The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
Surrogate Theories of
Art
Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 30 (2
Dec. 1969,
163-185.
Anyone who begins the study of
aesthetics is likely to be overwhelmed by the diversity of theories men have
devised to interpret their experiences of art. Indeed, it would seem that art means
different things to different people, and that there is as little agreement on
what art is as there is on the standards by which art is to be judged. Moreover, these two problems are not
unrelated, for the lack of success in resolving the one has contributed to the
failure in devising a solution to the other. Because of such widespread lack of
accord, it might seem as if any attempt to say something new on the subject
would be doomed in advance to the limbo of just another
opinion.
Consider the variety of proposals
that have already been made. Art,
according to some, is an attempt to represent through the use of a sensuous
medium the actual or ideal, the things we perceive or the underlying nature of
reality, by imitating their appearance or their formal structure. Others view art subjectively as the
manifestation of pleasure or emotion. At times art is interpreted as psychic
symbol; at other times it is seen as the symbol of feeling. It has been construed as a mode of
expression, and it has been rendered as a special language through which
communication can take place. It is
a free, self-gratifying activity resembling play, the manifestation of the inner
workings of the universal Will, or direct, intuitive vision. Moreover, each theory purports to give an
exclusive and comprehensive account of what art is; each seizes upon undeniable
features of art and casts them into a meaningful mold. It would appear almost as if the laws of
logic were here suspended, and that all the explanations, however incompatible
with one another, were collectively true.
Actually, no such startling move as
repudiating logic is necessary in order to have aesthetic theory. We must rather conduct a critical
examination of these various theories in the light of the phenomena to be
explained in order to clearly appraise the proposals each makes. Once we have made such a comparative
examination, it may then be possible to develop a comprehensive and systematic
account of the data of aesthetics that retains the valid insights of previous
attempts while avoiding their inadequacies. These inadequacies, as I shall attempt to
show in this
163
essay, are of two somewhat related
types. First, each theory commits
the same methodological error in being partial to some of the data to be
accounted for, yet offering itself as an exclusive and comprehensive
explanation. But more crucially,
each theory commits the identical logical error of equivocation by replacing the
explanandum or what is to be explained with a surrogate that inadequately
represents it. It is indeed
possible to avoid these difficulties by observing clear and, careful
methodological procedures. But we
shall better be able to indicate the direction of a sound theory in aesthetics
after we have make a critical examination of some of the major theories already
proposed.
The Criticism of Aesthetic
Theory
The criticism of theory in
aesthetics, like the criticism of theory in any other field of inquiry, may
follow any of several quite different directions. A theory may be judged and most often is
judged implicitly according to the different standards of the critic’s own
position, and on the basis of that position found lacking. A clear example of this is the
repudiation of representational painting by formalists like Clive Bell and Roger
Fry, who insist that the representational element in art is nonaesthetic. Yet their rejection of resemblance in
favor of purely pictorial features like color, line, and composition is made on
the basis of their own formalist theory and the sharp distinction they draw
between emotions about life evoked by the resemblance of forms to things outside
art and aesthetic emotion that arises from the contemplation of the form itself.
Imitation theory, however, which
justifies the creation of representational art, claims resemblance to be of
central aesthetic importance. Hence
the criticism of imitation is made by means of an alien theory, one which
consequently does not meet it on its own terms. The criticism of imitation from the
position of a still different theory occurs when Eugene Veron derides the artist
who is concerned with imitating as a person who is reducing himself to a copying
machine. Yet this follows from
Véron’s emotionalist position, though, according to which the artist should
attempt to express his individual feeling. Another illustration of this type of
critical disputation is the denial that the artist’s sincerity is aesthetically
relevant on the grounds that to claim so is to commit the genetic fallacy. Yet clearly the defender of this position
maintains it precisely because he is convinced that in this case not only is
reference to the conditions of a work’s creation pertinent, but. that an account
which ignores the artist’s personality is by that fact erroneous. Still another example, of this critical
approach is the denial that contemporary tragedy exists as a dramatic form
because no pertinent instance conforms to Aristotle’s classic
theory
164
of tragedy. Here, again, a theory of tragedy not
followed by much contemporary drama is used as the basis for judging it inferior
to classic drama.
A related type of criticism is that
made, not from the standpoint of an alternative theory of aesthetics alone, but
rather from a prior commitment to a position outside the domain of aesthetics
entirely. A famous illustration of
this is Plato’s attack on art from the standpoint of theory of knowledge. For him, art can at best only imitate the
appearance of things, which in its turn is but a reflection of rea1ity and so
art necessarily falsifies reality since it is thrice removed from it. Furthermore the- poet is also suspect,
since he purports to convey profound truths which he actually does not
comprehend, because he writes not from knowledge but solely from
inspiration. Moral grounds for
criticizing art also figure significantly. Plato’s criticism of Homer for describing
the jealous, lascivious, and criminal behavior of the gods is a case in point.
So, too, is Tolstoi’s moralistic
attack on art which does not communicate the religious perception of the times.
A similar direction is taken by
theories that derive their support from a particular religious allegiance. Here artistic strictures are inferred
from the doctrines or policies of a religious movement or institution, and art
that does not conform to them is censured. As illustrations of this one can cite the
implications for aesthetic theory as well as for artistic production of moral
standards derived from puritanism, by which art was regarded as frivolous and
unworthy, and was therefore discouraged if not dispensed with entirely. Another case of the same kind of
criticism was the promulgation of an official theory by the Council of Trent by
which the practice, and by implication the principles which guided such
practice, of composers of ecclesiastical music and painters of religious
subjects was to be regulated by theologians so as to serve a strictly
propagandistic religious purpose.
