logic as revealing, in
a precise fashion, the real structure of any language. Any seeming departure from this structure in
ordinary language must therefore be attributed to the fact that its surface
grammar fails to reveal its real structure and is apt to be misleading. As a corollary, philosophers who have held
this view have often explained philosophical problems as arising from being
taken in by the surface features of the language. Because of the similarity of sentences such as
“Tigers bite” and “Tigers exist,” for example, the verb “to exist” may seem to
function, as other verbs do, to predicate something of the subject. It may seem, then, that existence is a
property of tigers just as their biting is. In symbolic logic, however, the symbolic
equivalent of the two sentences would be quite different; existence would not
be represented by a symbol for a predicate but by what is called the
existential quantifier, (∃ x), which means “There exists at least one x such
that...”
2. The other sense in which symbolic logic has been seen as the
framework of an ideal language is exemplified in the work of Rudolf Carnap, a 20th-century semanticist, who was concerned with
what the best language - especially the best for the purposes of science - is.
One distinctive feature of the formal language of Principia Mathematica is that it becomes,
when interpreted, a language of true-or-false statements. In ordinary language, on the contrary, one is
not restricted to statements of truths; in it one can also issue commands, ask
questions, make promises, express beliefs, give permission, and assert
necessities and possibilities. Consequently,
many philosophers have developed nonstandard logics that incorporate the non-assertoric features of language. Thus, various systems of logic have been
formulated and studied (see logic).
On the other side of the coin, many philosophers - most notably the
later Wittgenstein and those influenced by him - have thought that attempting
to put language into the straitjacket of a formal system is to falsify the way
that language works. Language performs a
multitude of tasks, and even among expressions that seem to be alike in the way
they function - those sentences, for example, that one might think are used
simply for expressing facts - examination of their actual use reveals many
differences: differences, for instance, in what is counted as showing them to
be true or false and in their relationships to other parts of language. Formal systems, according to this view, at
best oversimplify and at worst can lead to philosophical problems generated by
supposing that all language operates strictly according to a simple set of
rules. Accordingly, far from settling
philosophical disputes by getting underneath the misleading exterior of ordinary
language, formal systems add their own share of confusion.
Early History of Analytic Philosophy
During the last decades of the 19th century, English philosophy was
dominated by an absolute Idealism that stemmed from the German philosopher
G.W.F. Hegel. For English philosophy
this represented a break in an almost solid tradition of Empiricism. The seeds of modern Analytic philosophy were
sown when two of the most important figures in its history, Bertrand Russell
and G.E. Moore, broke with Idealism at the turn of the 20th century.
Absolute Idealism was avowedly metaphysical in the sense that its
adherents thought of themselves as describing, in a way not open to scientists,
certain very fundamental truths about the world. Indeed, what pass for truths in the sciences,
were, in their view, not really truths at all; for the scientist must,
perforce, treat the world as composed of distinct objects and can only describe
and state the relationships supposedly holding among them. But the Idealists held that to talk about
reality as if it were a multiplicity of objects is to falsify it; in the end
only the whole, the absolute, has reality.
In their conclusions and, most importantly, in their methodology, the
Idealists were decidedly not on the side of commonsense intuition. Thus, a
One can hardly claim that Analytic philosophers have universally
thought of themselves as on the side of common sense and much less that
metaphysical conclusions (on the ultimate nature of reality) are absent from
their writings. But there is in the
history of the Analytic movement a strong anti-metaphysical strain, and its
exponents have generally assumed that the methods of science and of everyday
life are the authentic ways of finding out the truth.
Founding fathers: Moore and Russell
The first break from the Idealist view that the physical world is
really only a world of appearances occurred when Moore, in a paper, “The Nature
of Judgment” (1899), argued for a theory of truth that implies that the
physical world has the independent existence that, apart from philosophical
theories, it is naively supposed to have. Though the theory was soon abandoned, it did
represent a return to common sense.
The influences on Russell and
Russell was a major influence on those who approached philosophical
problems armed with the technical equipment of formal logic, who saw the
physical sciences as the only means of gaining knowledge of the world, and who
regarded philosophy - if a science at all - as a deductive and a priori enterprise on a par with
mathematics. Russell's contributions to
this side of the Analytic tradition have been important and, in great part,
lasting.
