The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
The Sensuous and the Sensual in
Aesthetics
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
23 (2
Winter 1964, 185-192.
Content |
AMONG ALL THE AREAS
of cultural activity, the arts have
occupied a position of considerable dependence during most of the course of the
development of Western civilization. Indeed, the claim of artistic expression
to the status of equal merit with the other manifestations of the human creative
genius is of comparatively recent occurrence and has rarely been freely allowed.
More commonly, the arts have been
tolerated as a means of enhancing those beliefs and values and their
institutional expressions which have dominated intellectual activity and which
were regarded as embodying unquestionable truth. So thoroughly has the belief in the
subordinate role of the arts pervaded Western thought, moreover, that during
recent times, when the arts have largely emancipated themselves from
subservience to the church, state, and social interests, concepts under which
much aesthetic discussion is conducted betray the extent to which aesthetic
theory still remains bound to biases deriving from the inferior origins of the
arts.
While the scope of critical inquiry
that can be made in these directions is vast, we shall confine our remarks here
to a traditional distinction which has become so deeply engrained in our
thinking about the arts that it has acquired the position of a largely
unquestioned postulate in most modern aesthetic theory. This is the distinction between the
sensuous and the sensual as employed in characterizations of aesthetic
experience and the objects which evoke it.
The sensuous is commonly regarded as connoting the pleasurable attraction
of the sensations of sight, hearing, and the other senses. The sensual, on the other hand, refers to
that experience of the senses which is confined to bodily pleasures as
contrasted with intellectual satisfaction, where appeal is to the “grosser”
bodily sensations, particularly the sexual. Discrimination between these notions is
commonly encountered in aesthetic theory and is maintained to be coterminous
with the bounds of art, the sensuous being reluctantly admitted into the
province of aesthetic experience and the sensual rejected.
While one hardly wonders at meeting
this distinction among aesthetic theorists with a commitment to a religious or
moral doctrine or to a spiritualistic metaphysic, it is more surprising to find
it accepted without serious question by writers on aesthetics whose naturalistic
or scientific bent might cause one to have expected otherwise.
1 Our object is to reveal how the restraining hand of the
moral censor, gloved in metaphysical doctrine, is still a powerful force in
aesthetic theory, an influence which exhibits itself in this commonly observed
distinction. Moreover, we shall
show that
ARNOLD BERLEANT is assistant
professor and acting chairman of the philosophy department at C. W. Post College
of Long Island University. He has written several articles and reviews for
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
185
such a discrimination has a distorting influence on aesthetic theory in general, eliminating a large area of experience from the possibility of aesthetic perception of which it is intrinsically capable.
Sense
Perception
Irrespective of theoretical
commitment, every treatment of aesthetic issues involves reference to human
experience. Independent of the
ontological status attributed to the art object, the relation of men to it, in
producing, appreciating, appraising it, is an experiential relation. That this is a perceptual experience
involving the various senses has long been acknowledged, explicitly so since the
formal establishment of the discipline by the very name given it. In choosing the Greek word aesthesis,
Baumgartner, in the eighteenth century, made clear the primary commitment of
the theory of art to sensation, to sense perception, and since that time
aestheticians have continued to acknowledge the importance of the sensuous
element in art. Among the
significant attempts to accord adequate recognition to this aspect of art is
Prall’s concept of aesthetic surface, by which he meant the sensuous surface of
experience. Indeed, he went so far
as to maintain that “Experience is genuinely and characteristically aesthetic
only as it occurs in transactions with external objects of sense or with the
objects of sensuous imagination held clearly before the mind in intuition…” and,
the sensuous elements of experience in general… are the very materials of
beauty... [T]hey are our first concern, the primary subject matter of aesthetic
theory.” 2
While we, like Prall, are not
suggesting that such other fundamental aspects of aesthetic experience as the
formal and the conceptual or significant are unimportant, they have perhaps been
overemphasized in recent discussion at the expense of the sensuous, possibly
because of their greater adaptability to discourse and explication. Although one can comment on the formal
characteristics of a musical work like Wozeck or a Mondrian canvas, or
advance another interpretation of Ulysses, one can hardly make someone
see the colors in a watercolor or an article of common use, feel
the texture of cloth or stone, or hear the sounds of a modern musical work
regarded as “offensive” by the prejudiced ear.