1
Related to this is the judgment of art in the
On the other hand, a position may be
judged on the grounds of difficulties relating to its internal consistency or
the adequacy of its concepts. This
type of criticism is found less often than the previous type, but
it
1. Vide
165
has considerably greater logical
justification. Here a theory is
regarded as an integral whole, and the concepts and principles which compose it
are analyzed in the light of their self-consistency and mutual
compatibility. This procedure for
judging a theory appears in the criticism of Suzanne Langer’s proposal that a
work, of art is a presentational symbol or C.J. Ducasse’s view that art is an
immediate symbol. These terms have
been attacked for being self-contradictory, since symbols mediate between an
object and a knower, and thus by their very nature; cannot be immediate or
direct. Another example of this way
of appraising a theory is illustrated by the criticisms that have been leveled
against .the views of Véron and Tolstoi because of difficulties that develop out
of their emphasis on the artist’s individuality or sincerity as the main
determinant of the value of his work.
In this case such critical remarks do not deny the aesthetic relevance of
individuality or sincerity but rather raise-legitimate questions about our
ability to determine whether or to what degree an artist succeeded in expressing
his personality or was sincere. The
observation that the only pertinent evidence of the artistic individuality or
sincerity of a painter or writer lies exclusively within the work he has
produced results in a virtual denial in practice of the usefulness of any
reference to these traits at all, since to be interested in the artistic
sincerity or individuality of the creator is to be concerned not with the work
but with the artist.
There exists yet a third
.alternative for the criticism of theory. It is a procedure encountered least
frequently, perhaps, but it is the one which offers the greatest positive value.
This type of criticism consists in
judging a theoretical proposal, not on the, basis of its internal consistency
nor by the external standard of a quite different position, but rather in the
light of some independent objective basis common to all theories in a given
field. This common basis is the
body of data which a theory is constructed to account for and which lies largely
outside the conceptual framework of any theory. Such data are capable of .being
formulated into factual statements and ordered into a more or less comprehensive
and organized arrangement by means of an appropriate theory. In the field of aesthetics, these data
are the phenomena associated with aesthetic experience in its different
connections, phenomena which form a relatively stable body of material which can
be formulated by the various kinds of aesthetic facts that it is possible to
identify. Here the arbitrariness of
judgment is reduced to a minimum, for the independence of the data provides a
firm support for the critical claims that are made. In this case, aesthetic theory is judged
not only by its internal consistency and conceptual adequacy. It is judged as well by its ability to
adequately explain the relevant aesthetic facts, to account for new data, and to
offer a satisfactory solution to the peculiar problems that have constantly
perplexed
166
every, aesthetic theory. One instance of’ this is the objection
voiced by Bernard Bosanquet and Joyce Cary to Croce’s identification of artistic
intuition .and expression. On the grounds that this does not take into account
the creative activity of the artist, who must work on his intuited idea and
embody it in the materials of his craft. Only then can he fix and preserve its
meaning, but this-takes much effort and skill.
It. is this last mode of criticism
that I shall pursue here. Rather
than throw up our hands in despair at the multitude of conflicting accounts of
art, we need only return to a common base from which to begin our inquiry, and
proceed from there to incorporate into a sounder framework the insights that
.have gone to compose seemingly irreconcilable theories.
I contend that the major attempts to explain art fail to be entirely satisfactory and convincing because they commit a common error in being false to the independent data of aesthetics. Let -me illustrate this contention by examining briefly some of the explanations of art that are proposed most frequently in order to shows what this common failing is, and then indicate how aesthetic theory might proceed so as to avoid such a difficulty. I am not concerned here with offering a comprehensive, account of each theory; hence, the partial descriptions which follow ought not to be regarded as parodies of entire theories. In identifying and dealing with what I call surrogate theories of art, I am interested only in extrapolating in every instance a primary feature which is central to each of these theories, and in showing how in every case these features function as surrogates for aesthetic experience, thus rendering inadequate and defective the theories in which they are leading elements. While many of the specific objections I shall make are already familiar, they combine here to form a critical judgment of significant generality. In following this procedure, I hope not only to contribute to the clarification and development of aesthetic theory, but also to prepare the way for a theoretical proposal that aims to avoid the common defect of the positions considered here. 2
Those theories which interpret art
as an attempt to provide an accurate representation of the objects and events we
experience are undoubtedly the most obvious instances of surrogate theories.
Art, according to
the
2. Dewey embarks on a similar
criticism of various theories of art that distort by seizing upon a particular
aspect of experience in Art as Experience (1934), Ch. XII. The proposa1 suggested here is developed
systematically in Arnold Berleant, The Aesthetic Field
(
167
imitation theories, must be
“realistic” and depict its subject truly. The novel, the drama, the film must all
be faithful mirrors of life and provide an accurate portrayal of human events:
the improbable must be excluded.
So, too, must the fine arts clearly represent their subjects. A painting must be a recognizable image
and look like whatever it is portraying; a statue must resemble its model. Fidelity to the subject of the work is
the keynote.
Mimesis may, of course, assume
various forms. It may demand
exactitude of representation, literal accuracy, as exemplified in Leonardo’s
insistence that “That painting is the most praiseworthy which is most like the
thing represented.” To this end,
the artist may try to portray things as they really are by recording their exact
proportions and details. Alternatively, he may attempt to imitate
their appearance, and consequently employ devices like perspective and modeling
which are designed to create an illusion of reality, and which culminate in the
techniques developed by the impressionists to better “imitate” the effects of
light and atmosphere. Or as during
the neoclassical period, mimesis may be directed toward depicting universal
properties, the essential nature or form of things. Here the artist is selective in what he
represents, revealing the universal in the form of .a particular. This version of imitation, unlike the
preceding, can be accommodated to provide an account of music, dance, and
architecture. The mimesis in dance
may be of idealized action, or it may take on metaphysical overtones in
imitating the form of beauty by emulating its balance and harmony in musical
forms and architectural structures. Again, as in ‘the “theory of the
affections” ‘popular in Kant’s time, music may be explained as imitating the
diverse agitations of the soul.
Despite their apparent plausibility,
however, mimetic theories no longer seem to offer a satisfactory account of art.
In its more sophisticated versions,
imitation proceeds beyond direct representation. By sanctioning illusion, it leads to the
toleration of distortion, but in doing this places the realistic thesis of the
theory in question. Moreover, the
attempt to penetrate beneath the surface appearance of things directs imitation
theories past perception into metaphysics, leaving outward resemblance far
behind. Further still, a concern
with the inward movement of a troubled soul ends by discarding any pretense of
imitation in favor of more direct attention to emotion. And so, mimesis ends by replacing
itself.