Because of these two themes,
The Idealists were given to arguing for what, in
Although some commentators have seen
One of the recurring themes in philosophy is the idea that the subject
needs to be given a new methodology. Among
Empiricists this has often meant making it more scientific. From an early date, Russell enunciated this
viewpoint (which was not shared by
The question then arises of how philosophical analysis, which is
concerned with how men talk about the world, can presume to give any answers
about how the world is. The search for
an answer begins with the above-mentioned theory of descriptions - a theory
that seems to be closely tied to linguistic concerns. It will be recalled that Russell considered
that such definite descriptions as “the author of ‘On Denoting’” are not really
expressions used to refer to things in the world but that, instead, they make
the statements in which they occur into quite general propositions about the
world, to the effect that one and only one thing of a certain sort exists and
that it has a certain property. Because
there must be some way, however, of directly speaking of the things in the
world, Russell turned his attention to proper names. The name Aristotle, for example, does not seem
to carry any descriptive content. But
Russell argues, on the contrary, that ordinary names are really concealed
definite descriptions (“Aristotle” may simply mean “The student of Plato who
taught Alexander, wrote the Metaphysics,
etc.”). If a name had no descriptive
content, one could not sensibly ask about the existence of its bearer, for one
could then not understand what is expressed by a statement involving it. If “Bosco” were a
name in this sense (without any descriptive content), then merely to understand
the statement that Bosco exists or the statement that
Bosco does not exist presupposes that one already
knows what the name Bosco refers to. But then there cannot be any genuine question
about Bosco's existence, for just to understand the
question one must know the thing to which the name refers. Ordinary proper names, however - Russell,
Homer, Aristotle, and Santa Claus - as Russell pointed out, are such that it
makes sense to question the existence of their bearers. Thus, ordinary names must be concealed
descriptions and cannot be the means of directly referring to the particular
things in the world.
Names in the strict logical sense, then, are very rare; Russell, in
fact, suggests that in English the only possible candidates are the
demonstrative pronouns, this and that. Yet, if men are ever to talk about the actual
things in the world directly, there must be the possibility of such
demonstrative expressions underlying their language - in their private thoughts
about the world if not in their public language.
To this point, Russell had concluded that things in the world can be talked
about only through the medium of a special kind of name; in particular, one
about which no question can arise whether it names something or not. At this point there was a transition from
questions about the nature of language to results about the nature of the
world. Russell asked what sort of thing
it is that can be named in the strict logical sense, that can be known and
talked about, and that can tell a man something about the world. The important restriction is that no question
can arise about whether it exists or not. Ordinary physical objects and other people
seem not to fit this requirement.
In his search for something whose existence cannot be questioned,
Russell hit upon present experience and, in particular, upon sense data: one
can question whether he is really seeing some physical object - whether, for
example, there is a desk before him - but a person cannot question that he has
had visual impressions or sense data; thus, what a man can name in the strict
logical sense and what things he can actually talk about turn out to be the
elements of his present experience. Russell
therefore made a distinction between what can be known by acquaintance and what
can be known only by description; i.e.,
between those things the existence of which cannot be doubted and those about
which, at least theoretically, doubt can be raised. What is novel about Russell's conclusion is that
it was arrived at from a fairly technical analysis of language: to be directly
acquainted with something is to be in a position to give it a name in the
strict logical sense, and to know something only by description is to know only
that something uniquely fits the description.
Russell was not constant in his view about physical objects. At one point he thought that the observer must
infer their existence as the best hypothesis to explain his experience. Later he argued that they could be taken as
logical constructions out of sense data.
Logical atomism: Russell and the early Wittgenstein
The next important development in Analytic philosophy was initiated
when Russell published a series of articles entitled “Philosophy of Logical
Atomism” (1918–19), in which he acknowledged a debt to Wittgenstein, who had
studied with Russell before the war. Wittgenstein's
own work, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
(1922), which can also justly be said to present a logical atomism, turned out
to be not only tremendously influential on developments in Analytic philosophy
but also such a deep and difficult text that it has generated a growing body of
scholarly interpretation.