3
At the time of endless talk about
art, it would seem fitting to recall our attention to what is perhaps one of
art’s most characteristic features. For the distinctive quality of art is
neither harmony, 4 unity in variety, aesthetic form,
symbolic meaning, or the like, but rather what may be termed the intrinsic
perception of sensation, either directly, as in painting, music, and
sculpture, or indirectly, as in the case of the literary arts. For every perception is potentially
aesthetic. When intellectual,
moral, or emotional elements begin to obtrude, experience becomes less aesthetic
and more cognitive, homiletic, or affective. Furthermore, recognition of the
sensuousness of art emphasizes the particularity, the specificity of the
aesthetic experience. The negation
of aesthetic is, in every sense,
anaesthetic.
Aesthetic
Experience
In asserting the sensuousness of
aesthetic perception, it is appropriate to consider, if briefly, the role of the
senses in aesthetic experience. This is a topic which is usually given
but passing attention in most treatments of the questions of aesthetics. The classic opinion that the aesthetic
senses are the visual and the aural is dutifully echoed as a truth whose
obviousness renders justification superfluous, after which attention is turned
to seemingly more pressing matters. Yet this proposition is worth serious
examination, if for no other reasons than that the senses are a necessary
condition for most if not all aesthetic experience, and the bearing this has on
the roles of the sensuous and the sensual in aesthetic
perception.
The belief that sight and hearing
are the aesthetic senses occurs in Greek philosophy, receiving the endorsement
of Plato, Aristotle, and their later followers including Plotinus and Aquinas.
This is no isolated judgment,
however. Following the
rational
186
bent of the dominant tradition of
Greek thought, sight and hearing were regarded as the higher senses because they
were held to be the senses most closely related to the operations of reason.
5
This belief complements the classical attitude which
considers theoretical activity distinct from and superior to practical doing,
and concurs with the Platonic metaphysic which relegates the material, the
physical, to an inferior status, a belief which was reinforced during the
centuries that the Christian influence was dominant in aesthetic theory. Since the organs of sight and hearing are
distance receptors, detachment from direct contact with the physical may be
retained, for the other senses call attention to the body, so destroying the
isolation of the contemplative mind. Thus the aristocratic attitude of
classical Greek culture has been preserved: the conviction of the superiority of
the essentially passive aloofness of the meditative spirit and contempt for the
practical and manipulative. 6
Indeed, this division between the
distance receptors and the contact senses corresponds to the distinction between
the sensuous and the sensual. The
sensuous is admissable only when made safe by being perceived through the senses
of sight and hearing, while the senses of taste, smell, and especially touch,
are ineradicably suggestive of the sensual. In modern times, this view has obtained
considerable prominence in aesthetics through the notions of psychical distance
and disinterestedness. Thus, while
it is sometimes allowed that the aesthetic attitude be taken toward any object
of which we may be aware, 7
the enjoyment of some kinds of beauty
has usually been regarded as possible only through the intervention of distance.
8 Only when the sensual has been depersonalized, removed
from proximity, spiritualized, does it render itself aesthetically acceptable.
Love as beauty, for example, has
been held to demand the use of the principle of distance for its most complete
development and fulfillment. 9
And,
as might have been expected, transcending the physical presence entirely has
been taken as affording the greater beauty.
10
In such a way, aesthetic theory has
become subservient to the tenets of a metaphysical position whose truth may well
be questioned. Not only this. In addition to the a priori
rejection of the possibility of aesthetic perception as involving the other
senses, experience is distorted by categorizing it on the basis of the sense
through which it is obtained. This
is encountered in discussions in aesthetics which isolate the senses and
associate them with specific art media. And since there are no major art forms
corresponding to the senses of touch, taste, and smell, they are excluded from
any role in aesthetic perception.