This is not the place for a full
discussion of the theoretical difficulties of imitation theories of art. Yet from the viewpoint elaborated here,
these theories suffer from a serious defect which follows from their very
nature. By focusing the attention
of both the creator and the perceiver beyond the work of art to the objects and
events represented, mimesis interprets the activity of art as concerned with
something outside the perceptual. Imme-
168
diacy of the aesthetic
situation. The extraaesthetic
obligations of the representational object force it beyond the experience of
art, and that experience is itself understood, and appraised by being related to
something outside of and-apart from itself, namely, the thing being imitated.
The point here is that the object
being imitated acts as a surrogate for the inherently aesthetic character of the
original experience. By leading the
perceiver toward itself, away from the art work and outside the aesthetic
situation, it substitutes a nonaesthetic object for the one that functions
aesthetically. 3
Furthermore, mimesis judges the
artistic product,by standards of accuracy or literal truth. By employing cognitive perception as
their model, imitation theories apply the postanalytic standards, of the
knowledge process to the preanalytic experience of art. In this case, the cognitive object
becomes a surrogate for the aesthetic object. Thus in both respects, aesthetic
perception is replaced by a nonaesthetic surrogate, either by the object or from
represented, or by cognitive perception. 4
To seek and be guided by feeling in
attending to art continues to be a motive popular among artists’ and their
audiences alike. The affective
force of art works is taken, too, as the standard by which they are judged.
Widely held in diverse forms as
emotionalist theories are, however, they commit an error which resembles that of
the imitation theories, although they do so less in their own right than in the
ways in which they are interpreted and elaborated.
That an emotional component can be
discerned in the experience of art, as in the experience of almost anything,
cannot, I think, be seriously
3. Edmund Burke reveals the final
inadequacy of the imitation theory when he admits that an audience would empty a
theater in which a most elaborate tragedy was about to be performed, if they
heard that a state criminal of high rank was about to be hanged nearby. Cf. A Philosophical Enquiiry...
(New York, 1958), p. 47.
The complete antithesis of this
occurs in Sartre’s suggestive observation that “Sculpture suggests movement,
painting depth or light. Calder
suggests-nothing; he captures and embellishes true, living, movements. His mobiles signify nothing, refer to
nothing other than themselves; they simply are, they are, absolutes.” Essays in Aesthetics” (New York:
Philosophical Library, 1963), p. 79.
4. My second argument here rests on
the supposition that aesthetic perception is preanalytic and therefore radically
different from the cognitive process. While the substantiation of this claim is
reserved for another place the view that art is noncognitive is a central thesis
of this essay. Here it is only
necessary to admit, however, that art is different from the literal
knowledge-gathering activity of the sciences. This is a much milder form of the thesis,
and is rarely disputed today.
disputed. Moreover, in ascribing major importance
to the experiential factor in aesthetics, emotionalist theories of- art
constitute a significant advance beyond the imitation theories. Yet this accomplishment is soon countered
by the way in which the emotional side of aesthetic experience is described and
misinterpreted by widely accepted explanations of how emotion functions in
art.
The emotional ingredient in
experience is but lamely described by general terms like “joyful,” “sorrowful,”
“exhilarating,” “depressing,” and “exciting.” Any one of these epithets might
justifiably be applied to an indefinite number of otherwise remarkably
dissimilar art works, and it helps but little to resort to strings of
descriptive terms. Furthermore, the
vocabulary in which we talk about emotions is impoverished in contrast with the
richness of emotional experience. In ascribing a single such term or even a
combination of them to a work of art, one succeeds more in misrepresenting and
distorting than in characterizing it. How insipid is the description of a
musical composition as sad, tragic, amusing or cheerful! Moreover, to select a single type of
emotional reaction like pleasure is merely to seize upon a common kind of
affective experience and generalize it to cover all cases of aesthetic
response. Besides being
uninformative, reference to pleasure unduly limits the variety and scope of
aesthetic experience by confining it to a single facet of its emotional aspect.
Nor is the difficulty overcome by
referring to a peculiarly aesthetic emotion which is aroused by the significant
formal relations of the work. To
describe aesthetic experience as an occurrence characterized by an “aesthetic
emotion” is to beg the question of its identifiable feature. It assumes that such experience is
emotional in quality and yet tells us nothing positive about it, merely
isolating a peculiarly aesthetic quality of the experience from other emotional
tones of human experience, and maintaining that it is entirely unlike the
emotions of “life.”
At most, the explanation of art by
means of one or many emotions offers but a partial account. The emotional- element is just one factor
that is discernible when the experience of art is reflected upon. Other features may be present, such as
interest, recognition of motifs, forms, or ideas, acute perceptual awareness,
intuitive insight, perception of relationships, and the like. Moreover, during the experience and
before reflecting on it, the emotional component is fused with all the other
aspects of experience. To
characterize the totality of an experience by its emotional component is at best
to indulge in synecdoche by mistaking a part of aesthetic experience for the
whole experience; to do so at worst aborts it. In either case, emotion becomes a
surrogate for full aesthetic experience.
Perhaps only by using a term with
great inclusiveness, as. when Suzanne
170
Langer employs “feeling” to mean
“everything that can be felt, from physical sensation, pain and comfort,
excitement and response, to the most complex emotions, intellectual tensions, or
the steady feeling-tones of a conscious human life,”
5 can one hope
to avoid falsification. Such
generality, however, makes feeling equivalent to the entire range of human
experience of which we may become aware, and goes well beyond emotionalism.
Furthermore, a notion as broad as
this does little to help us account for the emotional quality of specific art
works, nor does it yet explain the way in which feeling is manifested or the
significance of art in human emotional experience. We are thus led to those theories which
interpret art as expressing, communicating; or symbolizing
emotion.
One of the most common ways of
accounting for art in current discussions is to explain it as a mode of
expression. We often speak of a
painting or a symphonic movement as being expressive, or we ask what the author,
painter, or composer is trying to express in a work. Indeed, we sometimes wonder what the work
itself expresses. Because of their
popularity, the expression theories have received extensive discussion. It is not my object here to present a
thoroughgoing critique of the various forms of expression theory. I do wish to raise, however, what seem to
me to be crucial objections against any attempt to characterize art as
expressive. For in whatever way
they are formulated, theories of art as expression entail one or another kind of
misrepresentation.