Russell's choice of the words logical atomism to describe this
viewpoint was, in fact, particularly apt. By using the word logical Russell meant to
sustain the position, described earlier, that through analysis - particularly
with the aid of the ideal structure provided by symbolic logic - the
fundamental truths about how any language functions can be revealed and that
this disclosure, in turn, would show the fundamental structure of that which
the language is used to describe. And by
using the word atomism Russell highlighted the particulate nature of the
results that his analyses and those of Wittgenstein seemed to yield.
On the linguistic level, the atoms in question are atomic propositions,
the simplest statements that it is possible to make about the world; and on the
level of what language talks about, the atoms are the simplest atomic facts,
those expressible by atomic propositions. More complex propositions, called molecular
propositions, can then be built up out of atomic propositions via logical
connectives such as “either... or...,”
“both... and...,” and “not...” - the truth-value of the molecular proposition
being in each case a function of the truth values of its component atomic
propositions.
Language, then, must break down, upon analysis, into ultimate elements
that cannot be analyzed into any other component propositions; and, insofar as
language mirrors reality, the world must then be composed of facts that are
utterly simple. Atomic propositions are
composed, however, of strings of names understood, as Russell had explained it,
in the strict logical sense; and atomic facts are composed of simple objects,
the things that could be thus named.
The details of the Russell–Wittgenstein view have fascinated philosophers
by the way in which they not only formed a coherent view but also seemed to
follow inexorably from the central assumptions. There are close connections between this
period, which was perhaps the most metaphysical in contemporary Analytic philosophy,
and traditional Empiricism. The
breakdown of language and the world into atomic elements had been one of the
prominent features in the classical Empiricists, John Locke, George Berkeley,
and David Hume. There was also a view of
the connection between language and the world - adumbrated in Russell but fully
evident in the Tractatus - which has been important
and influential, viz., the picture
theory, which holds that the structure of language mirrors that of the world. Analysis is important because ordinary
language does not show immediately, for example, that it is founded on the
atomic-molecular proposition model. Another
theme is that the deductive sciences - mathematics and logic - are based solely
on the way that language operates and cannot reveal any truths about the world,
not even about a world of entities called numbers. Finally, logical atomism, in Wittgenstein's
thought as opposed to Russell's, was at one and the same time metaphysical - in
the sense of conveying via pure
reasoning something about how the world is - and anti-metaphysical. Wittgenstein's Tractatus is unique in the
history of Empiricism in its acceptance of the fact that it is itself a
metaphysic and that part of its metaphysics is that metaphysics is impossible:
the Tractatus
says of itself that what it says cannot be coherently said. Only empirical science can tell a man anything
about the world as it is. Yet the Tractatus
apparently tells him, for example, about the relationship between language and
the facts of the world. For
Wittgenstein, the solution of this seeming paradox lies in his distinction
between what can be said and what can only be shown. There are certain things that can somehow be
seen to be so - in particular, the ways in which language is connected with the
world. The Tractatus could not
straightforwardly tell its readers about these matters - metaphysics cannot be
a body of facts expressible in any language - but the attempt to say these
things, done in the right way, can show them what it cannot coherently express.
Logical Positivism: Carnap and
Schlick
Wittgenstein's Tractatus
was both a landmark in the history of contemporary Analytic philosophy and
perhaps its most aberrant example. It
not only contained the most highly sophisticated metaphysics but also was an
important influence on the most anti-metaphysical of the positions taken by
Analytic philosophers, viz., that of
Logical Positivism, which was mainly developed by a group of philosophers,
scientists, and logicians who were centred in Vienna
and came to be known as the Vienna Circle. Among these, Rudolf Carnap
and Moritz Schlick have perhaps had the most
influence on Anglo-American philosophy, although it was an English philosopher,
A.J. Ayer - whose Language, Truth and
Logic (1936) is still the most widely read work of the movement in America
and England - who introduced the ideas of Logical Positivism to English
philosophy. Its main tenets have struck
sympathetic chords in the Analytic philosophers and are still important today,
even if in repudiation.