Both views commit an identical
error. We are misled by thinking
that since the various senses have their seats in specific bodily organs and
areas, their signals are distinguishable on such grounds in actual perceptual
situations. The ability to
discriminate among the data of the various sense receptors results from
selective experience and reflection and is not a spontaneous recognition. On the contrary, it is most usual for
several or all of the senses to be involved in ordinary perception, although the
fact usually comes as a surprise when this widespread misconception is revealed
as such to an individual as a result of the impairment of one or another sense
organ. 11
In like
manner, characterizing art media on the basis of the sense through which they
are perceived, as in describing music as an aural art and painting as a visual
one, leads to gross distortion of aesthetic experience by making its major media
conform to the several senses. It
has been argued convincingly that sculpture, nominally a visual art, is not
primarily visual in appeal but tactile,
12 and the sense of touch is appealed to in much graphic
art, albeit indirectly, through the concern with texture, surface, and the like.
Music, perhaps, fits this theory
more easily than the other arts, but the experience of music is inseparable from
its performance, and this introduces the influence of the visual spectacle.
13 The case of the theatrical arts hardly supports the
theory of direct correspondence between major art and major sense, and the
literary arts are inexplicable in its terms.
There is another explanation for the
difficulty commonly alleged to exist in at-
188
taining an attitude of aesthetic
sensitivity toward sensory experiences involving those senses requiring contact
or close proximity for their employment. Activities involving these senses have
frequently been excluded as possible occasions for aesthetic experience because
of their failure to meet the criteria of aesthetic acceptability imposed by the
“higher” senses. One of the more
illustrative examples of this occurs in Plato’s Hippias Major. 14
In proposing pleasure as a definition of the beautiful,
Socrates restricts aesthetic pleasure to that received through the senses of
sight and hearing. Although it
cannot be denied that pleasure is to be found in taste, love, and the like,
these things may be termed pleasant, he argues, but hardly beautiful. “… [E]verybody would laugh at us if we
should say that eating is not pleasant but is beautiful, and that a pleasant
odour is not pleasant but is beautiful; and as to the act of sexual love, we
should all, no doubt, contend that it is most pleasant, but that one must, if he
perform it, do it so that no one else shall see, because it is most repulsive to
see.” 15
This is
scarcely a surprising conclusion, since the major sensory channel through which
love is experienced is not the visual but the tactile, not the distance but the
contact receptors. Were the touch
to be the standard for judging the aesthetic level of a pleasurable experience,
the visual enjoyment of an object, then, would hardly prove
passable.
Indeed, there is a powerful
aesthetic appeal which touch, smell, and taste possess, an appeal which resides
almost entirely in their immediate and direct sensuous attraction and not in
their potentialities for meaning and for structural organization. Perhaps this sensuous immediacy limits us
from developing art forms and techniques dependent largely on these senses that
are on a par with those appealing to sight and hearing which do possess these
potentialities, but such perceptual experience retains, nevertheless, a strong
aesthetic quality as sensuously perceived, which often plays a part in aesthetic
perception occurring mainly through the other senses.
It would seem that the most accurate
resolution of the issue may be obtained through the recognition of the
interrelated action of the senses and their connection with the total organism.
16 If we admit the
continuity of man with nature, the constant transaction between the human
organism and his natural surroundings, we are led to the conclusion that
separation between man and nature, discrimination between the sensory data of
the various receptors, between active involvement and passive contemplation,
between the material and the spiritual and their opposing values, and the like,
are products of a highly developed analysis which, in turn, is a consequence of
traditional metaphysical commitments which are not beyond challenge. Direct aesthetic experience, on the other
hand, is largely undifferentiated, and discussion of it must be made on its own
terms, and not as a consequence of non-aesthetic
convictions.
Moral Beliefs
Although metaphysical opinions play
a large part in the rejection of the sensual from aesthetic employment, moral
beliefs closely related to them are probably the major reason for this practice.