Art has been interpreted by
expression theories as expressing different kinds of things. Some writers cite emotion, others ideas,
and still others images as the things being expressed. Each of these proposals, however,
presents certain difficulties.
Most frequently, perhaps, expression
theories speak about the expression of emotion. Yet here we cannot avoid the conclusion
that such a theory of art is unsatisfactory in that it misdirects our
attention. For this version of
expression explains art, not by the art object nor by the full experience of
art, but beyond both either to the emotion being expressed (in which case our
criticisms of emotionalist theories are pertinent) or to its source in the
artist’s impulses, motives, and needs. Either alternative, though, leaves us
with a surrogate theory. The first
does this by reducing the fullness of aesthetic experience to an abstracted
emotional component, and the second by taking us outside art to the biography of
the artist.
5. Problems of Art (New York,
1957). Reprinted in M. Rader, ed., A
Modern Book of Esthetics, 3rd ed. (Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1960), p.
249.
171
Sometimes it is argued, however,
that art expresses ideas rather than emotions. Still, to say that art expresses ideas
directs our attention away from the perceptual qualities of the aesthetic object
and our direct encounter with it, and focuses instead on the belief being
expressed. This shifts our interest
from the features which make our experience of art intrinsically and uniquely
interesting, and occupies us with matters quite independent of any aesthetic
concern. Did Brutus really betray
Caesar, as Shakespeare suggests? Was the massacre on
To say, finally, that rather than
expressing emotion or ideas, art expresses images in any literal sense, leads us
to interpret art through its effect on the imagination. This tends to take us away from the art
object and beyond aesthetic perception to the images the art work excites. Now it is undeniable that imaginative
processes play a necessarily large role in the experience of certain arts. Literature, in particular, relies heavily
on an imaginative response. Yet it
is equally undeniable that the images stimulated, especially in connection with
other arts, are frequently irrelevant to the art work that acts as stimulus.
Music and painting are all too
often used merely to set in motion a train of daydreams or fantasies which have
no connection with the art objects that excite them. Their imaginative appeal here revives
difficulties similar to those from which imitation theories were seen to suffer.
For by directing our attention away
from experience centering on the art object, the images act as surrogates for
aesthetic perception.
Furthermore, there are some general
difficulties which all versions of the expression theory entail. This manner of accounting for art focuses
on only a part of the situation in which art occurs. It calls attention first to the art
object in an attempt to understand its expressive qualities. Yet by its interest in the expressiveness
of the object, this theory moves quite naturally to the ‘origin’ of such
qualities, and thus tends to lead us still farther away from the art object,
centering our concern more with its genesis and the artist who created it than
with the object itself. Here
expression becomes the combined result of the intention of the artist
and
172
his productive activities. But in doing this, the expression theory
incurs in some measure the intentional fallacy and, more generally, the genetic
fallacy. By directing attention to
the origin of the art object and to the artist’s expressive motives, a surrogate
is introduced for the functioning of the art object in the aesthetic situation.
Etienne Gilson put the point well
when he observed, “What makes self-expression beautiful is not that it is
expression, but rather that, taken in itself, it is a thing of beauty enjoyable
for its own sake.” 6
Yet our aesthetic concern is
properly with art rather than biography, and the farther we remove ourselves
from the art object and the situation in which it functions, the more distant we
become from any strictly aesthetic interest. Even by returning to the object of art so
that we may examine it for its expressive clues, the difficulties with this
theory remain. For we well may ask,
How can art express anything? Without going into semantic details, are
we not speaking metaphorically here of aesthetic experience? Is not calling an object expressive
simply a way of testifying to the effectiveness with which the work functions in
our experience? Clearly, to speak
of an object as being expressive or as expressing something is to
interpret it animistically. The
object is not expressive nor is it expressing anything; it is
we who regard it as possessing great import. The object itself simply is. And so expression theories oblige us to
return to the experience of art.
These difficulties are not overcome
when art is interpreted as communication rather than expression. This approach encompasses a wide variety
of positions, from Croce’s subsumption of art as an intuitive-expressive
activity under the general theory of linguistic to the popular description of
music as “the language of the emotions.” While all such attempts to provide an
account of art do see it as a species of human activity, they fail to supply a
satisfactory explanation of the distinctive features of the experience to which
it gives rise. For they assume that
art performs the same kind of function that language does, and by interpreting
the aesthetic activity as a communicative one, the experience of art is again
replaced by a surrogate. This is
because language is a device for the embodiment and communication of meaning
through the use of symbols. Except
for special occasions, language .is rarely reflexive. Its value is preeminently
instrumental. Intrinsically,
language is relatively unimportant, and it seldom concentrates attention on
itself except when
6. The Arts of the Beautiful
(New York: Scribners, 1965) p. 61.
173
it is used as an artistic medium or
becomes the subject matter of a linguistic science or philosophy. How different is this from a description
of the function of art. Whereas
language points beyond itself, the art object plays a key role in aesthetic
experience and becomes the focal point of intrinsic perceptual awareness. Indeed, the explanation of art on an
analogy with language is one of the most widespread, and one of the most
mendacious theories; it distracts us from the aesthetic and leads us to expect
from art that which it is least capable of supplying.
Those theories which seize on the
surface resemblance of art to linguistic activity invariably attribute meaning
to art. Yet again, in any literal
sense, this is foreign to aesthetic experience. To say that a painting or a sonata has
meaning refers at most, not to the work itself, but to the perceiver’s response.
It is nothing more than what the
percipient projects onto the art work. To speak of meaning is to refer literally
to a cognitive feature; any other sense is metaphorical. Yet if anyone should seek information
from a poem, we would not regard him as exhibiting an aesthetic interest or
response. Indeed, cognitive meaning
is generally regarded as being embodied in statements or propositions, and these
are independent of specific languages and their peculiar traits. But in art it is the individual, unique
characteristics which are indispensable. Whatever meaning an art work may be said
to have is inseparable from these features. As A. C. Bradley so well expressed it,
the poet “meant what he said, and said what he meant.... Meaning they [a
Beethoven symphony or a Turner picture] have, but what meaning can be
said in no language but their own.”