Above all else, Logical Positivism was anti-metaphysical; nothing can
be learned about the world, it held, except through the methods of the
empirical sciences. The Positivists
sought a method for showing both (1) when a theory that seemed to be about the
world was really metaphysical and (2) that such a theory was, in fact,
meaningless, and this they found in the principle of verification. In its positive form, the principle said that
the meaning of any statement that is really about the world is given by the
methods employed for verifying its truth or falsity - the only allowable
methods being, ultimately, those of observation and experiment. In its negative form, the principle said that
no statement could both be a statement about the world and have no method of
verification attached to it. Its
negative form was the weapon used against metaphysics and for the vindication
of science as the only possible source of knowledge about the world. The principle would, thus, class as
meaningless many philosophical and religious theories that purport to say
something about the world but provide no way of testing the truth of the
statements; for example, in religion it would render suspect the statement that
God exists, which, being metaphysical, would be, strictly speaking,
meaningless.
The principle of verification ran almost immediately into difficulties,
most of which were first raised by the Positivists themselves. The attempt to work out these difficulties
belongs to a more detailed study of the movement. It is sufficient to note here that these
problems were sufficient to make most subsequent Analytic philosophers wary of
appealing directly to the principle. It
has, however, influenced philosophical work in more subtle ways.
With the principle of verification in hand, the Positivists thought
that they could show a great many theories to be nonsense. There were several areas of discourse,
however, which failed the test of the principle but which were simply
impossible to rule out as concealed nonsense. Foremost among these disciplines were
mathematics and ethics. Mathematics (and
logic) could hardly be written off as nonsense. Yet their theorems are not verifiable by
observation and experiment; they are known, in fact, by pure a priori reasoning alone. The answer seemed to be provided in
Wittgenstein's Tractatus,
which held that the propositions of mathematics and logic are, in Kantian
terms, analytic; i.e., true-like the
statement “All bachelors are unmarried” - in virtue of the conventions that lie
behind the use of the symbols involved.
About ethics or, more precisely, about any statements
involving value judgments, the Positivist view was different, yet still of
lasting importance. In this view,
value judgments are not, like mathematical truths, necessary adjuncts to
science. But they cannot be put off as
nonsense; nor, obviously, are they true by definition or linguistic convention.
The usual view of the Positivists,
called emotivism, is that what look like statements
of fact (e.g., that one should not
tell lies) are really expressions of one's feelings toward a certain action;
thus, value judgments are not really true or false. The Positivist's position was that neither
mathematical nor ethical statements could be dismissed, as were metaphysical
propositions. Both had then to be
exempted from the principle of verification; and this was done by arguing that
their statements are not really about the world: mathematical truths are
conventions, and ethical statements are merely expressions of feelings. The divorce of ethics from science, once
again, reflects an old Empiricist theme, to be seen, for example, in David
Hume's dictum that from matters of fact one cannot derive a conclusion about
what ought to be nor vice versa.
“Philosophical Investigations”: the later Wittgenstein
A crucial turn that initiated developments that were destined to have a
lasting and profound effect on much of contemporary Analytic philosophy
occurred in 1929, when Wittgenstein, after some years in Austria during which
he was not philosophically very active, returned to England and established his
residence at Cambridge. There, the
direction of his thought soon shifted radically away from his Tractatus, and
his views became in many ways diametrically opposed to those of logical
atomism. Because he published none of
the materials of this period, his influence on other English philosophers - and
ultimately on those in all of the countries associated with Analytic philosophy
- spread by way of his students and those who heard him in the small groups to
whom he spoke at
Although Wittgenstein's thoughts ranged over almost the entire field of
philosophy, from the philosophy of mathematics to ethics and aesthetics, their
impact has been felt most, perhaps, where it has concerned the nature of
language and the relationship between the mental and
the physical.