To the imposition of distance is
conjoined the rejection of the contact or lower senses, especially touch, as
vehicles of aesthetic enjoyment. Because touch and the other contact
senses are so closely associated with physical pleasure, particularly erotic
pleasure, their role in aesthetic experience is proscribed. This argument is not altogether
convincing, however, as soon as we recognize that art media involving the visual
and auditory senses have also been regarded capable of erotic influence and
consequently requiring moral controls. From the time of Plato to the present,
music, literature, and the other arts have been regarded with unabated suspicion
on precisely these grounds. For
while it has been claimed that the intervention of distance is capable of
allaying the suspicions of the censor and rendering his activities superfluous,
theater, dance, sculpture, and music are acknowledged to have a strong tendency
to decrease distance and hence would seem to justify the moralist’s concern.
17
189
For art, centering around the
intrinsically perceived qualities of sensory experience, turns men’s eyes not to
the glory of heaven but to the glories of the earth. And yet not only to its beauties. By intensifying our perceptual awareness,
art can bring home to us directly, as can perhaps no other medium, the
uglinesses, the meanness, the unbearables of life. Be it a conveyor of the sublime or the
sordid, artistic perception is a call to the world of natural existence of the
present, and hence, in this respect, is the least illusory of all our
experience. For nothing is as
undoubtedly real as the direct experience of the moment - the significant
insight of empirical subjectivism.
18
It is not the contention of the
moral critic of art that we are denying, but its aesthetic relevance. There is an erotic appeal present in
certain forms of artistic expression which is integral to the work and cannot be
expunged without impairing, if not destroying, its aesthetic merit. This is especially true of art employing
the human figure, particularly the nude.
19 Yet the presence of powerful
sensual appeal is hardly surprising, for probably no object is infused with such
emotional meaning as the human body, and this is transferred with no effort to
representations of and allusions to it. This does much to explain the perennial
attraction the human form possesses for the artist, for, from neolithic cave
painting to the art of the present, objects and matters of human interest have
occupied the creative artist, and nothing has obsessed him more than the
unquenchable appeal of the human figure. 20
Not only does the form of the body
have aesthetically sensuous attraction; the function of its members does as
well. Is there not a beauty in the
free and graceful movement of the body, a beauty which is perhaps bound up with
its form? Such an appeal exists in
the chance observations of daily life in addition to the art forms such as the
dance and pantomime which take bodily movement for their materials. Here, as in architecture and design, lies
the basis for challenging the religiously repeated exclusion of objects and
activities of mainly practical significance from aesthetic enjoyment. Dewey’s query is highly
appropriate:
Why is the attempt to connect the higher and ideal things of experience with basic vital roots so often regarded as betrayal of their nature and denial of their value? Why is there repulsion when the high achievements of fine art are brought into connection with common life, the life that we share with all living creatures? Why is life thought of as an affair of low appetite, or at its best a thing of gross sensation, and ready to sink from its best to the level of lust and harsh cruelty? A complete answer to the question would involve the writing of a history of morals that would set forth the conditions that have brought about contempt for the body, fear of the senses, and the opposition of flesh to spirit. 21
Sensuous and Sensual
What then, can we conclude about the
significance for aesthetics of the distinction between the sensuous and the
sensual? Largely that it is not a
tenable one. The differentiation
resembles those other dichotomies that have had the intent of safeguarding the
interests, the cherished domain of an institution or a tradition. The traditional view in this instance
sees aesthetic pleasure not as physical pleasure but completely dissociated from
it, and while the role of the senses must be acknowledged, it is a role enacted
on a spiritualized plane, disembodied, “de-physicalized,” as it were. Yet by admitting the sensuous in the form
of art to acceptable enjoyment, the time-honored mind-body dualism of which this
distinction is the aesthetic manifestation destroys itself.
22 For the sensual enters with the sensuous, and in a vast
area of aesthetic creation and experience the sensual becomes a major if not
predominant feature of its sensuous appeal. Indeed, the two are often
indistinguishable.