7
Any change in the work changes
its meaning. Furthermore, Bradley
denies meaning in its literal, cognitive sense.
Moreover, those attempts to rescue
the notion of meaning by construing it in an emotive rather than a cognitive
sense also fail to satisfy. Besides
encountering the difficulties of the emotionalist theories, the reference to
emotive “meaning” is at best metaphorical. It reveals the pervasive presence of an
intellectualist bias which insists that emotion be construed in cognitive
terms.
To attribute meaning to art calls
attention at most to its importance, to the significance of the experience to
which art gives rise. But reference
to meaning in art, like reference to language, tends to be misleading and ends
by replacing art with a surrogate. Art, however, must be taken on its own
terms. Archibald MacLeish’s “Ars.
Poetica” captures this insight, especially in its famous lines, “A poem should
not mean/But be.” 8 It is what it is as it is. No more, no less.
7. “Poetry for Poetry’s Sake,”
reprinted in Rader, op. cit., p.
321.
8. Collected Poems; p. 41.
174
Symbolic theories of art offer
perhaps the most salient examples of surrogate theories. While employed with great ingenuity and
considerable insight by Cassirer, Panofsky, Langer and others, art, when
interpreted as symbolic form, becomes the emissary of meaning. Here again art leaves the aesthetic and
enters the realm of the cognitive.
9 This is equally true of all such theories, whether art
be taken as the symbol of the artist and his times, as a religious symbol, as an
emotional symbol, as a psychoanalytic symbol, or as a poetic
archetype.
It is curious to observe the various
ways in which the need to attribute meaning to art results in the ad hoc
attachment of symbolic significance to it.
I. A. Richards, even while recognizing the prior importance of the
sensory aspect of most poetry, interprets poetry as mainly the evocative use of
signs, particularly by means of metaphors.
10 Langer’s suggestion is perhaps more tenable when she
describes art as an extended metaphor or prominence to the directness of the
aesthetic response, is drawn into the immediacy of experience
11 And yet the closer Langer comes to relating art to the
direct perception of experience, the less art functions as a symbol and the more
it asserts itself in its own right. The commitment to a communication theory
combines with the awareness of the direct immediacy of aesthetic experience to
lead her to the ironically self-contradictory notion of art as a presentational
symbol. And even Ducasse, who gives
prominence to the directness of the aesthetic response, is drawn into the same
odd posture when he interprets the aesthetic object as the “immediate symbol” of
an emotion, so embodying it that we receive the “taste” of that emotion by
directly apprehending the symbol.
12
Theories of art which employ the
notion of a symbol, as in those developed by Langer and Ducasse, so distort the
usual meaning of symbol
9. This is clearly illustrated in
Panofsky’s analysis of meaning in painting into four layers: recognizable
objects and events (recognition involves an associative process of cognition,
relating past learning to present experience), the style of a period
(distinguishing style requires a body of scholarship which must be employed in
the cognitive process of analyzing a work), allegorical figures or types
(awareness of universal types requires the use of abstractive techniques), and
finally the intrinsic, philosophical significance which embodies its symbolic
function (this involves fitting art into the schema of a philosophic system).
Cf. Studies in Iconology
(New York, Oxford University Press, 1939), p. 16. According to the criticisms developed in
this essay the significance of painting on each of these levels lies outside the
object and the experience it elicits.
10. “Many, if not most, of the
statements in poetry are there as means to the manipulation and
expression of feelings and attitudes.” Practical Criticism, (New York,
Harcourt, Brace, 1929), p. 186.
11. Problems of Art, in Rader,
op. cit., pp. 254-255.
12. Art, the Critics, and You
(New York, 1944), p. 179.
175
that they appear more concerned to
defer to the common association of art with meaning that so typifies aesthetic
intellectualism than to be controlled in their account by the experience they
are supposed to explain. 13
There is a directness to the experience
of art which the more perceptive symbolic theories feel forced to acknowledge,
and it is this immediacy which is incompatible with describing art as language
or symbol. The linguistic theory of
Croce reflects the identical influence, for he makes much of the intuitive
individuality of aesthetic forms and emphasizes the untranslatability of
aesthetic expressions. 14
What Langer and Ducasse seem to be saying in a
circuitous way is not that art functions as a symbol ordinarily does, but rather
that the art object is not complete and self-sufficient in itself. It must instead be regarded as a factor
in the larger context of experience. This observation is both correct and
important, but it is misrepresented by a theory that through its literal content
removes the art object from the involvement it properly has in aesthetic
experience. At best these descriptions are merely suggestive
metaphors, but there is no place in theory for metaphor. A theoretical account .properly should
provide a literal explanation. As a
whole, then, the communication theories are surrogate theories. They commit the error of confusing the
reflective analytic, symbol-using attitude and activity with the inherently
noncognitive. aesthetic.
13. For a general criticism, of such
semiotic theories, especially that of Charles W. Morris, see Richard Rudner, “On
Semiotic Aesthetics,” Journal Of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 10 (1951), 67-77.. Rudner also
makes a good defense of nonsemiotic aesthetics, particularly against theories of
expression, in “Some Problems of Non-Semiotic Aesthetic Theories,” same journal,
15, 298-3 10. The statements
of artists (and their expositors) contain many attempts to express the
directness of aesthetic experience, although they are often couched in the
terminology of conventional theoretical accounts. Henry Moore, for example, has written,
“For me a work must first have a vitality of its own. I do not
mean a reflection of the vitality of life, of movement, physical
action, frisking, dancing figures and so on, but that a work can have in it a
pent-up energy, an intense life of its own, independent of the object it may
represent. When work has this
powerful vitality we do not connect the word beauty with it. (Italics mine.) And Herbert Read, developing Moore’s
point, explains, “The terms of the debate [between beauty and vitality need
careful definition; but obviously the whole scope of art is altered if you make
it, instead of the more or less sensuous symbolization of intellectual ideals,
the direct expression of an organic vitalism. No doubt intellectual elements will enter
into the choice and elaboration of the images which the intellect selects to
represent its ideals, but the difference is about as wide as is humanly
possible.” (Italics mine.) (From
Henry Moore, “The Sculptor’s Aims” in Herbert Read, ed., Unit One, 1934,
p. 30; and Herbert Read,
The Philosophy of Modern Art, New York, 1952, p. 207. Both were reprinted :in. M. Weitz; ed.,
Problems in Aesthetics,
14. Benedetto Croce, Aesthetic
(New York, 1958),
pp. 67, 68.
