The Competitiveness of Nations in a Global Knowledge-Based Economy
A Note on the Problem on Defining ‘Art’
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 25 (2
Dec. 1964, 239-241
Recent attempts at explicating the essential
character of art [1] have
given rise to discussions concerning the significance of this question for
aesthetic theory and to skepticism in some quarters about the very possibility
of defining ‘art’. While this issues
raises numerous difficulties, not the least of these revolves around the
nature of the concept ‘art’ itself. Some
(Weitz and Morgan, following Wittgenstein) term it an “open” concept, since
its boundaries, by the very nature of an empirical concept, cannot be finally
drawn. Others (Kahier) object to this
manner of definition, maintaining, instead, that an empirical concept must be
defined from its central feature, and that while this feature may be made
clear, there will always occur borderline instances that are ambiguous.
Still others (Beardsley, Pepper) have
attempted to demarcate the aesthetic field so as to arrive at dependable
aesthetic criteria.
It might be helpful in dealing with the problem
of defining ‘art’ to look at the concept once more, going, as it were, not
from a proposed definition (be it by boundaries or central notion) outward to
the phenomena which it may be considered to denote, but from those phenomena
commonly considered to exemplify art and from the experiences by which they
are known and for which they are sought, inward to the concept.
If we were to do this, that is, if we
were to approach the problem of concepts, not as hypostatizations, each
possessing its distinctive essence or its precise limits, but as conceptual
constructs formed by people for the purpose of effectively dealing with their
multitudinous similar and diverse experiences, we would come to realize that,
apart from formal notions amenable to rigid delimitation, the search for a
completely demarcated concept, unequivocal in its denotation, is an ignis
fatuus, as impossible to attain as it is undesirable to possess.
For concepts are
[1]
Cf. Symposium in Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, XX, 2 (Winter,
1961), 175-198
(Beardsley, Morgan, and Mothersill), and Pepper’s comment, “Evaluative
Definitions in Art and Their Sanctions,” ibid., XXI, 2 (Winter, 1962),
201-208. Also Morris Weitz, “The Role
of Theory in Aesthetics,” ibid., XV, 1 (September,
1956), 27-35.
Reprinted in Weitz’s
Problems in Aesthetics (New York,
1959), pp.
145-156, along with a
reply by Erich Kahler, “What is Art?,” pp.
157-171.
239
employed and acquire their importance in the
ordering of experience previously undifferentiated or indistinct, and the
concept ‘art’ functions in the ordering of the experience of art and the
objects which give rise to such experience. If
we deal primarily empirically with experiences and not rationalistically with
concepts, it takes little insight to recognize that the concept will be
dependent upon the experiences from which it obtains its meaning and to which
it refers. Consequently, it will vary
in its connotation to the extent that the experiences vary; that is, it will
be relative to the experiencer and will embody whatever constancy and
variability lie in such experiences. Here
is an instance in which the genetic account of the functional origin of
concepts provides a healthier influence and a more satisfactory explanation
than does abstract analysis, by redirecting our consideration back to
essentials. Thus it can be seen that
the use of the same term is no guarantee of identity of connotation or
denotation. Rather, it reveals the
poverty of language in attempting communication of a rich variety of
experiences with a paucity of verbal means. And
no mode of experience surpasses the richness and variety of the aesthetic.
Such an interpretation as this requires a review
of our thinking about our conceptual tools. It
demands a forthright repudiation of the Platonic-Aristotelian inheritance of
completed concepts or ideas, each possessing its own essence.
Indeed, it observes that any
discussion of concepts, independently of or in isolation from our experiences,
individual and social, is destined to be empty dialectics, perhaps absorbing
as a kind of mental acrobatics, but ineffectual or even debilitating for the
purpose of sharing experiences. Thus
the skepticism of many toward the question of the definition of ‘art’ is a
fitting conclusion to a disjoined inquiry. Let
us better admit of a plurality of meanings to encompass a plurality of
experiences, having perhaps some things in common (these being expressed in
the conventional connotations of terms), but shading off imperceptibly into
experiences inadmissible to some and eventually inadmissible to all.
A language of experience is far more
appropriate in dealing with experiences than is a language of things.
The sooner we repudiate the
rationalistic conception of a world of finished objects and turn to that one
in which we live and act, the more effectively shall we be able to adapt our
thinking and expressing to our experiencing.
The touchstone of all art is thus seen to be the aesthetic experience and not a definition. Clearly, the experience of art is prior to its definition. If an object succeeds in evoking an aesthetic experience, it, then, in that instance, becomes an aesthetic object. The problem, consequently, resolves into the description and clarification of the experience of art. Similarly, the assertion that “evaluations occur by way of definitions” [
2]
[2]
Pepper, op. cit., 203.
240
raises the question of whether a definition must
be a prerequisite for evaluation or whether evaluation follows from the
experience of art and then becomes formulated in a justificatory definition.
The latter, if it were the case, would
not necessarily mean subjectivism in evaluating art.
It does insist, however, that art is
never art by definition. A rule, in
this case a definition, never made a painting or a piece of music beautiful.
It is the intellectual, who strives for cognitive apprehension of what
he has undergone in an art gallery or concert hail, who seeks to understand,
to codify, to systematize and regularize, who may inadvertently discover
himself upholding the contrary. Nor is
there anything amiss in his cognitive activities, so long as the priority of
experience to definition be acknowledged and deferred to.
241