If we regard the sensual as
continuous with the aesthetic, numerous problems in aesthetic theory move closer
to clarification and resolution, issues such as the significance of the nude in
art, psychological theorizing about the relation of the artist to sexuality, and
especially the place of the tactile and other contact senses in aesthetic
experience. For the tactile urge,
undeveloped and unencouraged as it is, reveals itself surreptitiously (as may be
observed at any sculpture exhibit), and becomes a fissure in the rock of
aesthetic respectability. And by
thus acknowledging the physical
190
more openly and involving it more
squarely in aesthetic experience, it becomes possible to explain differences of
response to the same aesthetic stimuli through differences in physical states of
receptivity and sensitivity.
What this interpretation suggests,
then, is that aesthetic experience at its fullest and richest is experience by
the whole man; the entire person is now involved in the aesthetic event. And instead of making aesthetic
experience a “spiritual” communion of “kindred souls,” effete and insubstantial,
we have indicated how it may be revitalized by being brought into the world of
natural events, universal in its inclusiveness - experience perhaps more
fundamental, vital, and intrinsically significant than any
other.
1. Santayana, for example, distinguishes between physical
and aesthetic pleasures. The former
are lowly and call attention to the part of the body in which they arise, while
in the latter the bodily organs do not capture our attention but direct it to an
external object. Cf. The Sense
of Beauty (New York, 1896), pp. 36-37. Dewey makes the distinction on similar
grounds: “Any sensuous quality tends, because of its organic connections, to
spread and fuse. When a sense
quality remains on the relatively isolated plane on which it first emerges, it
does so because of some special reaction, because it is cultivated for special
reasons. It ceases to be sensuous
and becomes sensual. This isolation
of sense is not characteristic of esthetic objects, but of such things as
narcotics, sexual orgasms, and gambling indulged in for the sake of the
immediate excitement of sensation. In normal experience, a sensory quality
is related to other qualities in such ways as to define an object.” Art as
Experience (New York, 1934), p. 124.
2. D. W. Prall, Aesthetic Judgment
(New York, 1929), pp. 28, 56. Peirce’s metaphysical category of
firstness, by which he meant immediacy, feeling, quality, suchness, corresponds
to this feature of the aesthetic experience. Recently his three categories have been
adapted to a theory of art. Cf.
Albert William Levi, “Peirce and Painting,” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, XXIII, 1 (1962), 23-36.
3. The neglect of the aesthetic
appeal of art by the intellectualistic absorption in organization and meaning
has occasionally been remarked upon. Hanslick was well aware of this in the
case of music: “The reason why people have failed to discover the beauties in
which pure music abounds, is, in great measure, to be found in the
underrating, by the older systems of aesthetics, of the sensuous
element, and in its subordination to morality and feeling – in Hegel to the
‘idea.’ Every art sets out from the
sensuous and operates within its limits. The theory relating to the expression of
feelings ignores this fact, and disdainfully pushing aside the act of
hearing, it passes on immediately to the feelings. Music, say they, is food for the
soul, and the organ of hearing is beneath their notice.” Eduard Hanslick, The
Beautiful in Music, in Problems in Aesthetics, ed. M. Weitz (New
York, 1959), p. 383.
The perceptive critic has not been
the only one to remark upon the primacy of the aesthetic in art. While poetry is sensuous in its effect
mainly indirectly through its ability to stimulate imaginative recollection, the
poet, too, has engaged in similar observations: “Art bids us touch and taste and hear and
see the world, and shrinks from what Blake calls mathematic form, from every
abstract thing, from all that is the brain only, from all that is not a fountain
jetting from the entire hopes, memories and sensations of the body. Its morality is personal, knows little of
any general law…” William
4. Although its meaning has been
modified periodically, the philosophy of art has regarded harmony historically
as the goal of artistic struggling and identical with beauty. Cf. K. E. Gilbert and H. Kuhn, A
History of Esthetics, rev. ed. (Bloomington, Ind., 1954), pp. 186
ff.
5. lbid., pp. 117,
139.
6. Cf. the brief but excellent
discussion of some of these questions in Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and
Philosophy of Art Criticism (
7. lbid.,pp.
39ff.