176
I believe it can readily be shown
how all the major theories of art embroil themselves in difficulties similar to
those just described. It is not
necessary, however, to provide an exhaustive account of all such theories to
establish the point of my criticism.
Let me conclude, then, with a final example of a surrogate theory, a
theory to which it might seem difficult to object because it, more than any I
have discussed so far, endeavors to explain art on its own peculiar terms, and
thus arrive at a more authentic statement than earlier theories of what art is
about.
Formalism came as a revolutionary
corrective to a history of misleading and unquestioned assumptions about art.
Never before had the representative
character of the graphic and plastic arts so been challenged, at least in
theory. Yet Roger Fry, Clive Bell
and others insisted on the startling position that the representational element
in art was nonaesthetic and, indeed, that it distracted the perceiver from the
genuinely pictorial qualities such as line, color, mass, and plane that he ought
properly to be concerned with. Several decades earlier, Eduard Hanslick
had applied a similar standard to music, insisting that the listener occupy
himself exclusively with musical elements like sound and motion, and not use
music as an emotional stimulus. Most recently, the New Criticism in
literature also bears an affinity to the same general position in its emphasis
on the literary use of language with its levels of meaning, its associations,
rhythms and formal arrangements. Despite the importance of its insights,
though, formalism establishes both too much and too
little.
Formalism developed as an attack on
and an alternative to the pervasive influence of the imitation theory and its
condemning application to modem nonrepresentational art. In rejecting representation entirely,
however, formalism construed it exclusively in terms of a theory of simple
imitation. Yet it is possible to
keep the entire recognizable image within the painting itself and to regard its
significance as wholly determined by its place in the painting. Instead of representation or resemblance,
which imply reference to something outside the painting that is reproduced in
it, we can speak rather of presentation or semblance, in which the image is
viewed in its own right and not primarily as a sign of something else. Certainly one can regard recognizable
images as doing more than recording appearances or reminding one of outside
associations. Within the painting
the image is something quite different from what it would be when regarded only
as a reminder. It may function to
inform and enhance the total perceptual effect by introducing ideas,
associations and feelings that are transformed in being embodied in an art
object, and
177
which add to and benefit from the
peculiarly painterly qualities of the medium.
Hence formalism excludes from the
data of aesthetics much that need not be cast out on aesthetic grounds. While it is certainly not true that all
art should be representational, it does not follow that the converse of this,
that representational painting may be art, is likewise false. Representational art may be aesthetic in
that very respect. The range of
objects aesthetically regarded includes both. Formalism then establishes more than it
need. It is sufficient to justify
abstract art without excluding the representational in the process. One difficulty with formalism, then, is
that the nonrepresentational form becomes a surrogate for the whole range of
aesthetically perceivable images.
Formalism also errs in proving too
little. In their anxiety to
restrict attention to purely artistic elements, the formalists, together with
sympathetic minds from literature and music, seem inclined to focus almost
entirely on the art object. Their
attention is wrapped up in the pictorial qualities of the painting, the literary
features of the poem or novel, or the structural components of the musical
composition. Certainly this is an
improvement over a theory such as emotionalism, in which the art object is apt
to be forgotten in the concern with the feelings of the person appreciating
it.
The insistence that we confine our
aesthetic attention to the painting, poem, or musical work, per se, is unduly
limiting, however. That they should
be the center of the perceiver’s attention does not mean that other factors may
not play an important role in our appreciation of art. There are connections with experience
beyond the perception of form alone that maybe aesthetically relevant. The art object does not exist in a world
by itself; it rather occupies a place in the broad matrix of human experience.
Art’s indictment of social evils,
its commentary on human relationships, its championing of new ideas and causes
all suggest connections, more inclusive and profound than the formalists are
willing to admit. Theirs is an
inverted romanticism that would keep out the philistine fingers of culture,
history, and technology from the sacred grove of art.
It might seem that
178
ception to the formal elements in a
work of art. We must conclude,
then, that in this respect, too, formalism is a surrogate theory. It replaces the full scope of the social
origins, experience, and relevance of art with a sacrosanct object protected by
the hallowed walls of the museum and nurtured in the sensitive soul of the
esthete.
Contributions of the
Surrogate Theories
Despite the force of these
criticisms, it is not my contention that all the theories examined here, while
misleading are entirely false. Indeed I am ready to recognize their
individual merits, for theories that have been taken as seriously as has each of
these by so many perceptive minds cannot be summarily dismissed. Each, in fact, contains a true and
important insight. Yet because this
observation is part of a surrogate theory, it is obscured and often
misinterpreted. It would be useful
at this point to suggest in a preliminary way where the contribution of each of
these theories lies.
In the imitation theories, it is not
nature, appearance, or reality which must be slavishly emulated. Art, nonetheless, must be “true of life”
in that it must bring us into direct contact with the immediacy of our
experience. Art is not the occasion
for an isolated esoteric mode of response, open only to the initiate and
unconnected with anything else. The
encounter with art is more than a magical escape from life; it is more than a
peculiar sort of occurrence, independent of the remainder of human interest.
On the contrary, successful art
evokes a response from the reservoir of man’s readiness to react to the events
in which he is involved. Art,
indeed, has a deep and important connection with the life of man. Obviously this varies with the particular
art and with the style or movement being considered. Nineteenth century realism in literature,
for example, emphasizes the closeness of this relationship, and Georg Lukács’
observation was a perceptive one when he noted that “Great literature…, reveals
a ‘piece of life’ providing more truthful and more profound reflection of
reality than is generally obtained in ordinary life.” Clearly the same rationale holds for
those arts embodying social criticism. Pop art, to take a recent example, rests
entirely on this connection with the experiences of popular culture. It can best be understood not for its
formal qualities but for the implied social criticism of its subject matter.