In logical atomism, as shown above, language was conceived as having a
certain necessary and fairly simple underlying structure that it was the job of
philosophy to expose. Wittgenstein began
to tear away at this assumption. Language,
he now thought, is like an instrument that can be used for an indefinite number
of purposes. Hence, any effort to codify
how it must operate by giving some small set of rules would be like supposing
that there is some rigid necessity that a screwdriver (for instance) can be
used only to drive screws and forgetting that screwdrivers are also, quite
successfully, used to open jars and to jimmy windows. Language is a human institution that is not
bound by an outside set of rules - only by what men consider to be correct and
incorrect. And that, in turn, is not
really a matter for a priori theories
to consider.
The notion of a rule and what it means to follow a rule was especially
prominent in his writings. Several
concerns made this point of particular interest to Wittgenstein. In mathematics and logic, emphasis was being
placed on the rules for manipulating the symbolism. As has been seen, symbolic logic has also been
a model for the underlying structure of language. If this fact is coupled with the fact that
Russell and the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus saw language as reflecting these rules and with
the general Empiricist tradition that explains how language operates by each
person following internal rules and standards for the use of his words, the
picture of the system that Wittgenstein thought mistaken then emerges, and it
becomes clear why he placed the notion of a rule so centrally.
Natural languages, however, are significantly different in that one
does not first learn the rules and then use the language; indeed, prior to
learning the language, one would not know what to do with rules. Mathematics and logic are, in this sense, bad
models for language because they aim at setting out beforehand the rules and
principles that are subsequently to be used. They encourage the belief that language must
have a rigid structure and that, without rules, no language would be possible. The “rules” that one might plausibly discern
in the language that one speaks are not, as rules, already there, in a ghostly
way, guiding what one says; they are either generalizations from the finite
data of what is counted as correct or incorrect, or they are rules that, as
Wittgenstein metaphorically expressed it, one puts away in the archives - one
adopts the rule but only after the fact.
Following a rule, however, was a concept that Wittgenstein saw as
wrongly analyzed in many classical views about language. Thus, he cast irrevocable doubt on the
prevalent theory - typified best, perhaps, in John Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) - that to use an
expression meaningfully is to have in one's mind a standard or a rule for
applying it correctly. Against this
theme, Wittgenstein's point was that a rule by itself is dead - it is like a
ruler in the hands of someone who has never learned to use it, a mere stick of
wood. Rules cannot compel nor even guide
a person unless he knows how to use them; and the same is true about mental
images, which have often been thought to provide the standard for using
linguistic expressions. But if rules
themselves do not give life to words but require a similar explanation for what
gives them life, then there is a useless regress and no (philosophical)
explanatory value in the whole apparatus of internal rules and standards.
Relation between mental and physical events
In some respects, Wittgenstein made some significant breaks with the
Empiricist tradition - in his views about language and the explanation of the rigour of the deductive sciences. His treatment of the relationship between
mental events and physical events also represents an important departure. Empiricists generally have started from the
important assumption that what a person is immediately acquainted with is his
own sensations, ideas, and volitions, and that these are mental and not
physical; and, most importantly, that the things he knows immediately are
essentially private and inaccessible to others. For both Moore and Russell there then arose
the problem of how, in view of the privacy stressed by the sense-datum theory,
the world of physical objects could be known. Wittgenstein's attack on this viewpoint, which
has come to be known as “the private language” argument, has become well known,
partly because it was in this area that Wittgenstein presented what could most
easily be picked out as a more or less formal argument - one that could then be
analyzed and criticized in an analytic manner. Even in this case, however, his style of
writing was such that his precise formulation of the argument has become a main
source of controversy. Wittgenstein
argued that the notion of an utterly private experience would imply: (1) that
what goes on in the mental life of a person could be talked about only in a
language that that person alone whose mental life it was could understand; (2)
that such a private language would be no language at all (this has been the
main source of controversy); and (3) that the widely held doctrine that there
are absolutely private mental events cannot be intelligibly stated, because to
do so would be to suppose that one can publicly say something about what the
doctrine itself says cannot be mentioned in a language accessible to more than
one person.
The fact that Wittgenstein's argument against private language depends
essentially on the question, “What is it to follow a rule?” illustrates a
common characteristic of his writings, viz.,
that themes developed in one area of philosophy continually emerge in
apparently quite divorced areas. His
extraordinary ability to see a common source of difficulty in philosophical
problems that seem to be unrelated helps to explain his style of writing, which
seems at first sight to be a somewhat chaotic arrangement of ideas.