8. “That the appeal of Art is sensuous, even sensual, must be taken as an indisputable fact. Puritanism will never be persuaded, and rightly so, that this is not the case... [T]he whole sensual side of art is purified, spiritualized, ‘filtered’… by Distance. The most sensual appeal becomes the translucent veil of an underlying spirituality, once the grossly personal and practical elements have been removed from it. And - a matter of special emphasis here - this spiritual aspect of the appeal is the more penetrating, the more personal and direct its sensual appeal would have been BUT FOR THE PRESENCE OF DISTANCE.” Edward Bullough, “‘Psychical Distance’ as a Factor in Art and an Esthetic Principle,” in A Modern Book of Esthetics, ed. M. Rader, 3d ed. (1960), p. 410.
9. “This limitation and restriction of
amatory intercourse is demanded by the aesthetic rule of distance. In the long run the petty incidentals of
physical presence menace the beauty of the visionary image that I have created
of the human being I love. Insofar
as beauty is of decisive significance in my love relationship - since, according
to my understanding and interpretation, it is only thus that the primitive forms
of sensuality acquire a
190
content of infinite meaning - the
destruction and obfuscation of the image created by the desire for beauty will
cause the strength of love itself to wane and gradually disappear. For a short period, to be sure, the love
object may be given to the lover, to touch and blissfully embrace, without any
danger to the beauty of the love relationship. After all, the full sense of love
includes a demand for the development of sensual desire. Even in a love formed on the basis of
aesthetic values sensual desire must be accorded its due. It cannot be a question of mere
beholding, of the kind of disinterested pleasure with which we meet dead works
of art, and those living works of art that are and remain created forms for my
artistic enthusiasm; for in the love relationship, a coming together and a
fusion, with heavenly moments of passing intoxication, is of the essence; but
the observance of the law of distance will reveal itself in the courage of
leave-taking, in the consciously willed separation from the object of my
love.
“Certainly, love is destined to die
insofar as it is interwoven with the temporal fate of the senses. It has its moment of fulfillment in the
most beautiful surrender and the attained understanding of the lovers, and then
must necessarily wane in consequence of sickness, age, misunderstanding, and
death. Nevertheless, the law of
distance is able to counter certain dangers that threaten this beautiful
relationship, and protect it from tiring and cooling off. For this, too, a certain keeping of
distance, a concealment of emotional qualities from the object of love is
required. The great value relations
in life, love and friendship, should never be quite clear and transparent as we
live them. We should spread over
them the beautiful veil of illusion, and they should always hold a last residue
of insolubility for us.” Georg
Mehlis, “The Aesthetic Problem of Distance,” in Reflections on Art, ed.
S. Langer (Baltimore, Johns Hopkins Press, 1958), pp. 84-85.
10.
“The pleasure of the present may be greater
than the enjoyment of the past and the future; but the appearance of the unreal,
of that which was or is to come, is more beautiful, because here the obstructive
and weakening elements of embodiment have been replaced and enhanced by
felicitous allusions and connections. Thus beauty gains by the distance of
expectation, just as it gains by the distance of the past.” To this, a fitting conclusion: “If, then,
love itself has an aesthetic character, the feeling of love must also be
controlled by the law of distance. Those who love only the beautiful, whose
affections are destroyed by ugliness and bad taste, should be ever reminded of
the law of distance; for profane proximity destroys the bliss of pure aloofness,
as ugly frequency and intimacy annihilate the enjoyment of the rare and
unknown.” Ibid., pp.
87-88.
11.
“ -. [M]any sense data apprehended as
sight and sound are actually complex in origin, having been built by the
combined action of eyes, ears and hands… In experience our sense organs are
seldom exercised separately but are simultaneously engaged in exploring objects
which appeal to several senses at once. After the interrelations of the various
qualities of experience have been learned… we can then get the complex of these
qualities indirectly through the mediation of any one of the senses
involved.” Frances W. Herring,
“Touch the Neglected Sense,” JAAC, VII (1949), 210. Cf. also pp. 200-201,
203.
12.
Cf., for example, Herring, pp.
206-207.