In this respect it succeeds
admirably in forcing us to see the oppressive vulgarity of our commercial
culture. It is even true that the
sensory awareness of the most stylized and abstract art objects conveys
associations for us. This is
acknowledged by even the most ardent defenders of modern nonrepresentational
art. Ortega y Gasset admits this
when he observes that “perhaps in the most abstract
179
ornamental line there vibrates as in
disguise a tenacious reminiscence of certain ‘natural’ forms.” Even Roger Fry, after vehemently
attacking representational painting and arguing for the aesthetic relevance of
only formal, qualities, comes in intellectual honesty to admit a tenuous
connection of art with the emotions of life.
15 There would then seem to be an intimate connection that
art has, not necessarily with the appearances of things, but rather with our
experiences of them. Art can
intensify the rest of human experience, and this experience can, in turn,
enhance the significance of art. It
is the whole man that experiences art, and art influences the whole
man.
The insights of the other theories
we have considered are more obvious. By involving the personal human response
as an essential component of the aesthetic situation, the emotionalist theories
have provided a contribution of signal importance in the understanding of art.
Art can hardly be understood with
any accuracy apart from the way it functions in human experience, and the
emotional element in experience is clearly undeniable. The emotionalist theories, then, rightly
move us away from any position that would elevate and eternalize art objects by
removing them from their dependency on experience. They return art squarely to its human
setting.
Finally, the theories of art as
expression and communication make us aware of the fact that art involves much
more than subjective experience. Art is a social event. It possesses social significance through
the community of human experience. This is an essential factor in the
understanding of art, one which no comprehensive theory can afford to
overlook.
There is, then, significant merit in
each of these theories. In each
case, however, the insight is obscured by the surrogate character of the way the
theory is developed. It is clear,
however, that a full account of art must retain these insights while at the same
time avoiding their distortions.
15. “Now, from our definition of this
pure beauty, the emotional tone is not due to any recognizable reminiscence or
suggestion of the emotional experiences of life; but I sometimes wonder if it
nevertheless does not get its force from arousing some very deep, very vague,
and immensely generalized reminiscences.
It looks as though art had got access to the substratum of all the
emotional colors of life; to something which underlies all the particular and
specialized emotions of actual life. It seems to derive an emotional energy
from the very conditions of our existence by its relation of an emotional
significance in time and space. Or
it may be that art really calls up, as it were, the residual traces left on the
spirit by the different emotions of life, without however recalling the actual
experiences, so that we got an echo of the emotion without the limitation and
particular direction which it had in experience.” Roger Fry, The Hogarth Essays,
1924, “The ‘Artist’ and
Psychoanalysis.”
180
It is possible to discover in the
history of aesthetic theory a growing tendency to handle the phenomena of art as
the subject of inquiry that is autonomous. The sequence of theories that have been
proposed is not a circumstantial sequence but rather a developmental one. It can be seen to reflect the cumulative
development of our understanding of aesthetic perception. The earlier theories like mimesis tended
to confuse the aesthetic function of recording appearances and historical
events, and preserving and communicating information.
16 This continued even when the imitation was ideal rather
than real, for art then served the purpose of leading men to the apprehension of
a higher, spiritual order of being, and impressing upon them a moral ideal.
The rise of the emotionalist
theories signified that art was more important than before, that it was doing
something nothing else could do. These theories recognized the place of
originality and creativity. They
discovered the personal element in artistic perception and the intrinsic
importance of the experience of art. For the first time art was seen as
something valuable in its own right which had to be regarded disinterestedly.
By stressing the role of the
creative artist and the personal response to art, the emotionalist theories led
to the emancipation of the artist and perceiver from the manifestly nonaesthetic
concerns of the imitation theories. Yet emotionalism swung theory too much in
the opposite direction so that it became excessively concerned with matters of
personality, motives, biography, and other questions of psychological and
historical interest. Thus the
advent of formalism served as a corrective by directing our attention back to
the purely aesthetic features of the art object. Whereas emotionalism led to the
emancipation of the artist, formalism achieved the emancipation of the art
object and its medium. Now the
object had become independent and had to be regarded for its purely artistic
qualities.
This succession of theories clearly
does not present a. series of logical alternatives for the explanation of art.
We have already noted in the
preceding section how each can be seen to contribute its own peculiar insight
into what art is about. Yet the
sequence of theories reveals a highly significant trend toward interpreting art
on its own terms, toward freeing it from subordinance to religious, moral,
cognitive, and political influences, and is therefore of considerable
significance. Yet the emancipation
of aesthetic theory is still far from complete. The way in which art is approached, the
fashion in which it is described, and the manner in which
16. This is aptly illustrated by the
observation in Samuel Johnson’s Preface to Shakespeare that “The end of
writing is to instruct; the end of poetry is to instruct by
pleasing.”
181
it is interpreted all testify, as we
have tried to show in ‘this’ paper, to the incompleteness of its
liberation.
Undoubtedly one of the greatest
difficulties in interpreting the nature of art results from the need to give a
clear description of a mode of experience dissimilar in certain key respects to
every other. It is this difficulty
which leads the most widely held theories to account for art, no on the basis of
our experience of its own traits, but by relating or identifying it with other
kinds of things more clearly understood and more easily designated. Just as anirnistic explanations of
physical events were used before the advent of modern science to account for the
new and strange by interpreting them, in the manner of human actions which were
more familiar, the phenomena of aesthetics have thus far been described in the
commonly recognized but nonaesthetic terms of imitation, emotion, language and
the like. Surrogate theories,
however, do an injustice to art by reducing aesthetic experience to
nonperceptual, literally nonaesthetic modes of experience, or to stereotyped and
limited kinds of experience. Perhaps because these theories are
discursive attempts to formulate the inherently nondiscursive experience of art,
they fail to take proper account of the peculiar feature’s of aesthetic
experience, translating it instead into other, more readily identifiable kinds
of experience which differ from the aesthetic.