Analytic philosophy has also been attracted to a behaviouristic
view of mental phenomena that holds that such apparently private events as the
feeling of fear are not only not really private but also that they can be
identified with publicly observable patterns of behaviour.
The disposition toward empirical
science, with observation as its foundation, united with the observation that
the evidence men have of what goes on in the mental lives of other people must
come from what they see of their behaviour, has often
warred against the other inclination of Empiricism to regard the starting point
of all knowledge of the world, for each person, as being essentially private
sense experience. Wittgenstein has had
tremendous influence, however, in suggesting that these two extremes are not
the only alternatives. Yet attempts to
state how Wittgenstein could deny the privacy of experience without espousing
some form of behaviourism have not been very
successful. Sympathetic interpreters
have taken up the notion of “criteria,” used, but not developed in any detail,
by Wittgenstein. For mental states such
as fear, outward behaviour (e.g., running away, blanching, or cringing) does not constitute
what it is to be in that state, as behaviourism would
have it, but neither is it merely evidence of some completely private event. The problem has been to characterize the
relation between behaviour and mental states so that
the two are neither identical nor evidence one for the other, while still
acknowledging that a knowledge of the person's characteristic behaviour is essential to understanding the notion of a
certain mental state.
Those philosophers who might fairly be labelled
“Wittgensteinians,” who follow the methods that
Wittgenstein employed in his later period, should be distinguished from those
who have been influenced more indirectly by the
general trends and philosophical atmosphere that arose in large part from
Wittgenstein's work.
Close students of his ideas have tended to work chiefly on particular
concepts that lie at the core of traditional philosophical problems. As an example of such an investigation, a
monograph entitled Intention (1957),
by G.E.M. Anscombe, an editor of Wittgenstein's
posthumous works, may be cited as an extended study of what it is for a person
to intend to do something and of what the relationship is between his intention
and the actions that he performs. This
work has occupied a central place in a growing literature about human actions,
which in turn has influenced views about the nature of psychology, of the
social sciences, and of ethics. And, as
an extension of this British influence into the
After World War II,
It is true that Ryle did ask, in pursuit of
his method, some fairly detailed questions about when a person would say, for
example, that someone had been imagining something; but it is by no means clear
that he was appealing to ordinary language in the sense that his was an
investigation into how, say, speakers of English use certain expressions. In any case, the charge, often voiced by
critics, that this style of philosophizing trivializes and perverts philosophy
from its traditional function would probably also have to be levelled against Aristotle, who frequently appealed to
“what we would say.”
A powerful philosophical figure among postwar
Although the
Among those philosophers for whom symbolic logic occupies a central
position, W.V.O. Quine, Pierce professor of
philosophy at
The second important departure of Quine's
philosophy has been his attempt to show that science can be successfully
conducted without what he calls “intentional entities.” In contrast to “extensional,” used above as an
essential feature of standard symbolic logic, intentional entities include many
of the common items that Analytic philosophers often assume that they can talk
about without difficulty, such as the meanings of expressions, propositions, or
the property of certain statements (such as those of mathematics) of being
necessarily true. Quine's
program - as exemplified by Word and
Object (1960) - is intended in part to show that science can say everything
that it needs to say without using concepts that cannot be expressed in the
extensional language of standard logic. Quine's work, though by no means widely accepted, has made
Analytic philosophers at least wary of uncritically accepting certain of their
standard distinctions.
Since the mid-20th century, there has been an interaction between the
science of linguistics and Analytic philosophy. This did not occur before because Analytic
philosophers had almost always considered their study of language to be a priori and unconcerned with empirical
facts about particular languages. However,
a book by Noam Chomsky, a
It is not possible to forecast in any detail the future trends of
Analytic philosophy in Anglo-American and Scandinavian countries. It seems relatively certain, however, that the
two conceptions of the subject that stem from Moore and Russell will both
continue.
Analytic philosophers, mainly influenced by
Keith
S. Donnellan
Professor of Philosophy,
Author of articles in various philosophical journals,
particularly on the theory of reference.