13. Stravinsky’s comment is worth
citing: “... one sees music. An experienced eye follows, adjudges,
sometimes unconsciously, the performer’s least gesture.” Quoted in Ernest Bacon, Words on Music
(
14. The question of this dialogue’s
authenticity is irrelevant to the point here being made.
15.
Hippias Major, trans. Fowler,
299A.
16. Cf. the discussion by
Dewey in Art as Experience, pp. 121 ff.
17. Cf. Bullough, pp.
402-403.
18. Cf. Irwin Edman, Arts and the
Man (New York, 1949), pp. 39 ff. Here, too, lies the utility of distance
for him who would pare art of any appeal to vital interests of all sorts: “...
{E]xplicit references to organic affections, to the material existence of the
body, especially to sexual matters, lie normally below the Distance-limit, and
can be touched upon by Art only with special precautions. Allusions to social institutions of any
degree of personal importance - in particular, allusions implying any doubt as
to their validity - the questioning of some generally recognized ethical
sanctions, references to topical subjects occupying public attention at the
moment, and such like, are all dangerously near the average limit and may at any
time fall below it, arousing, instead of esthetic appreciation, concrete
hostility or mere amusement.” Bullough, p. 400.
19.
“… [T]he human body, as a nucleus, is rich
in associations, and when it is turned into art these associations are not
entirely lost.... This is an aspect of the subject so obvious that I need hardly
dwell on it; and yet some wise men have tried to close their eyes to it. ‘If the nude,’ says Professor Alexander,
‘is so treated that it raises in the spectator ideas or desires appropriate to
the material subject, it is false art, and bad morals.’ This high-minded theory is contrary to
experience. In the mixture of
memories and sensations aroused by Rubens’ Andromeda or Renoir’s
Bather are many that are ‘appropriate to the material subject.’ And since these words of a famous
philosopher are often quoted it is necessary to labor the obvious and say that
no nude, however abstract, should fail to arouse in the spectator some vestige
of erotic feeling, even though it be only the faintest shadow - and if it does
not do so, it is bad art and false morals. The desire to grasp and be united with
another human body is so fundamental a part of our nature that our judgment of
what is known as ‘pure form’ is inevitably influenced by it; and one of the
difficulties of the nude as a subject for art is that these instincts cannot lie
hidden, as they do, for example, in our enjoyment of a piece of pottery, thereby
gaining the force of sublimation, but are dragged into the foreground, where
they risk upsetting the unity of responses from which a work of art derived its
independent life. Even so, the
amount
191
of erotic content a work of art can
hold in solution is very high. The
temple sculptures of tenth-century
“Apart from biological needs, there
are other branches of human experiences of which the naked body provides a vivid
reminder - harmony, energy, ecstasy, humility, pathos; and when we see the
beautiful results of such embodiments, it must seem as if the nude as a means of
expression is of universal and external value. But this we know historically to be
untrue.” Kenneth Clark, The
Nude, (New York, Bollingen Foundation, 1953), pp. 28-29; quoted by
permission of the Bollingen Foundation. Cf. also Herring, p.
208.
30. [T]he body provides an
inexhaustible source for a vocabulary of expressive forms, a vocabulary that is
continually being enriched. Whether
we consider the immense sensuous appeal of the living body, the equally powerful
ascetic revulsion from it as loathsome, or any of the host of intermediate
experiences, we are compelled … to reckon with the response to the body as an
integral and ineradicable component of artistic and aesthetic experience.” Matthew Lipman, “The Aesthetic Presence
of the Body,” JAAC, XV (1957), p. 434. Cf. also p.
428.
31. Dewey, p. 20. Cf. also Chap. II
in its entirety.
32. “The moralist knows that sense is allied
with emotion, impulse and appetition. So he denounces the lust of the eye as
part of the surrender of spirit to flesh. He identifies the sensuous with the
sensual and the sensual with the lewd. His moral theory is askew, but at least
he is aware that the eye is not an imperfect telescope designed for intellectual
reception of material to bring about knowledge of distant objects.” Dewey, p. 21.
192