Of course one may object that every
theory is an attempt to codify experience into recognizable types. Why, then, should aesthetic theory be
castigated merely for doing the same? The objection lies not with aesthetic
theorizing per se, but with the failure to apprehend the characteristic traits
of aesthetic experience by reducing it to alien modes. An account of aesthetic experience is a
separate task, and we must also make sufficiently clear the case for a
distinguishable kind of perceptual experience associated with art. And if only the identity of aesthetic
experience be granted, the force of the criticisms presented here is undeniable.
A mode of experience
distinguishable from other kinds can hardly be adequately represented by them.
17 That is why attempts to interpret art as
feeling,
17. I emphatically disclaim any
intention of subscribing to what L.A. Richards has termed ‘“the phantom
aesthetic state.” (Cf. his
Principles of Literary Criticism,
182
as emotion, as pleasure, or as form
do injury to the richness and inclusiveness of aesthetic experience when they
merely abstract a commonly recognized facet of experience and ascribe it to
art.
That is: why theories that interpret
art as mimesis, as a means of expression, as a language for communication, or as
a symbol are misrepresentations, for these all interpret the experience of art
as ultimately referential, as being like or about something other than
itself.
Toward a Theory of Aesthetic
Experience
Certainly I am not suggesting that
all efforts to theorize about aesthetics are cursed. Nor am I implying that, since aesthetic
experience is preanalytic, it cannot be inquired into. My criticisms are directed toward the
failure to theorize by treating aesthetic experience in the light of its own
distinctive characteristics rather than like radically different modes of
experience. I am proposing,
instead, that aesthetic theory become genuinely empirical, that it be guided not
by prior commitments or preconceptions from outside aesthetic experience but by
the intrinsic qualities of such experience, and that it study man’s aesthetic
experiences in their characteristic situations. One important consequence of this
approach to aesthetic theorizing is that we must reject those interpretations
that displace the distinctive experiences of art by reducing them to a mode of
experience different from the aesthetic. We must put aside theories of art with
animistic and biographical overtones, like expression and communication
theories. Finally, we must dispense
with all surrogates for aesthetic experience. While these may have some explanatory
value, they are solely metonymical and ought to be, replaced by a literal
account of aesthetic experience. Speaking analogically, what is needed is
the reformation in aesthetic theory that would be achieved by supplanting the
priesthood of the surrogate theories by the protestantism of direct communion
with experience that art is capable of furnishing.
It is not sufficiently recognized
that aesthetic theory is, literally speaking, meta-aesthetics. If the major importance of the
perceptual aspect of aesthetic experience were properly acknowledged (as is
suggested by the etymology of the term “aesthetics” - aisthesis, meaning
sense-perception), we should come to realize that aesthetic theory is talk about
a kind of experience which such talk itself is not. Yet this condition is not peculiar to
aesthetics. It is the case with the
natural and behavioral sciences, too only in linguistics, semantics, the
philosophy of logic, methodology and theory constrution is this not so. Perhaps the problem here arises out of
the attempt to render in concepts what is actually a recognizable type of
experience that is itself of quite a different order. Indeed, as I
suggest
183
elsewhere, a large share of the
difficulty lies in the fact that aesthetic experience is nonconceptual, and the
discursive nature of language is foreign to the nondiscursive nature of
art. Thus the failure to
distinguish clearly between aesthetic experience and the theory of aesthetic
experience has led recently to skepticism in some quarters about the very
possibility of aesthetics, since it may seem impossible to get at the nature of
art without ending up with a closed definition that cannot do justice to the
limitless variety of the experience of art. And it is not difficult to understand
also why the artist, by his
precognitive reliance on the totality of perceptual awareness, is drawn often to
express his experiences in the evocative language of the metaphysician or the
mystic.
The conclusion that may be drawn
regarding the ways in which art has been theorized about is that the study of
aesthetics has not proceeded beyond a preliminary stage. Aesthetic theory still, for the most
part, looks outside the experience of art to explain art. Most theories replace aesthetic
experience with a surrogate, and while doing this may serve to alleviate
puzzlement, they do this at the expense of accuracy. Yet it is the task of theory, in
aesthetics to provide a literal rather than a metaphorical account of aesthetic
experience. For a metaphorical
theory is a surrogate theory, and aesthetic theory with pretensions to
truthfulness must forego metaphor and deal with the experience and phenomena of
art in their own terms, that is, literally.
My intent here has been the
necessary preliminary of pointing up the importance of developing a rigorous
descriptive science of aesthetics based on a deliberate and careful examination
of aesthetic experience on its own terms. This is not to imply that the distinctive
characteristics and special values of aesthetic experience must be discounted or
will be lost. For it is the
theory of art which must develop into an empirical science and not art,
itself, or the experiences it evokes. What this does mean, however, is rather
that the opportunity here exists whereby we may achieve a fuller awareness of
the conditions under which aesthetic experience may take place, of the
significance of such experiences for human life, and of the role of art in human
culture and how it may most effectively serve its ends. But in pursuing the goal of an empirical
aesthetics, we must observe the dictum, adapt the theory to art, not art to the
theory. Only then will we be in a
position to enhance the totality of human experience by the explicit recognition
of the significance of its aesthetic aspect.
Undoubtedly this discussion leaves
many questions yet unanswered, including the implication of this thesis for a
great many problems in aesthetics, issues like the resemblance between aesthetic
experience in the creation and in the appreciation of art, the role of beliefs
in art, the
184
relationships of aesthetic
experience to other distinguishable kinds of experience, in particular the
practical, and the implications of the ideas developed here for the criticism of
art. Most important, however, is
the need to elaborate a theory of aesthetic experience which will embody the
critical results of the analysis we have just made and which will suggest a
resolution of such traditional and current problems in aesthetics indeed, many
of the criticisms voiced here presuppose a view of aesthetic experience rather
different from the way it is commonly described. A descriptive analysis of such experience
is therefore the task to which we should turn, and it is by doing this that
aesthetics can hope to progress toward a firmly grounded theory of
art.
185